Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Rule Utilitarianism and Rational Acceptance

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article presents a rule-utilitarian theory which lies much closer to the social contract tradition than most other forms of consequentialism do: calculated-rates rule preference utilitarianism. Being preference-utilitarian allows the theory to be grounded in instrumental rationality and the equality of agents, as opposed to teleological assumptions about impartial goodness. The calculated-rates approach, judging rules’ consequences by what would happen if they were accepted by whatever number of people is realistic rather than by what would happen if they were accepted universally or by exactly 90% of the population, allows it to select rules based not just on their ability to give good advice to their followers but also on their ability to attract followers in the first place. The result is a theory that, although fully utilitarian and not at all pluralistic or intuitionist, nevertheless offers a principled justification for giving some weight to seemingly non-utilitarian considerations: Lockean natural rights, Kantian respect for autonomy, and Scanlonian distributive justice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A functionally-similar combination, albeit under the bland title “equal consideration” rather than the more descriptive “calculated-rates rule preference utilitarianism”, has previously been advocated by Haslett (1987).

  2. Others have made similar points about possible non-teleological groundings of utilitarianism. For example, Scanlon (1982: 115) distinguishes “philosophical utilitarianism” from the possibility that utilitarianism will be a “normative implication” of contractualism, and Kagan (1998: 252, 319) likewise suggests that a theory which is contractarian or universalizing at a “foundational” level might be consequentialist at a “factoral” level.

  3. Haslett (1987: 49–50) asserts that neither he nor Hare are preference utilitarians. However, the disagreement is just a semantic one: he defines “preferences” in terms of a person’s actual attitudes rather than in terms of what the person would want if mentally competent and fully informed, and believes that we should promote the latter.

  4. Foot (1985: 203) explicitly acknowledges that “utilitarian theories of the type put forward by John C. Harsanyi and R. M. Hare” are exempt from her accusation of question-begging, so I think it is accurate to describe her as targeting only teleological consequentialism.

  5. This is the view defended in Hooker (2000), who extracts a rule consequentialist theory, mostly utilitarian but with some priority for the worst off, from Rawls’s principle of reflective equilibrium.

  6. Arguing for (a) and (b) would require replying to the “queerness” problems discussed by Mackie (1977: 38–42). Arguing for (c) and (d) would require reconciling the tension between the objectivity and normativity of moral judgments, as discussed by, e.g., Bagnoli (2002).

  7. I base the oligarch example on Gauthier (1986: 190–192), the racism example on Dworkin (1981: 197–201), and the medicine example on Taurek (1977).

  8. A more exotic route to preference utilitarianism would pass through noncausal decision theory: this pathway is implicitly suggested by Lewis (1979), and seems to be at least partially embraced by Hofstadter (1985: 737–779).

  9. I am of course using the phrase “universal law of nature” deliberately; contrast Hooker’s test with the one from Kant (1785: 4:421).

  10. Similar views have also been advanced by Haslett (1987: 55) and Miller (2021: 129), who respectively argue that the correct norms are the ones which would be the object of the optimific “social-pressure combination” or “uniform system of moral education”.

  11. This supposedly evolved as a paraphrase of an unpublished speech by Martin Niemöller; I do not know who first put it into its present form. See also the discussion of “indirect duties” to animals in Kant (1780: 239–241)—mistreating one group damages one’s own character, making it more likely than one will later mistreat others—and the discussion in Haslett (1987: 173–180) about the various ways in which discrimination tends to be bad even for the dominant group.

  12. Again, one might take this to be the project of Machiavelli (1532).

  13. For example, by Harsanyi (1977a: 634–635): “the main difference [between Harsanyi’s utilitarian view and Rawls’s contractualist view] is that Rawls makes the technical mistake of basing his analysis on a highly irrational decision rule, the maximin principle, which was fairly fashionable thirty years ago but which lost its attraction a few years later when its absurd practical implications were realized”.

  14. Compare with the discussion by Scanlon (1975: 317–318) on why individuals have an interest in having a zone of privacy.

  15. This formulation also closely resembles the view advocated by Gauthier (1986: 143–144).

  16. See Dworkin (1981) for an argument that there is no single conception of “equality of welfare” that is uniquely correct, and Temkin (1993) for a survey of the ways in which different conceptions of equality can disagree.

References

  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2010. The Honor Code: How Moral Revolutions Happen. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, Carla. 2002. Moral Constructivism: A Phenomenological Argument. Topoi 21: 125–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, Jeremy. 1789. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. London: T. Payne and Son.

  • Brandt, Richard B. 1963. Toward a Credible Form of Utilitarianism. In Morality and the Language of Conduct, ed. Hector-Neri. Castañeda and George Nakhinkian, 107–143. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, Richard. 1976. The Selfish Gene. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1981. What is Equality? Part 1: Equality of Welfare. Philosophy and Public Affairs 10(3): 185–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, Philippa. 1985. Utilitarianism and the Virtues. Mind 94(374): 196–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David. 1986. Morals by Agreement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R.M. 1981. Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, John C. 1953. Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-taking. Journal of Political Economy 61(5): 434–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, John C. 1977. Morality and the Theory of Rational Behavior. Social Research 44(4): 623–656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, John C. 1977. Rule Utilitarianism and Decision Theory. Erkenntnis 11(1): 25–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslett, D.W. 1987. Equal Consideration: A Theory of Moral Justification. Newark: University of Delaware Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1651. Leviathan. London: Andrew Crooke.

  • Hofstadter, Douglas R. 1985. Metamagical Themas: Questing for the Essence of Mind and Pattern. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, Brad. 2000. Ideal Code, Real World. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, Lester. 1985. On Improving Mankind by Political Means. Reason Papers 10: 61–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, Shelly. 1998. Normative Ethics. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1780[1963]. Lectures in Ethics. transl. Louis Infield. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1785[1996]. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. In Practical Philosophy, transl. Mary Gregor, 43–108. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lewis, David. 1979. Prisoners’ Dilemma is a Newcomb Problem. Philosophy & Public Affairs 8(3): 235–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1690. Second Treatise of Government. London: Awnsham Churchill.

  • Machiavelli, Niccolò. 1532. The Prince. Rome: Antonio Blado.

  • Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Dale. 2021. Moral Education and Rule Consequentialism. The Philosophical Quarterly 71(1): 120–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Timothy D. 2016. Solving Rule-Consequentialism’s Acceptance Rate Problem. Utilitas 28(1): 41–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters, vol. One. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, Michael. 2006. Introducing Variable-Rate Rule-Utilitarianism. The Philosophical Quarterly 56(223): 242–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T.M. 1975. Thomson on Privacy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 4(4): 315–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T.M. 1982. Contractualism and Utilitarianism. In Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, 103–128. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T.M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Holly M. 2010. Measuring the Consequences of Rules. Utilitas 22(4): 413–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taurek, John M. 1977. Should the Numbers Count? Philosophy & Public Affairs 6(4): 293–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, Larry S. 1993. Inequality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful for the assistance of several anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Evan G. Williams.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Williams, E.G. Rule Utilitarianism and Rational Acceptance. J Ethics 27, 305–328 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-023-09428-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-023-09428-7

Keywords

Navigation