Skip to main content
Log in

Kant, Richter and the a priori representations of Anfangsgründe der Stöchiometrie

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The chemist Jeremias Benjamin Richter (1762–1807) coined the term “stoichiometry” and proposed the “law of definite proportions.” He is also commonly acknowledged as having been a student of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804). This paper demonstrates how Kant’s philosophy positively shaped Richter’s approach to chemistry in the Anfangsgründe der Stöchiometrie (1792–1794) and outlines two ways in which Richter attempted to represent the chemical force in “pure intuition”: (1) “reductionistic forces,” in which qualitative features scale with the quantity of matter; and (2) generalized “abstracted forces,” in which a plurality of dissolution- and bonding-properties are latent within the chemical in the manifold of space-time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The book Grundriss der Experimentalchemie appeared in 1787 while Richter was a student at Königsberg. Snelders (1978, 8) contends that Richter had studied this book. A reference to Hagen’s experiments can be found in Richter (1793b, 224). It is uncertain, however, as to whether Richter attended his course, since Löwig (1874, 52) noted that: “According to the personnel files, as already noted, he occupied himself with philosophical and mathematical sciences; According to his own statements, he has not heard any chemical lectures.”

  2. As given in Löwig (1874, 46): “Theses philosophicae ad ampliandam disputationis materiam: 1) Non datur universale criterium veritatis materiale, sed tantum formale. 2) Phaenomena tantum sed non Noumena cognita habemus. 3) Animi substantia realis et immortalitas non demonstrari potest. 4) Initium et aeternitas mundi demonstrari nequit. 5) Animi libertas est assumenda sed non demonstranda. 6) Physicotheologiae probationes de existentia Dei nituntur probatione Cosmotheologiae, de qua probatione rursus ratio in Ontotheologia quaerenda est, quae, autem omnino non valet. Plura demonstrationis genera nisi haec tria non inveniuntur.”

  3. N.B. page numbers refer to the 1781/1922 (A) edition. These similarities suggest that Richter owned a copy of this text.

  4. Richter’s works have never been translated into English. The German texts can be accessed online. Richter 1792: https://books.google.de/books?id=4e48ZwtNCYEC&printsec=frontcover&hl=de&source=gbs_ge_summary_r&cad=0#v=onepage&q&f=false;

    Richter 1793a: https://www.google.com/books/edition/Anfangsgründe_der_Stöchyometrie/LusTAAAAQAAJ?hl=en&sa=X&ved=2ahUKEwju7uSB08b2AhWilGoFHek-B_UQiqUDegQIEBAG;

    Richter 1793b:

    https://www.google.com/books/edition/Ueber_die_neuern_Gegenstände_der_Chymie/R7s5AAAAcAAJ?hl=en&gbpv=0

  5. This reductionistic approach to the Kantian categories has been similarly noted by the twentieth century philosopher René Guénon (1886–1951) in the text The Reign of Quantity and The Signs of the Times (1945): “Here a new confusion makes it appearance: modern physicists, in their efforts to reduce quality to quantity, have arrived by a sort of ‘logic of error’ to the point of confusing the two, and thence to the attribution of quality itself to their ‘matter’ as such; and they end by assigning all reality to ‘matter,’ or at least all that they are capable of recognizing as reality: and it is this that constitutes ‘materialism’ properly so called” (Guénon 1945/2001, 19).

References

  • Blomme, Henny. 2015. Kant’s Conception of Chemistry in the Danziger Physik. In Reading Kant’s Lectures, ed. Robert Clewis, 484–504. Berlin: De Gruyter Press. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110345339.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bloxam, Charles L. 1867. Chemistry: Inorganic and Organic. London: John Churchill & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, Martin. 2001. Kant’s Theory of Matter and his Views on Chemistry. In Kant and the Sciences, ed. Eric Watkins, 205–230. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Hasok. 2010. The Hidden History of Phlogiston. HYLE–International Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry 16 (2): 47–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, Kuno. 1866. A Commentary on Kant’s Critick of the Pure Reason, trans. John Mahaffy. London: Longmans, Green, & Company.

  • Förster, Eckart, and Michael Rosen (eds. and trans.). 1995. Kant’s Opus postumum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Friedman, Michael. 2007. Kant—Naturphilosophie—Electromagnetism. In Hans Christian Ørsted and the Romantic Legacy in Science, eds. Robert Brain, Robert Cohen, and Ole Knudsen., 135–158. Dordrecht: Springer Press. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-2987-5_8.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael. 2013. Kant’s Construction of Nature: A Reading of the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fruton, Joseph S. 2002. Methods and Styles in the Development of Chemistry. v.245. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, Frederick. 2006. Extending Kant: The Origins and Nature of Jakob Friedrich Fries’s Philosophy of Science. In The Kantian Legacy in Nineteenth-century Science, eds. Michael Friedmann and Alfred Nordmann,, 81–100. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Guénon, René. 1945/2001. The Reign of Quantity and the Signs of the Times, trans. Lord Northbourne, ed. James R. Wetmore. 4th, rev. ed. Hillsday, NY: Sophia Perennis.

  • Heinig, Karl. 1975. Immanuel Kant und die Chemie des 18. Jahrhunderts (in der Darstellung der Wissenschaftsgeschichte). Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift der Humboldt-universität zu Berlin Gesellschafts und Sprachwissenschaftliche Reihe 24 (2): 191–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hess, Germain Henri. 1842. On the Scientific Labours of Jeremias Benjamin Richter. The London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science 21 (136): 81–96. https://doi.org/10.1080/14786444208621491.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1781/1922. Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Max Müller. London: MacMillan & Company.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1790/1931. Critique of Judgment, trans. John Bernard. London: MacMillan & Company.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 2002a. Theoretical Philosophy from 1755–1770, trans. eds. David Walford and Ralf Meerbote. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1786/2002b. Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, trans. Henry E. Allison and Peter Heath, eds. Gary Hatfield, Michael Friedman, Henry E. Allison and Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lagerkvist, Ulf. 2012. The Periodic Table and a Missed Nobel Prize, ed. Erling Norrby. 20. Hackensack: World Scientific.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Löwig, Carl. 1874. Jeremias Benjamin Richter: Der Entdecker der Chemischen Proportionen; eine Denkschrift. Breslau: Morgenstern Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahootian, Farzad. 2013. Paneth’s Epistemology of Chemical Elements in light of Kant’s Opus postumum. Foundations of chemistry 15 (2): 171–184. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-013-9182-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNulty, Michael B. 2014. Kant on Chemistry and the Application of Mathematics in Natural Science. Kantian Review 19 (3): 393–418. https://doi.org/10.1017/S136941541400017X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Richard J., ed. 1943. Gmelin Handbook of Inorganic and Organometallic Chemistry. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michałowska-Kaczmarczyk, Anna, Agustin G. Maria, Asuero, and Tadeusz Michałowski. 2015. Why not Stoichiometry versus Stoichiometry—why not? part I: General Context. Critical Reviews in Analytical Chemistry 45 (2): 166–188. https://doi.org/10.1080/10408347.2014.937852.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naragon, Steve. 2006. Kant’s Physics Notes. Manchester University. https://users.manchester.edu/facstaff/ssnaragon/kant/notes/notesPhysics.htm.

  • Onof, Christian. 2015. Kant’s Lectures on Physics and the Development of the Critical Philosophy. In Reading Kant’s Lectures, ed. Robert Clewis, 461–483. Berlin: De Gruyter Press. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110345339.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Psarros, Nikos. 2008. Die Chemie und ihre Methoden: Eine Philosophiche Betrachtung. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pulte, Helmut. 2006. Kant, Fries and the Expanding Universe of Science. In The Kantian Legacy in Nineteenth-century Science, eds. Michael Friedman and Alfred Nordmann, 101–122. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Richter, Jeremias B. 1792. Anfangsgründe der Stöchiometrie oder Meßkunst Chymischer Elemente, v.1. Breßlau und Sitschberg: Korn Publishers.

  • Richter, Jeremias B. 1793a. Anfangsgründe der Stöchiometrie oder Meßkunst Chymischer Elemente. v.2. Breßlau und Sitschberg: Korn Publishers.

  • Richter, Jeremias B. 1793b. Ueber die Neuern Gegenstände der Chymie. Breslau and Hirschberg: Korn Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rocke, Alan J. 1979. The Reception of Chemical Atomism in Germany. Isis 70 (4): 519–536. https://doi.org/10.1086/352339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulting, Dennis. 2015. Transcendental Apperception and Consciousness in Kant's Lectures on Metaphysics. In Reading Kant's Lectures, ed. Robert R. Clewis, 89–113. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter.

  • Shanahan, Timothy. 1989. Kant, Naturphilosophie, and Oersted’s Discovery of Electromagnetism: A Reassessment. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (3): 287–305. https://doi.org/10.1016/0039-3681(89)90009-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schummer, Joachim. 2012. Why Mathematical Chemistry cannot copy Mathematical Physics and how to avoid the Imminent Epistemological Pitfalls. HYLE–International Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry 18 (1): 71–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snelders, Henricus. 1978. Jeremias Benjamin Richter en Immanuel Kant. Gewina: Tijdschrift voor de Geschiedenis der Geneeskunde Natuurwetenschappen Wiskunde en Techniek 1: 3–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snelders, Henricus. 1981. Jeremias Benjamin Richter. In Dictionary of Scientific Biography, ed. Charles C. Gillispie, v.11, 434–438. New York: American Council of Learned Societies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strömdahl, H. R. 1999. On Mole and Amount of Substance: A Study of the Dynamics of Concept Formation and Concept Attainment. Goteborg: Acta Universitatis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabadvary, Ferenc. 1962. The Birth of Stoichiometry. Journal of Chemical Education 39 (5): 267–270. https://doi.org/10.1021/ed039p267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szabadváry, Ferenc. 1977. From Assaying to Analytical Chemistry: How an Art became a Science. Periodica Polytechnica Chemical Engineering 21 (4): 355–369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Brakel, Jaap. 2006. Kant’s Legacy for the Philosophy of Chemistry. In Philosophy of Chemistry: Synthesis of a New Discipline, eds. Davis Baird, Eric R. Scerri, and C. Lee, and McIntyre, 69–91. Dordrecht: Springer Press. https://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-3261-7_4.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Verbruggen, F. 1972. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) en de Scheikunde op het einde van de Achttiende Eeuw. Scientiarum Historia: Tijdschrift voor de Geschiedenis van de Wetenschappen en de Geneeskunde 14 (1): 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Spronsen, J. W. 1969. The Periodic System of Chemical Elements: A History of the First Hundred Years. New York: Elsevier Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, William. 1874. History of the Inductive Sciences. New York: D. Appleton Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to acknowledge Joachim Schummer for helpful feedback on an earlier version of this paper submitted to HYLE, as well as the constructive criticisms provided by two anonymous reviewers. Additionally, he wishes to thank Tilman Schmidt of Ruhr–Universität Bochum for a thorough review of the supplemental material. Further thanks must be added for the instructive suggestions provided by Dr. Helmut Pulte on Kant’s distinction between constitutive and regulative principles.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ryan L Vilbig.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary Material 1

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vilbig, R. Kant, Richter and the a priori representations of Anfangsgründe der Stöchiometrie. J Gen Philos Sci 55, 95–111 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-022-09626-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-022-09626-1

Keywords

Navigation