1 Introduction

A rich source of material for philosophical theorizing concerns the nature of our mental states. A prominent research program in this area tries to shed light on the character of these states by providing a logical, or semantical, account of their expression in natural language. This program focuses on describing the meaning, or truth-conditions, of so-called “propositional attitude reports”. In particular, there has recently been a considerable amount of work on desire ascriptions, for example reports of the form \(\ulcorner \)S wants/hopes/wishes p\(\urcorner \).Footnote 1 In this paper, I aim to contribute to this logico-semantic research agenda in two ways.

My first goal is to draw attention to a closely related, but underdiscussed construction, namely comparative preference claims: sentences of the form \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \).Footnote 2 I show that preference claims exhibit interesting properties, and try to develop an account that captures them. The key idea behind my theory is that preference is alternative-sensitive. This means that the objects relevant for the evaluation of preference claims are certain propositions, called alternatives; and whether p is preferred to q doesn’t just depend on the content of p and q alone, but also on which alternatives are relevant in context.

My second goal is to investigate whether my semantics for preference can help to provide an account of desire. I take inspiration from a fairly long tradition in philosophy that assumes there is a deep connection between preference and desire.Footnote 3 I develop this idea in a novel direction by proposing that the preference-desire connection is reflected in the object language itself. That is, I explore the idea that a desire report \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) means virtually the same as the preference claim \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to \(\lnot \)p\(\urcorner \). The resulting account of desire is elegant and independently motivated. It also allows us to explain a wide range of phenomena.

The paper is structured as follows. In Sect. 2 I present a semantics for preference claims, and outline some of its most interesting features. Then in Sect. 3 I use my account of preference to provide a semantics for desire reports. Finally, Sect. 4 raises and responds to some concerns for my approach to preference and desire.

2 Preference

In this section, I put forward my account of preference claims. First, I present some observations that any adequate theory should be able to explain (Sect. 2.1). Then I consider, and reject, some accounts of preference adapted from the existing literature on desire (Sect. 2.2). Finally, I develop my positive proposal, and discuss some important features of this semantics (Sect. 2.3).

2.1 Some observations about preference

Our first set of observations involves closure under entailment. If preference claims were upward monotonic in their first argument, then the following would hold:Footnote 4

Upwardness 1

If \(p \models q\), then \(\textit{S prefers p to r} \models \textit{S prefers q to r}\)

But our first observation is that Upwardness 1 fails. For instance, none of the (ii) examples below follow from the (i) examples:

figure a

You preferring prawns to chicken doesn’t mean that you prefer any type of seafood to chicken, e.g. you might well like lobster much less than chicken. Similarly, although preferring winning $100 to winning $50 is rational, (1b-ii) suggests that you prefer losing $100 to winning $50, which isn’t. Finally, for (1c) imagine that when Ann and Carol are together at a party they’re funny, charming and tell great stories. But if one attends without the other, the person attending always ends up being a real bore, and inevitably makes the party worse for everyone else. Then although (1c-i) will be true, (1c-ii) won’t be since Ann’s attending leaves open that she attends without Carol, and you certainly wouldn’t like that.

Similar patterns are exhibited by the second argument of preference claims. If preference claims were upward monotonic in their second argument, then the following would hold:

Upwardness 2

If \(r \models s\), then \(\textit{S prefers p to r} \models \textit{S prefers p to s}\)

But Upwardness 2 also fails. For example, none of the (ii) examples below follow from the (i) examples:

figure b

You preferring chicken to lobster doesn’t mean that you prefer chicken to any type of seafood, e.g. you might well like prawns much more than chicken. Similarly, although preferring winning $100 to winning $50 is rational, (2b-ii) suggests that you prefer winning $100 to winning $1000, which isn’t. As for (2c) suppose that when Ann attends a party alone (i.e. without Carol) she’s funny, charming and tells great stories. But if she and Carol attend together, they always end up being a real bore, and inevitably make the party worse for everyone else. Then although (2c-i) will be true, (2c-ii) won’t be since Ann’s attending leaves open that she attends without Carol, and you’d prefer this to neither attending.

Our second cluster of observations concerns downward monotonicity. If preference claims were downward monotonic in their first argument, then the following would hold:

Downwardness 1

If \(p \models q\), then \(\textit{S prefers q to r} \models \textit{S prefers p to r}\)

We observe that Downwardness 1 has something of a mixed status: a fairly wide range of phenomena provide support for the principle, but there are also cases which suggest that Downwardness 1 cannot be unrestrictedly valid.

On the one hand, the (ii) examples below can be legitimately inferred from the (i) examples:

figure c

Moreover, conjoining the (i) examples in (3) with the negation of the (ii) examples leads to infelicity. For instance, both (4a) and (4b) are unacceptable (as indicated by the ‘#’ preceding each example):

figure d

This is exactly what we would expect if Downwardness 1 was valid, and the (i) examples entailed the (ii) examples.

Further support for Downwardness 1 comes from the fact that if p and q are related by entailment, then \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is unacceptable. For instance, (5) is infelicitous:

figure e

Downwardness 1 provides us with a neat explanation of why this should be. If (5) was true, then by Downwardness 1 ‘You prefer getting prawns to getting prawns’ would be true as well. But we can assume that nothing can be preferred to itself. So, (5) must be false.

On the other hand, Downwardness 1 cannot be unrestrictedly valid. For instance, (6b) does not follow from (6a):

figure f

You preferring seafood to chicken doesn’t mean that you prefer seafood along with an arbitrarily bad outcome, for example having your house burn down, to chicken. But You get seafood and your house burns down obviously entails You get seafood.

The same patterns are exhibited by the second argument of preference claims. The relevant principle here is Downwardness 2:

Downwardness 2

If \(r \models s\), then \(\textit{S prefers p to s} \models \textit{S prefers p to r}\)

Once again, a wide range of phenomena provide support for Downwardness 2, but there are also cases which suggest that it cannot be unrestrictedly valid.

On the one hand, the (ii) examples below seem to follow from the (i) examples:

figure g

Also, Downwardness 2 provides a neat explanation for why the examples in (8) are unacceptable:

figure h

If (7a-i) entails (7a-ii), then (8a) cannot be true. And if Downwardness 2 holds, then (8b) entails ‘You prefer getting prawns to getting prawns’, but presumably the latter cannot be true.

On the other hand, (9a) does not entail (9b):

figure i

You preferring chicken to seafood doesn’t mean that you prefer chicken to seafood along with an arbitrarily good outcome, for example winning one million dollars. But You get seafood and you win one million dollars obviously entails You get seafood.

At this point, it is worth pausing to address some concerns raised by a reviewer involving the contention that preference claims are (restrictedly) downward monotonic in both their arguments. First, the reviewer argues that if the arguments of preference claims are downward monotone, then they should license weak negative polarity items (NPIs) such as ‘any’ and ‘ever’. However, the reviewer observes that although the second argument seems to license these expressions, NPIs sound degraded when they appear in the first argument:

figure j

In response, it is worth pointing out that there is a healthy debate about the correctness of monotonicity-based approaches to NPI licensing, and alternative licensing conditions have been developed.Footnote 5 So, the existence of a straightforward connection between downward monotonicity and NPI licensing shouldn’t necessarily be taken for granted. Moreover, even those who tie NPI licensing to monotonicity tend not to take downward monotonicity as sufficient for NPI licensing. Rather, they only take it to be a necessary condition.Footnote 6 Indeed, there are well-known counterexamples to sufficiency. For example, the restrictor arguments of the quantifiers ‘each’, ‘both’ and ‘the’ are all standardly taken to be (restrictedly) downward monotonic environments,Footnote 7 but these positions fail to license NPIs:

figure k

So, although it is worth investigating why the second argument of preference reports more readily accepts NPIs than the first argument, this doesn’t undermine the claim that both positions are restrictedly downward monotone.

Second, the reviewer suggests that some of the data I have canvassed in support of downward monotonicity could be explained by other means. In particular, they point out that disjunctions inside the scope of certain modal expressions are independently known to have a distributive effect. For instance, consider the so-called “free choice” phenomenon that arises when disjunctions are embedded inside possibility modals, e.g. epistemic ‘might’:

figure l

An utterance of (12a) implies (12b), i.e. (12a) suggests both that your winning a car is epistemically possible, and that your winning a caravan is epistemically possible.Footnote 8 The idea is that whatever mechanism is responsible for the distribution effect in (12a) is also responsible for this effect in examples such as (3b-ii) (‘You prefer winning a car or a boat to winning a caravan’).

I am sympathetic to the thought that disjunction has special properties. But I will leave it to others to try to use non-Boolean analyses of disjunction in order to explain examples such as (3b-ii).Footnote 9 This is because a response that simply appeals to the special properties of disjunction won’t provide us with a complete account of our observations. As we have seen above, the data motivating downward monotonicity for preference go beyond cases which feature explicit disjunction, e.g. the inference from (3b-i) (‘You prefer seafood to chicken’) to (3b-ii) (‘You prefer prawns to chicken’).Footnote 10 Here are some further examples:

figure m

These inferences seems robust. But neither (13a) nor (14a) involves disjunction, and so presumably these inferences can’t arise from a free choice effect. Indeed, note that the corresponding inferences with ‘might’ are much less good:

figure n

To summarize our observations: although preference claims aren’t unrestrictedly downward monotonic, downward monotonicity has a positive status not shared by upward monotonicity. This requires explanation, and the remainder of this section tries to satisfy this demand. I present my preferred account in Sect. 2.3. But before we get there, in the next subsection I consider two analyses of preference adapted from dominant theories of desire reports. These entries aren’t able to capture our observations, but their failures will be instructive.

2.2 Two attempts at a semantics for prefer

As mentioned in Sect. 1, preference claims have been given little attention in the literature on desire. But it might be thought that existing accounts of desire could be adapted to provide an analysis of preference. The extant literature is dominated by two sorts of accounts: (i) theories that analyze desire in terms of a subjective ordering over possible worlds (von Fintel , 1999; Rubinstein , 2012; Crnič , 2011); and (ii) decision-theoretic analyses that tie the desirability of a proposition to its expected value (Levinson , 2003; Lassiter , 2011; Phillips-Brown , 2021). I briefly consider natural extensions of these accounts to preference below.

2.2.1 Best worlds accounts

Best worlds analyses of desire involve two main elements: (i) a domain of worlds, or modal base \({\mathcal {B}}\), and (ii) a subjective ordering \(>_{S, w}\) over the worlds in \({\mathcal {B}}\).Footnote 11 The idea is that \(w' >_{S, w} w''\) when \(w'\) is more desirable to S (in w) than \(w''\).Footnote 12\(>_{S, w}\) is taken to be a strict partial order. The desirability of a proposition is usually measured by considering the top-ranked worlds in \({\mathcal {B}}\), as ordered by \(>_{S, w}\) (von Fintel , 1999). Since a preference claim \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) involves a comparison between p and q, simply considering the top-ranked worlds in \({\mathcal {B}}\) won’t be very helpful. For instance, even if all the top-ranked worlds are \(\lnot p \wedge \lnot q\)-worlds, \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) can still be true. One idea is that instead of considering the top-ranked worlds tout court, we should compare the top-ranked p-worlds to the top-ranked q-worlds. To make this a bit more precise, let us introduce a function \(\textsc {best}(\cdot )\) that takes a proposition p and yields the set of top-ranked p-worlds in \({\mathcal {B}}\), as ordered by \(>_{S, w}\).Footnote 13 Then the entry for ‘prefer’ is as follows:Footnote 14

Best worlds semantics for prefer

\(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is true relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {B}} \rangle \) iff for all \(w' \in \textsc {best}(p)\), and for all \(w'' \in \textsc {best}(q)\): \(w' >_{w, S} w''\)

In short, \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is true just in case every top-ranked p-world is preferred to any top-ranked q-world.

I have a general worry with this semantics, and also some more specific concerns relating to our observations in Sect. 2.1. The broad worry can be brought out by considering the following example adapted from Levinson (2003):

Insurance: Sue is deciding whether to take out house insurance. She estimates that the chances of her house burning down are \(\frac{1}{1000}\). But the results would be calamitous: she’d lose her home which is valued at \(\$1,000,000\). Comprehensive home insurance would cost her \(\$100\). Sue has a meeting with her insurance broker this afternoon, so she needs to decide what she would like to do.

figure o

If Sue is like most of us, (17) is true: even though she thinks it’s likely that her house won’t burn down, there is a small possibility that it does, and the badness of this possibility outweighs the cost of buying insurance. But the best worlds semantics seems to predict that (17) should be false: the best worlds in which Sue buys insurance are not better than the best worlds in which she doesn’t buy insurance, since Sue most prefers worlds where she spends no money on insurance (and there’s no fire). Examples such as (17) suggest that the relevant preference calculation shouldn’t be done at the level of individual worlds, but rather at a coarser grain, e.g. at the level of whole propositions.

The best worlds semantics also fails to capture our observations from Sect. 2.1. For one thing, although it doesn’t make preference claims fully upward monotonic, it still makes problematic predictions. Suppose that \({\mathcal {B}}\) consists of three worlds: \(w_{\textsc {c}}, w_{\textsc {p}}, w_{\textsc {l}}\), where \(w_{\textsc {c}}\) is the world where you get chicken, \(w_{\textsc {p}}\) is the world where you get prawns, and \(w_{\textsc {l}}\) is the world where you get lobster. Suppose that you love prawns, find chicken to be average, and hate lobster because you’re allergic to it. Then your ranking of these worlds looks as follows:

\(w_{\textsc {p}}>_{\text {You}} w_{\textsc {c}} >_{\text {You}} w_{\textsc {l}}\)

Then (3a-ii) (‘You prefer prawns to chicken’) is predicted to be true, since \(w_{\textsc {p}} >_{\text {You}} w_{\textsc {c}}\). But (3a-i) (‘You prefer seafood to chicken’) is also predicted to be true, since best(You get prawns) = best(You get seafood) = \(w_{\textsc {p}}\). But intuitively (3a-i) is not true in this context.

The best worlds semantics also renders Downwardness 1 and Downwardness 2 straightforwardly invalid, and fails to explain why these principles appear to have a positive status. For instance, although (3a-i) is true in the scenario sketched above, ‘You prefer lobster to chicken’ is false. Moreover, it allows \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) to be true even when p and q are related by entailment. For example, ‘You prefer getting seafood to getting lobster’ is predicted to be true in context.Footnote 15

2.2.2 Decision-theoretic accounts

Now let us turn to the decision-theoretic approach to desire. On this proposal, the desirability of a proposition for a subject S is tied to the expected value of this proposition for S (Levinson , 2003). The expected value of p for S is the utility of p for S weighted by S’s subjective probabilities (Jeffrey , 1965). Given this framework, a natural thought is that S prefers p to q when the expected value of the former is greater than the expected value of the latter:Footnote 16\(^{,}\)Footnote 17

Decision-theoretic semantics for prefer

\(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is true in w iff \(EV_{w,S}(p) > EV_{w,S}(q)\)

This account renders both Upwardness 1 and Upwardness 2 invalid. But it fails to explain the rest of our observations from Sect. 2.1. For instance, it allows \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) to be true even when p and q are related by entailment. Suppose once again that you will be given lobster, prawns or chicken. You really like prawns, you think chicken is average, and you hate lobster. Then we can assign utilities to these outcomes so that (8b) (‘You prefer getting prawns to getting seafood’) is predicted to be true. For instance, suppose your credences/utilities are as follows:

figure p

A routine exercise confirms that \(EV_{\text {You}}(\textit{You get prawns}) > EV_{\text {You}}(\textit{You get prawns or} \textit{lobster}) = EV_{\text {You}}(\textit{You get seafood})\). Thus, (8b) will be true.

It is worth remarking that although the decision-theoretic semantics fails to provide us with an adequate account of preference claims, I still think that decision-theoretic considerations impact preference. But as we will see in Sect. 2.3, this involves something more subtle than a simple expected value calculation of the arguments to ‘prefer’.

To sum up, we have considered two accounts of preference, both of which are extensions of popular approaches to desire, and found these accounts to be lacking. Our discussion provides us with sufficient motivation to consider a different approach, which is what I take up next.

2.3 An alternative-sensitive semantics for prefer

I develop my positive proposal in two stages. First, I provide a basic entry that captures some of the central features of my account. Then I propose a refinement that will help us generate a pleasing logic for preference.

Let us say that \({\mathcal {A}}\) is a set of alternatives if it is a set of pairwise incompatible propositions. So, if \(A, B \in {\mathcal {A}}\), then \(A \cap B = \emptyset \). To illustrate, let ann, mary, pete, and sue represent the propositions that Ann wins the race, Mary wins the race, Pete wins the race, and Sue wins the race, respectively. Then \({\mathcal {A}}_{1} = \{\) ann, mary, pete, sue\(\}\) is a set of alternatives. I propose that the set of objects that is relevant for the evaluation of a preference claim \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is a set of contextually supplied alternatives.Footnote 18\(^{,}\)Footnote 19

Given a set of alternatives \({\mathcal {A}}\) and a world w, \({\mathcal {O}}^{{\mathcal {A}}, w}(\cdot )\) is an ordering function from individuals to orderings over \({\mathcal {A}}\). It is assumed that \({\mathcal {O}}^{{\mathcal {A}}, w}(S)\) is a strict partial order. Intuitively, \({\mathcal {O}}^{{\mathcal {A}}, w}(S)\) represents S’s preference ordering over \({\mathcal {A}}\) in w, denoted \(\succ _{w, S}\). For instance, Bill’s preferences over \({\mathcal {A}}_{1}\) are represented below:

ann \(\succ _{\text {Bill}}\) mary \(\succ _{\text {Bill}}\) pete \(\succ _{\text {Bill}}\) sue

I propose that preference claims are evaluated relative to a contextually determined ordering function.

My first-run account of preference can then be expressed as follows:

Account 1

\(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is true relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {A}}, {\mathcal {O}} \rangle \) iff

for every \(B \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(B \subseteq p\), and every \(C \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(C \subseteq q\): \(B \succ _{w, S} C\)

In short: \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is true just in case S ranks every p-entailing alternative more highly than every q-entailing alternative. It is worth emphasizing that this semantics is in some sense strong: every p-entailing alternative and every q-entailing alternative is relevant for the assessment of a preference claim. So, it is sufficient for \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) to be false that that there is some p-entailing alternative that fails to be more highly ranked than some q-entailing alternative. Note, however, that the fact that preferences are computed over propositions rather than individual worlds means that this semantics isn’t implausibly strong. It is not required that subjects prefer every p-world to every q-world. As we saw in Sect. 2.2.1, this would be problematic: Sue can prefer buying insurance to not buying insurance, even if most worlds where she buys insurance are worse, by her lights, than most worlds she doesn’t buy insurance. By contrast, alternatives are relatively coarse-grained entities. So, even if there are some worlds in an alternative B that are non-optimal by S’s lights, S can still rank B higher than the other alternatives.

At this point, two natural meta-semantic questions arise for Account 1: (i) how exactly does the set of alternatives \({\mathcal {A}}\) get determined in context, and (ii) how is the subject’s ordering over alternatives \(\succ _{S}\) structured?Footnote 20 Regarding (ii), I’m attracted to the idea that the subject’s ordering is tied to decision-theoretic considerations. Most straightforwardly: \(A \succ _{S} B\) when \(EV_{S}(A) > EV_{S}(B)\). Assuming that the relevant alternatives in the Insurance scenario are just the proposition that Sue buys insurance and the proposition that she does not, this would explain why (17) (‘Sue prefers buying insurance to not buying insurance’) is true: the expected value of buying insurance, for Sue, is greater than the expected value of not buying insurance. As for (i), I will return to this issue in Sect. 4.2. For now, I want to discuss which features are exhibited by preference claims when we fix a context, and thereby fix a set of relevant alternatives and ordering over these alternatives. That is, our present concern is to detail the logic of preference.

Account 1 allows us to explain failures of upward monotonicity. Suppose that the relevant set of alternatives is \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\textsc {p}, \textsc {l}, \textsc {c}\}\), where p is the proposition that you get prawns, \(\textsc {l}\) is the proposition that you get lobster, and c is the proposition that you get chicken. Let us also suppose that your preferences over these alternatives look as follows:

p \(\succ _{\text {You}}\) \(\textsc {c}\) \(\succ _{\text {You}}\) \(\textsc {l}\)

Then (1a-i) (‘You prefer prawns to chicken’) is true, since p is ranked above every other alternative. However, (1a-ii) (‘You prefer seafood to chicken’) is false, since l entails that you get seafood, but it is ranked below c. Similarly, (2a-i) (‘You prefer chicken to lobster’) is true, since c is ranked above l. However, (2a-ii) (‘You prefer chicken to seafood’) is false, since p entails that you get seafood, but it is ranked above c. The other examples from Sect. 2.1 involving failures of disjunction introduction and conjunction elimination can be explained in a similar way.

However, Account 1 doesn’t quite capture our observations about downward monotonicity. The problem is that the logic it generates is too strong; it makes preference claims straightforwardly downward monotonic in both arguments. This has some good consequences, e.g. it predicts that (3a-i) entails (3a-ii), which explains why the latter seems to follow from the former:

figure q

After all, if every seafood-entailing alternative is ranked above every chicken-entailing alternative, then every prawns-entailing alternative will be ranked above every chicken-entailing alternative.

On the other hand, in Sect. 2.1 we saw that preference claims aren’t unrestrictedly downward monotonic. For instance, (6b) does not follow from (3a-i):

figure r

But (3a-i) also entails (6b) on Account 1: if every seafood-entailing alternative is ranked above every chicken-entailing alternative, then every seafood \(\wedge \) house burns down-entailing alternative will be ranked above every chicken-entailing alternative.

What examples such as (6b) show is that p and q need to be suitably related to \({\mathcal {A}}\) in order for \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) to be true. I will capture this as follows. Given a set of alternatives \({\mathcal {A}}\) and proposition p, let us say that p is represented by \({\mathcal {A}}\) just in case every alternative in \({\mathcal {A}}\) either entails p or entails \(\lnot p\).Footnote 21 For instance, the proposition that Ann or Mary wins the race is represented by \({\mathcal {A}}_{1} = \{\) ann, mary, pete, sue\(\}\), but the proposition that Mary eats pizza is not. And given a set of alternatives \({\mathcal {A}}\) and proposition p, let us say that p is non-trivially represented by \({\mathcal {A}}\) just in case (i) p is represented by \({\mathcal {A}}\), and (ii) there is some p-entailing alternative in \({\mathcal {A}}\).

I propose that \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is true only if both p and q are non-trivially represented by \({\mathcal {A}}\). One could impose this requirement as a regular truth-condition. However, I will instead treat it as a definedness condition, or presupposition, triggered by preference claims. The main reason for going this route is that it allows us to develop a pleasing logic for preference, which I will outline in a moment. The final entry for ‘prefer’ then looks as follows:

Alternative-sensitive semantics for prefer

\(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is defined relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {A}}, {\mathcal {O}} \rangle \) only if

   both p and q are non-trivially represented by \({\mathcal {A}}\)

If defined, \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) is true relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {A}}, {\mathcal {O}} \rangle \) iff

   for every \(B \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(B \subseteq p\), and every \(C \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(C \subseteq q\): \(B \succ _{w, S} C\)

In our discussions of upward and downward monotonicity, I (implicitly) assumed a classical notion of validity which requires preservation of truth at a point of evaluation. But now that we have presuppositions as part of the meaning of preference claims, more sophisticated notions of consequence can be formulated. More specifically, the notion that will be of particular relevance is that of Strawson validity (von Fintel , 1999). Essentially, an argument from a set of sentences \(\Gamma \) to a sentence \(\psi \) is Strawson valid just in case whenever all of the \(\varphi \in \Gamma \) and \(\psi \) are defined, if all of the \(\varphi \in \Gamma \) are true, then \(\psi \) must be true as well. A bit more explicitly:Footnote 22

Strawson Validity:

\(\Gamma \models \psi \) iff there is no context c and world w such that (i) every \(\varphi \in \Gamma \) and \(\psi \) are all defined at c, w; (ii) every \(\varphi \in \Gamma \) is true at c, w; and (iii) \(\psi \) is false at c, w.

On this alternative-sensitive semantics, preference claims are Strawson downward monotonic in both of their arguments. That is, Downwardness holds:

Downwardness

If \(p \models q\) and \(r \models s\), then \(\textit{S prefers q to s} \models \textit{S prefers p to r}\)

Suppose \(\ulcorner \)S prefers q to s\(\urcorner \) is true, and \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to r\(\urcorner \) is defined. Consider some arbitrary p-entailing alternative B, and some arbitrary r-entailing alternative C (such alternatives must exist since both p and r are non-trivially represented). Because \(p \subseteq q\) and \(r \subseteq s\), B entails q, and C entails s. Since \(\ulcorner \)S prefers q to s\(\urcorner \) is true, we must have \(B \succ _{S} C\). But then since B and C were arbitrary, \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to r\(\urcorner \) must be true as well.

Downwardness allows us to explain our remaining observations from Sect. 2.1. In the most natural contexts where (3a-i) (‘You prefer seafood to chicken’) is assessed, the proposition that you get prawns will be non-trivially represented by the relevant set of alternatives. Thus, since Downwardness holds, if (3a-i) is true, (3a-ii) (‘You prefer prawns to chicken’) will be true as well. However, in these same contexts, (3a-i) can be true without (6b) (‘You prefer seafood and having your house burned down to chicken’) being true: the proposition that you get seafood and your house burns down won’t be (non-trivially) represented by the relevant set of alternatives. For instance, if \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\textsc {p}, \textsc {l}, \textsc {c}\}\) from above, then if (3a-i) is true, (3a-ii) will be true as well. But (6b) won’t be defined, since some alternatives in \({\mathcal {A}}\) entail neither You get seafood and your house burns down nor \(\lnot \)You get seafood and your house burns down.Footnote 23

Moreover, we can explain why examples such as (4a) and (5) are unacceptable:

figure u

If both conjuncts in (4a) are defined, then since Downwardness holds, the second conjunct will be false if the first conjunct is true. And if one of the conjuncts isn’t defined, then the whole conjunction will fail to be defined.Footnote 24 So, (4a) can never be true. For (5), we observe that preference claims are irreflexive on this semantics:Footnote 25

Irreflexivity

\(\models \lnot \textit{S prefers p to p}\)

So, if (5) is defined, then given Downwardness it will be false. And if (5) isn’t defined then of course it cannot be true. In any event, (5) cannot be true.

Strawson entailment also allows us to validate several further patterns which are arguably necessary conditions for a subjective ordering to be considered a preference relation:Footnote 26

Transitivity

\(\textit{S prefers p to q}, \textit{S prefers q to r} \models \textit{S prefers p to r}\)

Asymmetry

\(\textit{S prefers p to q} \models \lnot \textit{S prefers q to p}\)

We also validate the following intuitively plausible principles:Footnote 27\(^{,}\)Footnote 28

Preference Weakening 1

\(\textit{S prefers p to q}, \textit{S prefers r to q} \models \textit{S prefers p or r to q}\)

Preference Weakening 2

\(\textit{S prefers p to q}, \textit{S prefers p to r} \models \textit{S prefers p to q or r}\)

I’lll close this section with a possible concern for my approach to preference involving indifference claims, i.e. sentences of the form \(\ulcorner \)S is indifferent between p and q\(\urcorner \).Footnote 29 A prima facie plausible principle linking preference to indifference is the following:

Preference-to-Indifference

\(\lnot \textit{S prefers p to q}, \lnot \textit{S prefers q to p} \models \textit{S is indifferent} \textit{between p and q}\)

That is, a lack of preference in either direction between p and q is sufficient for the truth of the corresponding indifference claim. However, my semantics appears to invalidate this pattern. Consider our running seafood example once again, where your preferences over the alternatives are as follows: p \(\succ _{\text {You}}\) \(\textsc {c}\) \(\succ _{\text {You}}\) \(\textsc {l}\). Then on my entry both ‘You don’t prefer seafood to chicken’ and ‘You don’t prefer chicken to seafood’ are true (relative to the most natural set of alternatives). However, (20) doesn’t seem acceptable in context:Footnote 30

figure v

In response, I maintain that such cases do indeed bring natural counterexamples to Preference-to-Indifference. In the seafood example, it would be natural for you to say something like ‘I don’t prefer seafood to chicken, since lobster is much worse than chicken, and I don’t prefer chicken to seafood, since prawns are much better than chicken, but I also wouldn’t say that I’m indifferent between seafood and chicken’. Such contexts illustrate that a lack of preference isn’t sufficient for indifference, and that natural language expressions of indifference denote a more substantial mental state than we might have antecedently assumed. One proposal for indifference claims set in the alternative-sensitive framework that makes good on this idea is the following:

Alternative-sensitive semantics for indifference

\(\ulcorner \)S is indifferent between p and q\(\urcorner \) is defined relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {A}}, {\mathcal {O}} \rangle \) only if

   both p and q are non-trivially represented by \({\mathcal {A}}\)

If defined, \(\ulcorner \)S is indifferent between p and q\(\urcorner \) is true relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {A}}, {\mathcal {O}} \rangle \) iff

   for every \(B \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(B \subseteq p\), and every \(C \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(C \subseteq q\): \(B \not \succ _{w, S} C\) and \(C \not \succ _{w, S} B\)

In other words, a subject is indifferent between p and q only if no p-entailing alternative outranks any q-entailing alternative, and no q-entailing alternative outranks any p-entailing alternative. This is why (20) is false in the seafood context: the You get chicken-entailing alternative “splits” the You get seafood-entailing alternatives.

However, note that although this account of indifference invalidates Preference-to-Indifference, it is straightforward to check that it validates its converse:

Indifference-to-Preference

\(\textit{S is indifferent between p and q} \models \lnot \textit{S prefers p to q}\)

That is, being indifferent between p and q suffices for a lack of preference in either direction. This is a good result, since Indifference-to-Preference appears to be much more robust than Preference-to-Indifference.Footnote 31\(^{,}\)Footnote 32

In this section, we began with some observations about preference claims. I then developed an account of preference whose crucial features are (i) preference claims are alternative-sensitive, and (ii) the semantics is strong: in order for \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to q\(\urcorner \) to be true, every p-entailing alternative needs to be more highly ranked than every q-entailing alternative. I showed that this entry allows us to explain our initial observations, and gives rise to an intuitive logic for preference. In particular, this account explains the positive status of downward monotonicity without making it unrestrictedly valid; on my theory preference claims are Strawson, but not classically, downward monotonic. In the next section, I turn to desire reports, and explore whether the semantics for preference can help us develop an account of want ascriptions.

3 Desire

I begin by presenting an entry for ‘want’ that is inspired by my entry for ‘prefer’ (Sect. 3.1). Then I consider the logic that this semantics generates, and show that the proposal explains a wide range of phenomena that isn’t captured by existing accounts (Sect. 3.2).

3.1 An alternative-sensitive semantics for want

As mentioned in Sect. 1, many philosophers have assumed that there is a deep connection between preference and desire. I develop this thought in a novel direction by proposing that the preference-desire connection is in some sense reflected in the object language itself. More precisely, I want to explore the idea that a desire report \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) means virtually the same as the preference claim \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to \(\lnot \)p\(\urcorner \). We can find some intuitive motivation for this proposal if we consider how we tend to justify our desires: in providing reasons for why one wants or desires p, it is natural to appeal to one’s preference for p over the other relevant options. For example, (21b) is a perfectly natural answer to the question in (21a):

figure w

Moreover, in many contexts, \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) and \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to \(\lnot \)p\(\urcorner \) seem virtually synonymous. For instance, consider (22a) and (22b):

figure x

It is difficult to recover coherent interpretations of these sentences, which is what we would expect if desire reports and preference claims share an underlying semantics.Footnote 33

Supposing that \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) means the same as \(\ulcorner \)S prefers p to \(\lnot \)p\(\urcorner \), and given our entry for ‘prefer’, the entry for desire reports is then the following:Footnote 34

Alternative-sensitive semantics for want

\(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) is defined relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {A}}, {\mathcal {O}} \rangle \) only if

   both p and \(\lnot p\) are non-trivially represented by \({\mathcal {A}}\)

If defined, \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) is true relative to \(\langle w, {\mathcal {A}}, {\mathcal {O}} \rangle \) iff

   for every \(B \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(B \subseteq p\), and every \(C \in {\mathcal {A}}\) such that \(C \subseteq \lnot p\):    \(B \succ _{w, S} C\)

\(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) is defined only if both p and \(\lnot p\) are non-trivially represented by the set of relevant alternatives. If defined, \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) is true just in case S ranks every p-entailing alternative above every \(\lnot p\)-entailing alternative. As with our account of preference, every p-entailing alternative and every q-entailing alternative is relevant for evaluating a desire report. So, if defined, it is sufficient for \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) to be false that there is some p-entailing alternative that fails to be more highly ranked than some \(\lnot p\)-entailing alternative.

It is worth pausing to bring out a feature of this semantics. Almost all existing accounts of desire posit a close connection between what is desired and what is believed. More precisely, most accounts posit the following constraint: \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) is true only if S neither believes p nor \(\lnot p\) (Heim , 1992; von Fintel , 1999; Levinson , 2003).Footnote 35 By contrast, nowhere in my semantics for ‘want’ do I appeal to the subject’s beliefs. I take this to be a good-making feature of the entry. It has been recognized for some time (though it is often ignored) that subjects can want things that they are certain won’t obtain, as well as things that they are certain do obtain/will obtain:

figure y

These examples are perfectly felicitous, but they are difficult to account for given standard belief constraints on want ascriptions.Footnote 36 But my semantics has no problem with these cases, since I place no restrictions on what the set of alternatives needs to be like.

Note that my account is compatible with the idea that in many situations, the relevant alternatives for evaluating \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) will be things that S believes might obtain. But what the above examples show is that this isn’t always the case, and therefore shouldn’t be built into our semantics for want reports. Also, denying that there is a strong connection between believing and wanting is compatible with there being more subtle relationships between these states. For instance, beliefs could still play a role in explaining the way presuppositions project from desire contexts (Heim , 1992; Maier , 2015). Finally, claiming that ‘want’ does not carry strong belief requirements is compatible with thinking that other desire verbs do. For instance, analogues of the examples in (23) with ‘hope’ sound much worse:

figure z

This suggests that hope reports impose non-trivial constraints on the subject’s beliefs. We can capture such constraints if we introduce the following concept: given a subject S and world w, \(\hbox {Dox}_{w, S}\) is S’s belief set in w; the set of worlds compatible with everything S believes in w (Hintikka , 1962). Then we can say that hope reports carry an additional definedness condition: each alternative in \({\mathcal {A}}\) must have non-empty intersection with \(\hbox {Dox}_{w, S}\).Footnote 37 It is plausible that the meaning of other desire verbs, e.g. ‘wish’, can also be understood as variants of my semantics for ‘want’. But I’ll leave charting these fine-grained differences between desire verbs for future work. For the most part I’ll continue to focus on want reports.

Now that I have presented my account of desire, let us consider some of its most interesting logical properties.

3.2 The logic of desire

First, we have a number of closure failures: want reports are neither upward nor downward monotonic.

Not Up

There are pq such that \(p \subseteq q\), but \(\textit{S wants p} \not \models \textit{S wants q}\)

Not Down

There are pq such that \(p \subseteq q\), but \(\textit{S wants q} \not \models \textit{S wants p}\)

Such failures have been discussed a great deal in the literature on desire reports.Footnote 38 Not Up can be illustrated by considering the following case that is essentially from Levinson (2003):

Flip: Bill has agreed to play a game involving two coin flips. If the first coin lands heads, the game ends and Bill is given $200. If the first coin lands tails, then the second coin is flipped. If the second coin lands tails then the game ends and Bill gets $300, but if the second coin lands heads then the game ends and Bill gets nothing. That is, the outcomes are as follows: H = $200, TT = $300, TH = $0.

figure aa

Although (26a) seems true, (26b) does not. After all, if the first coin lands tails, then Bill knows there’s a good chance he’ll get nothing. We can explain this if we suppose that the relevant set of alternatives is \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\textsc {h}, \textsc {tt}, \textsc {th}\}\), where h is the proposition that the first coin lands heads, \(\textsc {tt}\) is the proposition that both coins land tails, and \(\textsc {th}\) is the proposition that the first coin lands tails and the second lands heads. Bill’s ranking of these alternatives looks as follows:

tt \(\succ _{\text {Bill}}\) \(\textsc {h}\) \(\succ _{\text {Bill}} \textsc {th}\)

Then we predict that (26a) should be true, since tt is ranked above every other alternative. But (26b) is false, since \(\textsc {th}\) entails that the first coin lands tails, but it is ranked below \(\textsc {h}\). It is worth saying that although most existing accounts of desire make want reports non-monotonic, examples such as (26) are fairly controversial. Most notably, von Fintel (1999) has argued that desire is upward monotonic after all. We will consider his arguments in Sect. 4.1.

Note that even if p entails q, our semantics allows \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) to be true without \(\ulcorner \)S wants q\(\urcorner \) even being defined. This can account for Stalnaker’s (1984) observation that (27a) can be true without (27b) being true:

figure ab

It is plausible that in most natural contexts, the relevant alternatives for evaluating (27a) will just be the proposition that I die peacefully, and the proposition that I die painfully. In that case, (27b) will be undefined, since there will be no alternatives that entail that I don’t die.

To illustrate Not Down, suppose that you are choosing between buying a Honda car, a Ford car, and a Vespa scooter. Scooters are dangerous, so you like the Vespa the least. Hondas have a reputation for being safe, so you like that the best. Then (28a) is true, but (28b) is not:

figure ac

Let us suppose that the set of alternatives is \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\textsc {h}, \textsc {f}, \textsc {v}\}\), where h is the proposition that you buy a Honda car, f is the proposition that you buy a Ford car, and v is the proposition that you buy a Vespa scooter. Your ranking over these alternatives is as follows:

h \(\succ _{\text {You}}\) \(\textsc {f}\) \(\succ _{\text {You}} \textsc {v}\)

Then (28a) is true, since both h and f outrank v. But (28b) is false, since h entails that you don’t buy a Ford, and yet is ranked above f.

Another important fact is that desire isn’t closed under believed equivalence:

No Belief Closure

\(\textit{S wants p}, \textit{S believes p iff q} \not \models \textit{S wants q}\)

This feature of desire reports has been discussed by Villalta (2008), Rubinstein (2012), and Phillips-Brown (2018). For instance, Villalta observes that both (29a) and (29b) can be true while (29c) is false:

figure ad

To see that this is possible, let wc, \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\) c, w\(\overline{\textsc {c}}\), and \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\overline{\textsc {c}}\) represent the propositions that Mary wins and physically collapses, that she doesn’t win but still collapses, etc. Consider some context where \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\) wc, \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\) c, w\(\overline{\textsc {c}}\), and \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\overline{\textsc {c}}\) \(\}\). Suppose further that Bill’s preferences over these alternatives are as follows:

\(\textsc {w}\overline{\textsc {c}}\) \(\succ _{\text {Bill}}\) wc \(\succ _{\text {Bill}}\) \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\overline{\textsc {c}}\) \(\succ _{\text {Bill}}\) \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\) c

Then (29a) and (29b) are true, but (29c) is false. Again, it is worth remarking that both (29a) and (29b) can be true without (29c) being defined. This could happen if, for instance, the alternatives are just w and \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\). Then (29c) will suffer from presupposition failure, since the proposition that Mary collapses physically won’t be represented. Presumably, this captures the felt infelicity of (29c) in many contexts.

So far, we have been concerned with failures of consequence, but there are also some interesting validities. For one thing, we have the following rule which Blumberg and Hawthorne (2021) call Want Weakening, after an analogous principle in deontic logic discussed by Cariani (2016):Footnote 39

Want Weakening

\(\textit{S wants p}, \textit{S wants q} \models \textit{S wants p or q}\)

The pattern exhibited by Want Weakening is highly plausible. However, it can be shown that several popular analyses of desire render it invalid.Footnote 40

Finally, we also have the following:Footnote 41

Acceptable Disjuncts

\(\textit{S wants p or q} \models \lnot (\textit{S wants} \ \lnot \textit{p})\)

Acceptable Disjuncts accounts for an observation by Crnič (2011, 166) to the effect that disjunctions in the scope of desire reports give rise to an “acceptability inference” regarding both disjuncts. That is, both disjuncts need to be judged to be acceptable, or OK, by the subject. For instance, neither (32a) nor (32b) are felicitous:Footnote 42

figure af

To sum up, the preference-based semantics for desire reports captures a fairly wide range of phenomena. Among other things, it accounts for why desire is neither upward nor downward monotonic (Stalnaker , 1984; Heim , 1992; Levinson , 2003; Lassiter , 2011), and why desire isn’t closed under believed equivalence (Villalta , 2008; Phillips-Brown , 2018). Moreover, although the theory allows for closure failures, it is not too weak, as it also validates some intuitively compelling principles. For instance, on this account \(\ulcorner \)S wants p or q\(\urcorner \) follows from \(\ulcorner \)S wants p\(\urcorner \) and \(\ulcorner \)S wants q\(\urcorner \), and it also explains why disjunctions in the scope of desire verbs give rise to an “acceptability inference” regarding both disjuncts (Crnič , 2011).Footnote 43 These successes are significant in themselves, but they gain even greater interest given that the proposal is independently motivated. The central features of the account of desire are shaped by the theory of preference from Sect. 2, and the intuitive connection between preference and desire. Overall, I think that this preference-based theory of want reports provides us with a promising approach to desiderative attitudes.

4 Possible worries

By way of a conclusion, I raise and respond to two concerns for the approach to preference and desire developed in Sects. 23. The first worry involves a detail in the logic of desire, namely non-monotonicity (Sect. 4.1). The second concern involves issues around how alternatives get fixed in context (Sect. 4.2).

4.1 Abominable conjunctions

In Sect. 3.2, I showed that desire reports are not closed under entailment on my account. For instance, I predict that there are contexts where (26a) is true but (26b) is false:

figure ag

Now, von Fintel (1999, 120) raises a challenge for approaches to desire that reject upward monotonicity. The central observation is that conjunctions such as (33) are unacceptable:

figure ah

But this is surprising if desire reports are non-monotonic: if (26a) is true and (26b) is false, then why can’t one felicitously conjoin them as in (33)? By contrast, this is easily explained on accounts that validate monotonicity—conjunctions such as (33) can never be true. Von Fintel takes this to be a compelling argument for thinking that desire is closed under entailment.Footnote 44

However, recent work on desiderative attitudes suggests that von Fintel’s argument fails to be decisive. For one thing, as Blumberg (2021) observes, it simply isn’t the case that conjunctions of the form \(\ulcorner \)S wants p but S doesn’t want q\(\urcorner \) are always unacceptable when p entails q. Consider the following scenario from Blumberg (2021, 3):

Prisoner: Ann thinks that there is exactly one prisoner in the dock. She also thinks that this individual is either Bill or Carol, and that the prisoner might be hanged. Bill is Ann’s mortal enemy, so it would be best for Ann if Bill is the prisoner and is hanged. By contrast, Carol is Ann’s friend, so even if Carol is the prisoner, Ann would hate it if she was hanged.

figure ai

The prisoner is Bill and Bill hangs obviously entails The prisoner hangs. Yet the conjunction (34) is perfectly acceptable. Indeed, Ann herself could say ‘I want the prisoner to be Bill and for Bill to hang, but I don’t want the prisoner to be hanged (since the prisoner could be Carol)’. This would be difficult to explain if desire was monotonic.

Moreover, Blumberg and Hawthorne (2022) note that the pattern exhibited by (33) also arises with attitude verbs that are plausibly non-monotonic. For instance, they consider ‘fear’. Suppose that you’ve just lost your job. Because you have bills to pay, (35a) is true. But it doesn’t follow that either (35b-i) or (35b-ii) are:

figure aj

This indicates that ‘fear’ is non-monotonic. Now consider the following scenario from Blumberg and Hawthorne (2021, 3):

Fortune: Three coins will be flipped, and Bill’s reckless brother has bet the family fortune on the outcome. If the first coin lands heads, and the second or third coin lands tails, the fortune will be doubled. Any other configuration of the coins leads to the fortune being lost.

(36) is easily heard as true in this scenario:

figure ak

After all, if all three coins land heads, Bill knows that the fortune will be lost, and he would certainly not like that. But by the same token, (37) is also easily heard as false:

figure al

After all, if the first coin lands heads, there’s a good chance that the fortune will be doubled, and Bill would certainly like that. However, Blumberg and Hawthorne observe that infelicity results if we try to conjoin (36) with the negation of (37):

figure am

Intuitively, the unacceptability of (38) is related to the infelicity of (33). Assuming that ‘fear’ is non-monotonic, the unacceptability of (38) can’t be explained by appealing to monotonicity. But then it is plausible that the infelicity of (33) shouldn’t be explained by appealing to monotonicity either. A more general explanation is needed. To be clear, such an explanation still needs to be provided, so there is more work to be done here. But for our purposes, the important point is that conjunctions such as (33) don’t obviously tell against a non-monotonic analysis of desire reports.Footnote 45

4.2 Fixing alternatives

Another worry is that my account seems to make too many desire reports come out false.Footnote 46 Consider the following example:

Wine: We’re at a restaurant choosing what to drink with dinner. The menu lists several wines and beers. The best wines are better than anything else, but some of the beers are better than some of the mediocre wines. You ask me what I’d like to drink. I reply:

figure an

(39) is perfectly acceptable here. However, the account seems to predict that the report should be false, since there are some wine-entailing alternatives that are ranked below some \(\lnot \)wine-entailing alternatives.

This worry assumes that the background set of alternatives is relatively fine-grained, so that each specific wine and beer is represented. But it’s not obvious that this is the case. If a comparatively coarser-grained set of alternatives is in play, then the account can handle this example. For instance, suppose that the relevant set of alternatives is \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\textsc {w}, \overline{\textsc {w}} \}\), where w and \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\) are the propositions that I get wine with dinner, and that I don’t get wine with dinner, respectively. We can suppose that my preference ranking over these alternatives is as follows:

w \(\succ _{\text {Me}}\) \(\overline{\textsc {w}}\)

In this case, (39) is predicted to be true.Footnote 47

This response touches on a more general issue about how the background set of alternatives gets determined in context. This is obviously an important topic, and the account won’t be complete without a predictive theory of how this parameter gets fixed. Unfortunately, I don’t have a detailed answer at present, and I must leave the provision of such a theory for future work. That said, I’d like to register that there is independent motivation for thinking that desire reports exhibit a fair amount of “shiftness” in the alternatives relative to which they’re evaluated. To see this, consider (40) in the following scenario:

Envelopes: There are two red envelopes and one blue envelope. One of the red envelopes contains $100, while the other contains $10; the blue envelope contains $50. An envelope will be selected at random and given to you. You say:

figure ao

(40) is easily heard as false here. For instance, it would be natural for someone to respond by saying something like ‘I’m confused, since obviously you don’t prefer getting the red envelope with $10 to getting the blue envelope. So, how could you be happy with getting a red envelope?’. On the other hand, the report can also be heard as true. This can be brought out if it is made salient that the expected value of getting a red envelope is greater than getting the blue envelope:

figure ap

(40) is acceptable here. But nothing concerning the subject’s internal psychology changed between these two contexts. So, accounts that reduce the semantic value of desideratives to internal psychological features will have a hard time explaining the contrast. This supports alternative-sensitivity: we can explain the differences in how (40) is heard by appealing to shifts in which alternatives are relevant. In the first context, a relatively fine-grained set of alternatives is relevant, e.g. \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\textsc {r100}, \textsc {r10}, \textsc {blue}\}\), where r100 is the proposition that you get the red envelope with $100, r10 is the proposition that you get the red envelope with $10, and blue is the proposition that you get the blue envelope. By contrast, (40) is acceptable in the second context because a more coarse-grained set of alternatives is used, e.g. \({\mathcal {A}} = \{\textsc {r}, \overline{\textsc {r}}\}\), where r is the proposition that you get given a red envelope, and \(\overline{\textsc {r}}\) is the proposition that you get given a non-red, i.e. blue envelope. If alternative-sensitivity is the correct way to explain what is going on here, then charting the dynamics of alternative shift is a project that should be of fairly broad interest.Footnote 48

It is also worth emphasizing that no matter how exactly this meta-semantic question gets settled, it constitutes progress to say that the evaluation of preference claims and desire reports goes by a contextually determined set of alternatives. As we have seen, the semantic structures that I have posited allow us to explain the logical features of these constructions in a neat fashion. So, to a fairly large degree, the good-making features of the account don’t essentially hang on how exactly the set of alternatives gets fixed in context.Footnote 49\(^{,}\)Footnote 50