Skip to main content
Log in

Asymmetries in Benefiting, Harming and Creating

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is often said that while we have a strong reason not to create someone who will be badly off, we have no strong reason for creating someone who will be well off. In this paper I argue that this asymmetry is incompatible with a plausible principle of independence of irrelevant alternatives, and that a more general asymmetry between harming and benefiting is difficult to defend. I then argue that, contrary to what many have claimed, it is possible to harm or benefit someone by bringing her into existence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This view is very widely held in the population ethics literature. For a prominent recent statement, see Broome (2004, p. 144).

  2. Thanks to Elizabeth Brake, Sarah Stroud and Tyler Doggett for pressing this point.

  3. For a recent defense of this view see Benatar (2006); also see Benatar, “Still Better Never to Have Been: A Reply to (More of) My Critics,” in this issue of The Journal of Ethics.

  4. Popper (1966, p. 284n2); for more recent examples see Shiffrin (1999) and Harman (2004, p. 98).

  5. Ingmar Persson argues against this sort of explanation of the asymmetry (Persson 2009).

  6. This view is similar to a “weak asymmetry” principle defended by Arrhenius and Bykvist (1995, p. 97).

  7. Maybe there are also non-welfare-related reasons for and against actions. I am focusing on welfare-related reasons.

  8. See A. Sen’s “basic contraction consistency” principle (Sen 2002, p. 128). The principle to which I am appealing is not quite the same; Sen’s principle merely entails that if (3a) must be chosen, then so must (2), whereas my principle entails that the relative strengths of (3a) and (3b) must be the same as (2) and (2″). The spirit behind the principles is the same. Sen argues that there are counterexamples to contraction consistency (Sen 2002, pp. 129–130). I find his counterexamples unconvincing. See Neumann (2007) for a response to Sen; see Broome (1991, pp. 94–117), for discussion of important related issues concerning the individuation of alternatives and outcomes. Depending on how finely we individuate alternatives, it could turn out that (3a) and (2) are not the same alternative, so contraction consistency would not pose a problem for the asymmetry (Arrhenius 2009, p. 308). This is sometimes the right move to make, but it strikes me as implausible in the example I give here; (3a) and (2) seem like clearly the same alternative, though I cannot here defend a general principle of individuation of alternatives that yields this result. On the other hand, one might reject contraction consistency on the grounds that it rules out the asymmetry, but this strikes me as a bad move in this context.

  9. This argument is sufficiently general that it might apply to the view that the asymmetry is explained by appeal to rights. Such views must appeal to a difference in rights-violations between procreative and individual-affecting decisions; but if there is such a difference, then the relative strengths of two options change depending on the existence of an independent third option.

  10. I prefer not to discuss harm, when possible, because it is not clear to me what harm is. See Bradley (forthcoming).

  11. Holtug argues that it is a good feature of prioritarianism that it implies this moderate asymmetry (Holtug 2010, p. 259).

  12. Note that if we understand the moderate view in this way, it follows that certain ways of analyzing well-being in terms of reasons must be rejected. If the value of something for someone is just the reason we have, for that person’s sake, to promote or prevent it, then if some bit of positive and negative well-being make same-sized but opposite impacts on someone’s well-being, there must be same-sized reasons to promote or prevent them. Perhaps this result could be avoided by distinguishing between different sorts of reasons. Thanks to Justin D’Arms for discussion of this point.

  13. For discussion of this question, see Griffin (1979, p. 53).

  14. Here Shiffrin is distinguishing benefits for already existing people from benefits for people who do not yet, or might not, exist.

  15. For discussion of lexical views and reasons to reject them, see Arrhenius and Bykvist (1995).

  16. This has been widely noticed, but for two recent discussions see Bradley (forthcoming) and Hanser (2008, p. 434).

  17. ‘This’ is ambiguous, but I follow Johansson (2010, p. 286) in taking it to refer to the world of the antecedent, rather than the actual world.

  18. One might think that even if well-being is not intrinsic, it requires the possession of intrinsic properties, even if desire satisfactionism is true, since intrinsic properties are necessary for having desires. This is true, but leaves open the question of when the individual is well- or badly-off in virtue of having those desires. It often seems wrong to say that it is when the desire takes place. (See Bradley 2009, pp. 18–30 for discussion of this and related issues.) In any case, the point about intrinsicness is not to establish that it is possible to have well-being at a world at which one never exists, but to forestall a possible argument against that possibility. Thanks to Jens Johansson for discussion of this point.

  19. As Broome argues, it is possible to treat goodness for a person, or well-being, as “a relation that the person has to a history, rather than as a property she has in a history” (Broome 2004, pp. 63–64). Nevertheless, for reasons that are unclear to me, Broome chooses to think of well-being as a property a person has, and he thus claims that “a history in which a person does not exist is neither better nor worse for her than any other history… the person’s value function will not assign any value to a history in which the person does not exist” (Broome 2004, p. 65).

  20. See Arrhenius (2009, p. 299) for a similar thought.

References

  • Arrhenius, G. 2006. The moral status of potential people. Manuscript.

  • Arrhenius, G. 2009. Can the person affecting restriction solve the problems in population ethics? In Harming future persons: Ethics, genetics and the nonidentity problem, ed. M. Roberts, and D. Wasserman, 291–316. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrhenius, G. 2010. Population ethics: The challenge of future generations. Manuscript.

  • Arrhenius, G., and K. Bykvist. 1995. Future generations and interpersonal compensations: Moral aspects of energy use. Manuscript.

  • Arrhenius, G., and W. Rabinowicz. 2010. Better to be than not to be? In The benefit of broad horizons: Intellectual and institutional preconditions for a global social science (Festschrift for Björn Wittrock on the occasion of his 65th birthday), ed. H. Joas, and B. Klein, 399–414. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benatar, D. 2006. Better never to have been: the harm of coming into existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. 2009. Well-being and death. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. 2010. Benatar and the logic of betterness. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, www.jesp.org.

  • Bradley, B. (forthcoming). Doing away with harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Broome, J. 1991. Weighing goods. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. 2004. Weighing lives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bykvist, K. 2007. The benefits of coming into existence. Philosophical Studies 135: 335–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. 1992. Confrontations with the reaper. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, J. 1979. Is unhappiness morally more important than happiness? The Philosophical Quarterly 29: 47–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanser, M. 2008. The metaphysics of harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 421–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. 2004. Can we harm and benefit in creating? Philosophical Perspectives 18: 89–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holtug, N. 2010. Persons, interests, and justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, J. 2010. Being and betterness. Utilitas 22: 285–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. 2009. The philosophy of death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. 2009. Asymmetries in the morality of causing people to exist. In Harming future persons: Ethics, genetics and the nonidentity problem, ed. M. Roberts, and D. Wasserman, 49–68. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Narveson, J. 1967. Utilitarianism and new generations. Mind 76: 62–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, M. 2007. Choosing and describing: Sen and the irrelevance of independence alternatives. Theory and Decision 63: 79–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, I. 2009. Rights and the asymmetry between creating good and bad lives. In Harming future persons, ed. M. Roberts, and D. Wasserman, 29–47. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. 1966. The open society and its enemies: The spell of Plato, vol. 1, 5th ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, M. 2003. Can it ever be better never to have existed at all? Person-based consequentialism and a new repugnant conclusion. Journal of Applied Philosophy 20: 159–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 2002. Rationality and freedom. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, S. 1999. Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm. Legal Theory 5: 117–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to the participants at NOISE 2 at Tulane in February 2011 and the Population Ethics workshop at McGill in April 2011. Special thanks to Gustaf Arrhenius, Ralf Bader, Elizabeth Brake, Eric Cave, Justin D’Arms, Tyler Doggett, Dale Dorsey, Iwao Hirose, Dan Jacobson, Jens Johansson, Melinda Roberts, David Shoemaker, and Sarah Stroud.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ben Bradley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bradley, B. Asymmetries in Benefiting, Harming and Creating. J Ethics 17, 37–49 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-012-9134-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-012-9134-6

Keywords

Navigation