Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

Blockage revision is a version of descriptor revision, i.e. belief change in which a belief set K is changed with inputs whose success conditions are metalinguistic expressions containing the belief predicate \(\mathfrak {B}\). This is a highly general framework that allows a single revision operator \(\circ \) to take inputs corresponding to sentential revision (\(K\circ \mathfrak {B}p\)), contraction (\(K\circ \lnot \mathfrak {B}p\)) as well as more complex and composite operations. In blockage revision, such an operation is based on a relation \(\rightharpoondown \) of blockage among the set of potential outcomes. \(X\rightharpoondown Y\) signifies that if X satisfies the success condition of a belief change, then Y cannot be its outcome. The properties of blockage revision are investigated, and conditions on the blocking relation are specified that characterize various properties of the resulting operation of change.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A finite composite descriptor can be replaced by the molecular descriptor that is the conjunction of all its elements. However, an infinite composite descriptor cannot in general be replaced by a single molecular descriptor.

  2. Descriptor disjunction will be used in Observation 3 and the discussion following it.

  3. I.e. \( \widehat{C}(\mathbb {Y})\in \mathbb {Y}\) whenever \(\mathbb {Y}\ne \varnothing \).

  4. Blockage relations were first introduced in Hansoon (2013b) where they were used to construct a contraction operator.

  5. Cf. Hansoon (2013b, pp. 418–419) and Rott (2014).

  6. Two different monoselective descriptor revisions \(\circ \) and \(\circ '\) may give rise to the same blockage relation. Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y,Z,W\}\), and let \(\circ \) be based on a monoselective choice function \(\widehat{C}\) such that \(\widehat{C}(\mathbb {Y})=K\) whenever \(K\in \mathbb {Y}\subseteq \mathbb {X}\) and that \(\widehat{C}(\{X,Y\})=X, \widehat{C}(\{X,Z\})=Z, \widehat{C}(\{X,W\})=X, \widehat{C}(\{Y,Z\})=Y, \widehat{C}(\{Y,W\})=W, \widehat{C}(\{Z,W\})=Z, \widehat{C}(\{X,Y,Z\})=X, \widehat{C}(\{X,Z,W\})=W, \widehat{C}(\{Y,Z,W\})=Z, \widehat{C}(\{X,Y,W\})=W\), and \(\widehat{C}(\{X,Y,Z,W\})=Y\). Furthermore, let \(\widehat{C}'\) coincide with \(\widehat{C}'\) with the sole exception that \(\widehat{C}'(\{X,Y\})=Y\), and let \(\circ '\) be based on \(\widehat{C}'\). Then \(\circ \) and \(\circ '\) give rise to the same blockage relation namely \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle K,X,\rangle ,\langle K,Y\rangle ,\langle K,Z\rangle , \langle K,W\rangle \}\). However, let \(\Psi \) be a descriptor that is satisfied by X and Y but not by KZ, or W. Then \(K\circ \Psi =X\) and \(K\circ '\Psi =Y\).

  7. The sentential version of cumulativity seems to have appeared in the belief revision literature for the first time in Makinson and Gärdenfors (1991, p. 198). It has often been divided into two parts, “If \(K*p\vdash q\) then \( K*p\subseteq K*(p \& q)\)” and “If \(K*p\vdash q\) then \( K*(p \& q)\subseteq K*p\)” that are called cautious monotony respectively cut, due to their close relationships with patterns of nonmonotonic reasoning with the same names (Rott 1992, p. 49). On these postulates, see also Rott (2001). Disjunctive identity does not seem to have been referred to in the belief revision literature, but it is a trivial consequence of the postulate of disjunctive factoring (Either \(K*(p\vee q)=K*p\) or \(K*(p\vee q)=K*q\) or \(K*(p\vee q)=K*p\cap K*q\)) that holds for transitively relational AGM revision. (Disjunctive factoring was proved by Hans Rott and first reported in Gärdenfors (1988, pp. 57, 212, and 244).)

  8. This follows from Theorem 3 and Observation 5.

  9. Reciprocity seems to have been introduced independently in Alchourrón and Makinson (1982, p. 32) and Gärdenfors (1982, p. 97). It has been further discussed for instance in Makinson (1985, p. 354) where it was called the Stalnaker property, Makinson and Gärdenfors (1991, p. 198), Rott (2001, p. 110), and Rott (2014).

  10. This applies in particular to the success conditions for contraction and sentential revision that can be translated into \(K\circ \lnot \mathfrak {B}p\Vdash \lnot \mathfrak {B}p\) respectively \(K\circ \mathfrak {B}p\Vdash \mathfrak {B}p\). It also applies to the recovery postulate for contraction that can be translated into \((K\circ \lnot \mathfrak {B}p)\circ \mathfrak {B}p\subseteq K\) and to the vacuity property for sentential revision that can be translated into: If \(K\nVdash \mathfrak {B}\lnot p\) then \(K\circ \mathfrak {B}p=\mathrm {Cn}(K\cup \{p\})\).

References

  • Alchourrón, C. E., & Makinson, D. (1982). On the logic of theory change: Contraction functions and their associated revision functions. Theoria, 48, 14–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1982). Rules for rational changes of belief. In T. Pauli (Ed.), Philosophical essays dedicated to Lennart Åqvist on his fiftieth birthday (pp. 88–101). Uppsala: Department of Philosophy, Uppsala University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux: Modeling the dynamics of epistemic states. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2013a). Outcome level analysis of belief contraction. Review of Symbolic Logic, 6, 183–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2013b). Blockage contraction. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 415–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2014a). Descriptor revision. Studia Logica, 102, 955–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2014b). Relations of epistemic proximity for belief change. Artificial Intelligence, 217, 76–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (1985). How to give it up: A survey of some formal aspects of the logic of theory change. Synthese, 62, 347–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D., & Gärdenfors, P. (1991). Relations between the logic of theory change and nonmonotonic logic. In A. Fuhrmann & M. Morreau (Eds.), The logic of theory change. Lecture notes in computer science (Vol. 465, pp. 185–205). Berlin: Springer.

  • Rott, H. (1992). Preferential belief change using generalized epistemic entrenchment. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, 1, 45–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rott, H. (2001). Change, choice and inference: A study of belief revision and nonmonotonic reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rott, H. (2014). Four floors for the theory of theory change: The case of imperfect discrimination. In E. Fermé & J. Leite (Eds.), JELIA 2014. Lecture notes of artificial intelligence, (vol. 8761, pp. 368–382) Berlin: Springer.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sven Ove Hansson.

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

Definition 2

(Hansson 2014a) For any belief set X, we denote by \(\Pi _X\) the descriptor \(\{\mathfrak {B}p \mid p \in X\} \cup \{\lnot \mathfrak {B}p \mid p \notin X\}\).

Definition 3

For any set \(\mathbb {X}\) of belief sets and any descriptor \(\Psi \):

$$\begin{aligned} \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket _\mathbb {X}=\{X\in \mathbb {X}\mid X\Vdash \Psi \}. \end{aligned}$$

The index can be omitted if no ambiguity follows from doing so, i.e. we can then write \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) instead of \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket _\mathbb {X}\).

Lemma 1

If a binary relation satisfies non-occlusion then it satisfies acyclicity. If it satisfies acyclicity then it satisfies asymmetry. If it satisfies asymmetry then it satisfies irreflexivity.

Proof of Lemma 1:

Left to the reader. \(\square \)

Lemma 2

\(K \Vdash \Psi \veebar \Xi \) holds if and only if either \(K \Vdash \Psi \) or \(K \Vdash \Xi \) holds.

Proof of Lemma 2:

See Hansson (2014b, p. 85). \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 1:

For one direction, let \(K\in \mathbb {X}\) and let \(\rightharpoondown \) satisfy irreflexivity within \(\mathbb {X}\setminus \{K\}\). It follows directly from \(K\in \mathbb {X}\) and Definition 1 that the outcome set is a subset of \(\mathbb {X}\). We also have to show that each element of \(\mathbb {X}\) is an element of the outcome set. For each \(X\in \mathbb {X}\setminus \{K\}\), \(\{X\}\) is the set of \(\Pi _X\)-satisfying elements of \(\mathbb {X}\), and due to the irreflexivity of \(\rightharpoondown , X\) is the unique unblocked element of \(\{X\}\), thus \(K\circ \Pi _X=X\). Furthermore, \(K=K\circ \lnot \mathfrak {B}{\scriptstyle \top }\) (where \({\scriptstyle \top }\) is a tautology) due to clause (ii) of Definition 1. Thus all elements of \(\mathbb {X}\) are elements of the outcome set.

For the other direction, we assume that either (i) \(K\notin \mathbb {X}\) or (ii) \(X\rightharpoondown X\) for some \(X\in \mathbb {X}\setminus \{K\}\). In the first case it follows from \(K\circ \lnot \mathfrak {B}{\scriptstyle \top }=K\) that the outcome set has an element that is not in \(\mathbb {X}\). In the second case \(K\circ \Psi \ne X\) for all \(\Psi \), thus X is not in the outcome set although it is in \(\mathbb {X}\). \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 2:

Part 1: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and:

$$\begin{aligned} \rightharpoondown =\{\langle K,X\rangle ,\langle K,Y\rangle ,\langle X,Y\rangle ,\langle Y,X\rangle \}. \end{aligned}$$

Then \(K\circ \Pi _X\Vdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\) but \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\nVdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\).

Part 2: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle K,X\rangle ,\langle X,Y\rangle ,\langle Y,K\rangle \}\). Then \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)=K\) and \(K\circ ((\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\cup (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y))=K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y)=Y\), thus \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y\) but \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\ne K\circ ((\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\cup (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y))\).

Part 3: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle K,X\rangle ,\langle X,Y\rangle ,\langle Y,K\rangle \}\). Then \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y\) and \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\) but \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\ne K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y)\).

Part 4: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X\}\) and let \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle X,K\rangle \}\). Then \(K\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\) but \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X)=X\). \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 3:

Part 1, peripheral cumulativity: Let \(K\circ \Psi \ne K\ne K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\) and \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Xi \). It follows from Definition 1 and \(K\ne K\circ \Psi \) that \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \), thus \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \cup \Xi \), i.e. \(K\circ \Psi \in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \). It also follows from \(K\ne K\circ \Psi \) that \(K\circ \Psi \) is unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \), and since \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \subseteq \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) it is then also unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \). Thus \(K\circ \Psi \) is \(\Psi \cup \Xi \)-satisfying and unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \). Since \(K\ne K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\) there is exactly one belief set with that property, namely \(K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\). It follows that \(K\circ \Psi =K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\).

Part 1, peripheral disjunctive identity: Since \(K\ne K\circ \Psi \), all elements of \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \setminus \{K\circ \Psi \}\) are blocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \), and similarly all elements of \(\llbracket \Xi \rrbracket \setminus \{K\circ \Psi \}\) are blocked within \(\llbracket \Xi \rrbracket \). Since \(\llbracket \Psi \veebar \Xi \rrbracket =\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \cup \llbracket \Xi \rrbracket \), all elements of \(\llbracket \Psi \veebar \Xi \rrbracket \setminus \{K\circ \Psi \}\) are blocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \veebar \Xi \rrbracket \). Since \(K\circ \Psi \) is unblocked both within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) and within \(\llbracket \Xi \rrbracket \), it is unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \veebar \Xi \rrbracket \). Thus \(K\circ \Psi \) is the only unblocked element within \(\llbracket \Psi \veebar \Xi \rrbracket \), thus \(K\circ \Psi =K\circ (\Psi \veebar \Xi )\).

Part 2, peripheral cumulativity: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y,Z\}\) and let \(\circ \) be based on a monoselective choice function \(\widehat{C}\) such that \(\widehat{C}(\{X,Y,Z\})=\{Y\}\) and \(\widehat{C}(\{Y,Z\})=\{Z\}\). Then \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z)=Y\) and \(Y\Vdash \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z\) but \(K\circ ((\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z)\cup (\Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z))=K\circ (\Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z)=Z\).

Part 2, peripheral disjunctive identity: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y,Z\}\) and let \(\circ \) be based on a monoselective choice function \(\widehat{C}\) such that \(\widehat{C}(\{X,Y\})=\widehat{C}(\{Y,Z\})=Y\) and \(\widehat{C}(\{X,Y,Z\})=X\). Then \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y) = Y, K\circ (\Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z) = Y\), and \(K\circ ((\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\veebar (\Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z)) = X\). \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 1:

From regularity to peripheral non-occlusion: Let \(K\notin \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) and \(X\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \). Due to Observation 1 and our assumption that \(\rightharpoondown \) is irreflexive there is some \(\Xi \) with \(X=K\circ \Xi \). Then \(K\circ \Xi \Vdash \Psi \) and regularity yields \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \). From this and \(K\circ \Psi \ne K\) it follows according to Definition 1 that \(K\circ \Psi \) is an unblocked element within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \).

From regularity to peripheral weak connectivity: Let \(X, Y \in \mathbb {X}, X\ne Y\) and \(X\ne K\ne Y\). Due to Observation 1 and our assumption that \(\rightharpoondown \) is irreflexive there is some \(\Xi \) with \(X=K\circ \Xi \). Thus \(K\circ \Xi \Vdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\). Regularity yields \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\), thus \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\in \{X,Y\}\), from which it follows that either \(X\rightharpoondown Y\) or \(Y\rightharpoondown X\).

From peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity to regularity: Let \(K\circ \Xi \Vdash \Psi \).

First case, \(K\nVdash \Psi \): Due to peripheral non-occlusion it follows from \(K\circ \Xi \Vdash \Psi \) and \(K\nVdash \Psi \) that \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) has at least one non-blocked element. It follows from peripheral weak connectivity that it has at most one such element. Due to clause (i) of Definition 1, that element is equal to \(K\circ \Psi \), thus \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \).

Second case, \(K\Vdash \Psi \): According to Definition 1, \(K\circ \Psi \) is either an element of \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) or equal to K. In both cases, \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \). \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 4:

For one direction, let \(\circ \) be a monoselective descriptor revision. Then \(\circ \) satisfies regularity, and we can conclude from Theorem 1 that \(\rightharpoondown \) satisfies peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity.

For the other direction, let \(\rightharpoondown \) satisfy peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity, and let \(\circ \) be the revision operator generated from \(\rightharpoondown \). It follows from Theorem 1 that \(\circ \) satisfies regularity. Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{X\mid (\exists \Psi )(X=K\circ \Psi )\}\) and let \(\widehat{C}\) be a function such that (a) when \(\varnothing \ne \mathbb {Y}\subseteq \mathbb {X}\), then \(\widehat{C}(\mathbb {Y})=K\circ \Psi \) for all \(\Psi \) such that \(\{X\mid X\Vdash \Psi \}=\mathbb {Y}\) and (b) otherwise \(\widehat{C}(\mathbb {Y})\) is undefined. We need to show (1) that \(\widehat{C}\) is a monoselective choice function on \(\mathbb {X}\), and (2) that \(\circ \) is the monoselective descriptor revision on \(\mathbb {X}\) that is based on \(\widehat{C}\).

For (1) it is sufficient to show that \(\widehat{C}\) is indeed a function. This can be done by noting that since \(\circ \) is a blockage relation it satisfies the uniformity postulate:

If \(K\circ \Xi \Vdash \Psi \) iff \(K\circ \Xi \Vdash \Psi '\) for all \(\Xi \), then \(K\circ \Psi =K\circ \Psi '\)

For (2) we need to consider the two cases referred to in Sect. 1. In case (i) there is some \(X \in \mathbb {X}\) with \(X \Vdash \Psi \). It follows directly from regularity that \(K\circ \Psi \) is in this case indeed identical to \(\widehat{C}(\{X\in \mathbb {X}\mid X\Vdash \Psi \})\). In case (ii) there is no \(X \in \mathbb {X}\) with \(X \Vdash \Psi \). It follows from Definition 1 that \(K\circ \Psi =K\), as required. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 2:

From cumulativity to peripheral non-occlusion: Suppose to the contrary that \(K\notin \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \ne \varnothing \) and \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) has no unblocked element. Let \(X\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \). Then \(K\circ \Psi =K, K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\), and \(K\circ (\Psi \cup (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X))=K\circ \Pi _X=X\), contrary to cumulativity.

From cumulativity to peripheral weak connectivity: Suppose to the contrary that there are \(X,Y\in \mathbb {X}\) such that \(X\ne Y\ne K\ne X\) and . Then \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)=K\), thus \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y\), but \(K\circ ((\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\cup (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y))=K\circ \Pi _Y=Y\), contrary to cumulativity.

From cumulativity to top adjacency: Let \(\circ \) be a blockage revision based on \(\rightharpoondown \), and furthermore suppose that top adjacency does not hold. We are going to show that cumulativity does not hold. Let \(X,Y\in \mathbb {X}\setminus \{K\}\) and \(X\rightharpoondown Y\rightharpoondown K\). Since top adjacency does not hold, if \(K\rightharpoondown X\) then , and furthermore, if then . We therefore have the following two cases:

Case 1, \(K\rightharpoondown X\) and : Then there is no unblocked element within \(\{K,X,Y\}\) but there is a unique unblocked element within \(\{K,Y\}\), namely Y. It follows that \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)=K\), thus \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y\), but \(K\circ ((\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\cup (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _Y))=Y\), contrary to cumulativity.

Case 2, and : We have \(X\rightharpoondown Y\) and by applying peripheral non-occlusion (that we have just proved) to \(\{X,Y\}\) we obtain . Thus \(\{K,X,Y\}\) has a unique unblocked element namely X, whereas \(\{K,X\}\) has the unblocked elements K and X. It follows that \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)=X\), thus \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\), but \(K\circ ((\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\cup (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X))=K\), contrary to cumulativity.

Thus in both cases, if top adjacency does not hold, then neither does cumulativity.

From peripheral non-occlusion, peripheral weak connectivity, and top adjacency to cumulativity: Let \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Xi \).

Case 1, \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket =\varnothing \): Then \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket =\varnothing \), and we have \(K\circ \Psi =K\) and \(K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )=K\).

Case 2, \(K\notin \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \ne \varnothing \): It follows from peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity that \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) has exactly one unblocked element, and due to Definition 1 that element is equal to \(K\circ \Psi \). It follows that \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \) and we already have \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Xi \), so \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \cup \Xi \). Since \(K\circ \Psi \) is unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \), it is also unblocked within its subset \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \). It follows from \(K\notin \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) and \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \subseteq \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) that \(K\notin \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \). It follows from peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity that \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \) has exactly one unblocked element, and then \(K\circ \Psi \) is that element. Due to Definition 1, \(K\circ \Psi =K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\).

Case 3, \(K\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) and \(K\ne K\circ \Psi \): It follows from Definition 1 that \(K\circ \Psi \) is the unique unblocked element of \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \). Since \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Xi \) we have \(K\circ \Psi \in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \). Since \(K\circ \Psi \) is unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \), it is also unblocked within its subset \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \).

Case 3A, \(K\notin \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \): It follows from peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity that \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \) has exactly one unblocked element, and then \(K\circ \Psi \) is that element. Due to Definition 1, \(K\circ \Psi =K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\).

Case 3B, \(K\in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \): Since \(K\circ \Psi \) is the unique unblocked element of \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \), there is some \(X\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) with \(X\rightharpoondown K\). Since \(K\circ \Psi \) is unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) we also have and . Due to peripheral weak connectivity, \(K\circ \Psi \rightharpoondown X\). We conclude from top adjacency that \(K\circ \Psi \rightharpoondown K\).

Next, let \(Z\in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \setminus \{K,K\circ \Psi \}\). Since \(K\circ \Psi \) is unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \) it follows from peripheral weak connectivity that \(K\circ \Psi \rightharpoondown Z\). Thus \(K\circ \Psi \) is the only unblocked element within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \), thus \(K\circ \Psi =K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\).

Case 4, \(K\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) and \(K=K\circ \Psi \): It follows from \(K\circ \Psi \Vdash \Xi \) that \(K\in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \).

Case 4A, K is unblocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \): If K is the only unblocked element within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \), then \(K=K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\) due to clause (i) of Definition 1. If it is one of at least two unblocked elements within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \), then \(K=K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\) due to clause (ii) of the same definition.

Case 4B, K is blocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \): Due to peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity there is some \(Y\in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \setminus \{K\}\) such that for all \(X\in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \setminus \{K,Y\}\). It follows that \(K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\) is either Y or K. We are going to show that it is not Y. Suppose that it is. Then clearly .

Case 4Ba, : Since K is blocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \) there is then some \(X\in \llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \setminus \{K,Y\}\) such that \(X\rightharpoondown K\). We then have and \(X\rightharpoondown K\), contrary to top adjacency.

Case 4Bb, \(Y\rightharpoondown K\): Due to peripheral non-occlusion and peripheral weak connectivity there is some \(Z\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \setminus \{K\}\) such that for all \(V\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \setminus \{K,Z\}\). Since K is blocked (within \(\llbracket \Psi \cup \Xi \rrbracket \) and therefore also) within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) and \(K\circ \Psi \ne Z, Z\) is blocked within \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \), thus \(K\rightharpoondown Z\). Since by assumption . We then have and \(K\rightharpoondown Z\), contrary to top adjacency.

Thus, in neither subcase can \(K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\) be equal to Y. We can conclude that \(K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )=K\), thus \(K\circ \Psi =K\circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\) in case 4B as well. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 3:

From cumulativity to regularity: Directly from Theorems 1 and 2.

From cumulativity to reciprocity : Let \(K \circ \Psi \Vdash \Xi \) and \(K \circ \Xi \Vdash \Psi \). Then cumulativity yields \(K \circ \Psi = K \circ (\Psi \cup \Xi ) = K \circ \Xi \).

From regularity and reciprocity to cumulativity: Let \(K \circ \Psi \Vdash \Xi \). There are two cases.

Case (i), \(K \circ \Psi \nVdash \Psi \): Regularity yields \(K \circ (\Psi \cup \Xi ) \nVdash \Psi \), thus \(K \circ (\Psi \cup \Xi ) \nVdash \Psi \cup \Xi \). It follows from Definition 1 that \(K \circ \Psi = K = K \circ (\Psi \cup \Xi )\).

Case (ii), \(K \circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \): Then \(K \circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \cup \Xi \). Regularity yields \(K \circ (\Psi \cup \Xi ) \Vdash \Psi \cup \Xi \). We thus have \(K \circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \cup \Xi \) and \(K \circ (\Psi \cup \Xi ) \Vdash \Psi \), and reciprocity yields \(K \circ \Psi = K\circ ( \Psi \cup \Xi )\). \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 5:

Part 1: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle X,Y\rangle , \langle Y,K\rangle \}\). It follows from Theorem 1 that regularity is satisfied. We have \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y) = X\) and \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X)=K\), thus \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\) and \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X)\Vdash \Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\) but \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y) \ne K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X)\), which shows that reciprocity does not hold.

Part 2: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle K,X\rangle , \langle K,Y\rangle \}\). In order to show that reciprocity holds it is sufficient to that there are no \(\Psi \) and \(\Xi \) such that either (1) \(K\circ \Psi =K, K\Vdash \Xi , K\circ \Xi =X\), and \(X\Vdash \Psi \), (2) \(K\circ \Psi =K, K\Vdash \Xi , K\circ \Xi =Y\), and \(Y\Vdash \Psi \), or (3) \(K\circ \Psi =X, X\Vdash \Xi , K\circ \Xi =Y\), and \(Y\Vdash \Psi \).

Suppose that (1) holds. Due to our construction of \(\circ \) it follows from \(K\circ \Xi =X\) that \(X\Vdash \Xi , K\nVdash \Xi \), and \(Y\nVdash \Xi \). But we also have \(K\Vdash \Xi \), thus (1) does not hold. A symmetrical proof shows that (2) does not hold. Suppose that (3) holds. It then follows from \(K\circ \Psi =X\) that \(X\Vdash \Psi , K\nVdash \Psi \), and \(Y\nVdash \Psi \), but we also have \(Y\Vdash \Psi \), so that this case is impossible as well. Thus there are no \(\Psi \) and \(\Xi \) that satisfy either (1), (2), or (3), thus reciprocity holds. It follows from \(K\circ \Pi _X=X, X\Vdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\), and \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)=K\) that regularity does not hold. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 4:

From confirmation to near-superiority: Let \(X\rightharpoondown K\). Confirmation yields \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X)=K\), which would not be the case if . Thus \(K\rightharpoondown X\).

If also follows from confirmation that \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)=K\). Since \(X\rightharpoondown K, K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)\) cannot follow from clause (i) of Definition 1, so it must be based on clause (ii). We already have \(K\rightharpoondown X\), thus Y must be blocked by either K or X.

From near-superiority to confirmation: Let \(K\Vdash \Psi \). If \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) does not have exactly one unblocked element, then clause (ii) of Definition 1 yields \(K\circ \Psi =K\). It remains to treat the case when \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) has exactly one unblocked element. Suppose that element is not K. Then there is some \(X\in \llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) with \(X\rightharpoondown K\). It follows from near-superiority that all elements of \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) are blocked (either by K or by X). This contradicts the assumption that the only unblocked element of \(\llbracket \Psi \rrbracket \) is not K. We conclude that it is K and that therefore \(K\circ \Psi =K\) in this case as well. \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 6:

Parts 1 and 2 are left to the reader.

Part 3: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle X,Y\rangle , \langle X,K\rangle , \langle Y,K\rangle \}\).

Part 4: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle X,Y\rangle , \langle Y,X\rangle , \langle Y,K\rangle , \langle K,Y\rangle \}\).

Proof of Observation 7:

Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle X,Y\rangle , \langle X,K\rangle , \langle Y,K\rangle \}\). It follows from Theorem 2 that \(\circ \) satisfies cumulativity and from \(K\circ (\Pi _K\veebar \Pi _X)=X\) that it does not satisfy confirmation. \(\square \)

Proof of Observation 8:

Part 1: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y\}\) and \(\rightharpoondown =\{\langle K,X\rangle , \langle K,Y\rangle \}\). It follows from Theorem 4 that \(\circ \) satisfies confirmation and from \(K\circ \Pi _X=X, X\Vdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\), and \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y)=K\) that it does not satisfy regularity.

Part 2: Let \(\mathbb {X}=\{K,X,Y,Z,V\}\) and:

$$\begin{aligned} \rightharpoondown =\{\langle K,X\rangle , \langle K,Y\rangle , \langle K,Z\rangle , \langle K,V\rangle ,\langle X,Z\rangle ,\langle Z,Y\rangle ,\langle Y,V\rangle ,\langle V,X\rangle \}. \end{aligned}$$

It follows from Theorem 4 that \(\circ \) satisfies confirmation. However, \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z)=X\) and \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _V)=Y\). Since \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z)\Vdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _V\) and \(K\circ (\Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _V)\Vdash \Pi _X\veebar \Pi _Y\veebar \Pi _Z\), it follows that reciprocity is not satisfied. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 5:

From relational revision to blockage revision: Let \(\rightharpoondown \) be the strict part of \(\leqq \). Note that near-superiority and top adjacency are satisfied vacuously. (Since \(\leqq \) is antisymmetric, \(\rightharpoondown \) is irreflexive. Since it also has the property that \(K\leqq X\) for all \(X\in \mathbb {X}\), there is no X with \(X\rightharpoondown K\).)

From blockage revision to relational revision: It was shown in Hansson (2014a) that \(\circ \) is a relational descriptor revision if it satisfies extensionality (If \(\Psi \dashv \Vdash \Psi '\) then \(K \circ \Psi = K \circ \Psi '\)), closure (\(K\circ \Psi = \mathrm {Cn}(K\circ \Psi )\)), relative success (\(K \circ \Psi \Vdash \Psi \) or \(K \circ \Psi = K\)), regularity, cumulativity, and confirmation. It follows straight-forwardly from Definition 1 that the first three of these conditions are satisfied. That the last three are satisfied follows from Theorems 1, 2, and 4. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hansson, S.O. Blockage Revision. J of Log Lang and Inf 25, 37–50 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-015-9223-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-015-9223-6

Keywords

Navigation