Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Responsibility, Manipulation, and Minutelings

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article explores the significance of agents’ histories for directly free actions and actions for which agents are directly morally responsible. Candidates for relevant compatibilist historical constraints discussed by Michael McKenna and Alfred Mele are assessed, as is the bearing of manipulation on free action and moral responsibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Mele (1995, p. 154) for a brief discussion of irresistible desires or Mele (1992, ch. 5) for a detailed discussion. I am not claiming that the desires in unsheddable values are irresistible.

  2. NFM is identical with a statement (NF) in Mele (2006, p. 170), with one exception: NFM includes the words “and is not morally responsible for A-ing” (between “does not freely A” and condition 1).

  3. I take it that being able to A at will entails being able to A very easily and with very little effort. Some might say “effortlessly”; but I regard that as a bit of an exaggeration, if the assertion is taken literally.

  4. For example, in Mele (1995), I replied to the view expressed in the following claim by Harry Frankfurt: “to the extent that a person identifies himself with the springs of his actions, he takes responsibility for those actions and acquires moral responsibility for them; moreover, the questions of how the actions and his identifications with their springs are caused are irrelevant to the questions of whether he performs the actions freely or is morally responsible for performing them.” (Frankfurt 1988, p. 54) As I explained in Mele (2009a, p. 163), this claim obviously does not commit Frankfurt to rejecting McKenna’s assertion (see Mele 2009a, p. 162) that two drunk drivers “are such that only one is responsible and not the other if only one freely chose to get drunk and then drive while the other was force-fed two bottles of tequila and put behind the wheel of a car.” (McKenna 2012, pp. 156–157) But Frankfurt’s claim does entail something interesting. Suppose that Art freely embarked on a program of self-perfection that included many free selfless actions for which he was morally responsible and eventually made himself such that it was psychologically impossible for him to turn down the reasonable request for assistance that he just received from a homeless child. Art fully identifies with the springs of his actions. Compare Art with Bart, who, until this morning, had been a self-made selfish jerk for years—a jerk who enjoyed humiliating the homeless when he had the opportunity. Last night, everything changed for Bart. Art’s wonderful values were implanted in him and all competing values were erased. Bart identifies with his implanted values to the same extent that Art identifies with his. As Art helps a homeless kid on one side of town, Bart helps another homeless kid just as much on the other side of town. The view expressed in the quotation from Frankfurt entails that if either kid-helping action is free so is the other—and the same goes for moral responsibility. If directly free action and action for which the agent is directly morally responsible are not options here, then this pair of cases is not getting at what McKenna wants to get at. But cases of this kind do receive a lot of attention in Mele (1995)—partly because of their direct relevance to Frankfurt’s stated position.

  5. For a real-life case in which a brain tumor turned a man into a pedophile, see Burns and Swerdlow (2003). After the tumor was excised, the pedophilia disappeared.

  6. I am grateful to Gunnar Bjornsson for motivating me to write this paper and to Michael McKenna for his comments on a draft. This article was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed here are my own and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation.

References

  • Burns, J., and R. Swerdlow. 2003. Right orbitofrontal tumor with pedophilia symptom and constructional apraxia sign. Archives of Neurology 60: 437–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. 1988. The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. 1988. The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. 2004. Responsibility and globally manipulated agents. Philosophical Topics 32: 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. 2012. Moral responsibility, manipulation arguments, and history: Assessing the resilience of nonhistorical compatibilism. The Journal of Ethics 16: 145–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 1992. Springs of action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 1995. Autonomous agents. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 2006. Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 2008. Manipulation, compatibilism, and moral responsibility. The Journal of Ethics 12: 263–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 2009a. Moral responsibility and agents’ histories. Philosophical Studies 142: 161–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 2009b. Moral responsibility and history revisited. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12: 463–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfred R. Mele.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mele, A.R. Moral Responsibility, Manipulation, and Minutelings. J Ethics 17, 153–166 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-013-9148-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-013-9148-8

Keywords

Navigation