In the first two parts of the present project (P1&P2), in compliance with ‘Navya-Nyāya Formal Language’ (NL; cf. Anrò 2022), the necessary logical foundations have been laid down in order to carry out the analysis of the section of Vācaspati Miśra’s (VM) Bhāmatī (VM-B) that Bhāskararāya, in his Prakāśa auto-commentary to Varivasyārahasya, calls hāṭaka-makuṭa-grantha (‘The golden crown section’; cf. P1. fn.1, 10; and VVR-P 3, 2000, p. 5). The pivotal role played by the notion of coreferentiality (sāmānādhikaraṇya; ) in defining the relation of non-difference (abheda; ) has been also shown. This latter, in turn, can never be reduced to equivalence (tulyatva; E), equality (samaniyatatva; Q), or identity (I), sensu stricto. In this third part the issue concerning permanence, transformation and difference is tackled. A new translation of VM-B is proposed and framed with the intention of highlighting its argumentative structure, expanding the logical and onto-gnoseological aspects there implied. NL formulae, for their part, could be considered as a form of translation themselves. The numbering of these formulae will refer to the first two parts of this project. Regarding, on the one hand, the relation between Navya-Nyāya (NN) and NL as hermeneutical devices, and, on the other, the relation between NL and VM’s vedāntin account as object of the former, refer to P1 & P2 and (Anrò 2022).

Existence and Temporality (1)

VM opens his reasoning with the claim that there is talk of “two kinds of permanence (nityatā): immutable (kūṭastha) one and permanence of ‘what transforms’ (pariṇāmin)”, just to immediately state that this latter cannot be said to be ultimately real (pāramārthika). How and why does VM come to this conclusion? Most importantly, what is its overall purport? VM’s strategy is sharp and lucid. In the hypothesis, he first asks, transformation would take place:

“in which manner [would it do]? In whole (sarvātman) or in part (ekadeśa)? [a] In the case of a transformation in toto, how [could] it not [generate a] contradiction (vyāhati) with ‘what [this transforming whole is supposed] to be’ (tattva) (cf. §2.1)? [b] [Otherwise], in the case of a partial transformation [only], is [this evolving] part distinct (bhinna) or non-distinct (abhinna) from that [which, on the contrary, in toto does not evolve]? If there would be a distinction, how [could] the transformation of that [subject which in toto does not evolve and which is distinct from what evolves, be possibly conceived]? When [something] distinct (anya) is transforming, [everything else, qua] other (anya) [from the former, undoubtedly] does not transform, lest [an undue] ‘over-application’ (atiprasaṅga) [of the concept of transformation be erroneously performed] (cf. §2.2.1). Or, given the case of non-distinction, how [to avoid falling back into the situation of] a transformation in whole (cf. [a] and § 2.2.2)?Footnote 1

For the purpose of clarification of VM’s implicit premises, let us first consider the primitive property, sattā (Being; st) as the most comprehensive genus (jāti).Footnote 2 By the Axiom of Possession (TvN, Tad-vattva-Nyāya; cf. P1.§3), ‘What is’ is forcefully an occurrence of sattā, since ‘What is not’ is conversely different from ‘What is [generically] in possession of Being’: asat sattāvadbhinnam (NK, p. 102). This perspective assumes tonality of more complexity in considering existence (astitva) as the relation between sattā and temporality (kālatva; tt). Indeed, what exists is an occurrence of the Being property in relation to time (kālatvāvacchinna-sattā: ttst), whereas what does not exist has no relation with time (kālatvānavacchinna-sattā: ∄(ttst)). Consequently, a particular qualified cognition (viśiṣṭa-jñāna, V; P1.§§3-4) such as the following will be generated: t1s1, i.e., ‘A generic being s1 (for s1|st|=S) is limited by a particular temporal coordinate t1 (for t1|tt|=T)’. This assertion is assumed to be true due to the fact that s1 is said to be actually in relation to time t1.Footnote 3 Conversely, the analogous assertion *t2s1 is false (*), because s1, existing at time t1, does not exist any longer at time t2 (i.e., s1 has no relationship with t2).Footnote 4 Conceived as proper cases of determined cognition, the reciprocal articulations of these terms may thus give rise to five fundamental alternatives.

First Configuration: A Temporal Being in a Potentially Empty Time (1.1)

According to this first hypothesis, every instance of the Being property (sattā) would always occur in time, which, however, does not always concern beings. Therefore, in this case, sattāṃ kālatvaṃ vyāpnoti, or ‘Temporality pervades Being’.

*[35] stV−1tt

yā sattāvacchedakāvacchinna-viśeṣyatā sā kālatva-nirūpitā; ‘The relational abstract qualified-ness, conditioned by temporality, is limited by Being’; whose purport (tātparya, (t)) is: (t)Being is always qualified by temporality; yet, there is a temporality independent from Being; that is, a sort of empty time’. Iff |st||V−1tt|; i.e., ‘The set Being (|st|=S) is a subset of What temporality (|tt|=T) qualifies (V)’; in standard notation (s.n.) (~∀x, ∀y | ~Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈ V). Regarding the reasons for its falsity (*), as well as of *[36], *[37] and *[38], see infra §2.

Second Configuration: A Temporal Being in a Never-Empty Time (1.2)

In this case, every being is necessarily in time. In parallel, temporality makes sense only if applied to beings. In other words, all beings (here, strictly speaking, existences) are always described in terms of temporality, and time is, likewise, always defined by events concerning those same existences. Indeed, what distinguishes instant t1 from t2? The fact that in t1 the state of affairs s1 is given, while s2 is given in t2. If time and events are mutually dependent, then nothing permanent exists, since everything is in time; in parallel, there is time only in relation to beings. In this case, there would be a mutual pervasion (samavyāpti) between Being and Temporality: sattākālatvayoḥ samavyāptiḥ. Thereby:

*[36] ttVst

yathā yā kālatva-avacchedakāvacchinna-viśeṣaṇatā sā sattā-nirūpitā, tathā yā sattā-avacchedakāvacchinna-viśeṣyatā sā kālatva-nirūpitā; ‘Just like the relational abstract qualifier-ness, conditioned by Being, is limited by temporality’, so the relational abstract qualified-ness, conditioned by temporality, is limited by Being’; that is, (t)‘Temporality qualifies some occurrences of Being’ and ‘Being is qualified by certain temporal determinations’; iff (ttVst) ∧ (stV−1tt), i.e., (|tt||Vst|) ∧ (|st||V−1tt|); therefore, (|tt|=|Vst|) ∧ (|st|=|V−1tt|), since in general if A⊆B and B⊆A, then A=B. In other words, ‘The set Temporality is coextensive with What qualifies Being’ and ‘The set Being is coextensive with What temporality qualifies’. In n.s. (∀x, ∀y | Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈V).

Third Configuration: A Potentially Atemporal Being in Relation with a Potentially Empty Time (1.3)

In this case, combining and widening the first two configurations, there would be existences in time, beings out of time, as well as an empty time without events.

*[37] tVst

yathā yā tat-kāla-niṣṭha-viśeṣaṇatā sā sattā-nirūpitā, tathā yā tad-vastu-viśeṣa-niṣṭha-viśeṣyatā sā kālatva-nirūpitā; ‘Just like the relational abstract qualifier-ness, conditioned by Being, is limited at least by one temporal determination, so the relational abstract qualified-ness, conditioned by temporality, is limited at least by one occurrence of Being’; that is, (t)‘Some temporal determinations qualify some beings’; iff (t.Vst) ∧ (s.V−1tt); i.e., t|Vst|s|V−1tt|; ergo: |tt||Vst| ≠ ∅ ∧ |st||V−1tt| ≠ ∅, ‘The intersection between Temporality and What qualifies Being is not empty, because there is at least one temporal determination qualifying at least one instance of Being’; in parallel, ‘The intersection between Being and What is qualified by temporality is not empty, since there is at least one specimen of Being qualified by temporality’; in s.n. (~∀x, ~∀y | ~Tx, ~Sy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈V). Regarding the term vastu, cf. supra fn. 2.

Fourth Configuration: An Atemporal Being and an Always Empty Time (1.4)

The inevitable consequence of a third hypothesis, according to which the two properties Being and temporality never coincide, would be beings never marked by time and an absurd empty temporality which never concerns ‘what is’, but only ‘what is not’.

*[38] tt−1⌞(Vst)

yā atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā kālatvāvacchinnā sā viśeṣaṇatā-nirūpitā, saiva viśeṣaṇatā sattā-nirūpitā, tadviparyayeṇa ca; ‘Constant absentee-hood, limited by temporality, is conditioned by qualifier-ness, in turn conditioned by Being’, and vice versa (&vv)’; iff |tt|∩|Vst| = ∅, ‘The intersection of Temporality and What qualifies Being is empty’; in s.n. (∀x,y | Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩∉V).

Fifth Configuration: A Potentially Atemporal Being in a Never Empty Time (1.5)

In this case, beings qualified and beings not qualified by time are equally possible; conversely, kālatva is unavoidably a qualification of sattā.

[39] ttVst

yā kālatvāvacchedakāvacchinna-viśeṣaṇatā sā sattā-nirūpitā; ‘The relational abstract qualifier-ness, limited by temporality, is conditioned by Being’, that is, (t)‘Every occurrence of temporality qualifies some, but not all, beings’; iff |tt||Vst|, ‘Temporality is a subset of What qualifies Being’; in s.n. (∀x, ~∀y | Tx, ~Sy) (⟨x, y⟩∈V).

Defining Permanence (2)

In order to decide which of these mutually exclusive configurations is adequate, the notion of permanence, as the starting point of VM’s reasoning, will be questioned. If a generic being s1 is said to be marked by temporality when it is limited or qualified by time t1 (t1s1 or t1Vs1), then the expression of its permanence must consist, as a first step, in the negation of this assertion; that is, ‘s1 is not qualified by t1’. The target of this negation clearly cannot cover only t1, but every possible temporal determination; that is, the whole temporal domain (i.e., (t1, t2, …, tn) ∈ (|tt|=T), or (∀x | Tx)). Consequently, the permanence to which VM is alluding has to be assumed as an indefectible being in the three times (trikāla; past, present, future). To properly express this quantification in NL, temporality (tt) must therefore appear in anuyogin position with respect to the relational abstract qualifier-ness (V). The following provisional formula, limited to s1 only, will be then obtained:

[40] s1 . −1⌞(ttV )

yā atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā tattad-vastu-viśeṣa-niṣṭhā sā viśeṣaṇatā-nirūpitā, saiva viśeṣaṇatā kālatvāvacchinnā; ‘Constant absentee-hood, conditioned by qualifier-ness, in turn limited by temporality, occurs in an instance of Being’; that is, (t)‘A certain being is not qualified or determined by temporality’; iff |tt|∩|Vs1| = ∅, since, s1|ttV |, ‘The intersection between Temporality and What qualifies s1 is empty’, since, ‘s1 does not belong to the set What temporality qualifies’; in s.n. (∀x, ∃y | Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩∉V).

Provisional formula [40] is visibly compatible with *[38], for (∀x, ∀y | Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∉ V). Does this compatibility imply that VM straightforwardly means *[38] here? Not quite. Although at this stage it is still not evident which truth conditions should be accepted, it is crystal clear that hypothesis *[38], expressing a radical separation between the domains Being and Temporality, is far more demanding than [40]. If it is still questionable whether there is a being out of time or faultlessly present in trikāla, it is beyond any doubt that innumerable existences are related to trikāla in a non-indefectible manner. Therefore, the intersection Being-Temporality cannot be said to be empty; ergo, *[38] is false. VM’s issue would not even arise without admitting this entanglement, since it exactly faces the puzzling evidence of beings that, in time, appear and disappear, just because they were not, are, and will not be. This opens up two alternative options: it is possible to accept this appearance, while assuming an Instantaneist Hypothesis (I-Hy); or, along the lines of VM’s analysis, to opt for the opposite account, claiming that no being may simply appear out the blue, but it always owes its existence to something else which somehow already exists.Footnote 5 Once the latter alternative is accepted, either an endless causal chain is supposed—what I call C-Hy, Hypothesis of Continuum—or a perfectly independent and fully indefectible existence has to be admitted, acknowledging a causal infinite regress as a logical fallacy. I call this latter plexus of basic assumptions, the Hypothesis of Permanence (P-Hy). P-Hy describes permanency in its strongest sense as ‘immutability’ (kūṭastha-nityatā). C-Hy, claiming a ‘permanency in transformation’ or the ‘permanency of what transforms’ (pariṇāmi-nityatā), implies instead a form of continuity somehow metaphysically lighter and less committing. Nonetheless, every form of instantaneism (I-Hy), conceived as complete absence of continuity, is dismissed by virtue of C-Hy and P-Hy. This implies that only C-Hy and P-Hy will be considered in VM’s analysis.

Hypothesis of Continuum. Total Transformation (2.1)

How then to decide between C-Hy and P-Hy? Let the first assumption be the hypothesis of continuity or permanence in transformation (C-Hy). This transformation might concern, in a first case, what transforms in its entirety (sarvātman); that is, completely and without residue. The consequence, VM argues, will inevitably be a contradiction (vyāhati) with “what [this transforming whole is supposed] to be” (tattva). Indeed, if s1 completely transforms into s2, the following conditions are necessarily required:

  1. A.

    (s1, s2) ∈ |st|; ‘beings s1 and s2 belong to the set Occurrences of Being (sattā)’, since both are something and not nothing, such as a hare’s horn (śaśaśṛṅga);

  2. B.

    (t1Vs1) ∧ (t2−1⌞(Vs1)); because, s1∈|V−1t1|, but s1∉|V−1t2| (i.e., s1 is qualified by t1, but not by t2; in t2, s1 is no more, having fully transformed into s2);

  3. C.

    (t2Vs2) ∧ (t1−1⌞(Vs2)); because, s2∈|V−1t2|, but s2∉|V−1t1| (i.e., s2 is qualified by t2, but not by t1; in t1, s2 is not yet, s1 not having transformed into s2);

  4. D.

    s1s2; because s1 has fully transformed, without residue, into s2.

Condition D is nonetheless in glaring contradiction with both condition A and, on a more general level, TvN. For a transformation without residue to come about, each and every property must transform, none excluded. Now, s1 is said, at a minimum, to be (for s1∈|st|). Clearly, the transformation would not be total if this property too would not fully undergo this transformation. It follows that *‘s2 must not be a being’ (for *s2∉|st|), which is utterly false, not only because ‘s2 is a being’ (for TvN), but also on the transformative account itself, which otherwise would not accomplish the purpose for which it has been invoked, that is, explaining how a being could convert into another one, e.g., how milk may turn into curd. Undermining the continuity linkage, a transformation of the sarvātman type violates the very basis of C-Hy and reveals itself as a form of unintentional instantaneism. Sarvātmapariṇāma not only allows, but imposes the awkward passage from milk to hare’s horn: tattvavyāhati, in VM’s words (cf. fn. 1). In order to avoid this contradiction, at least the property sattā has thus to be maintained throughout the process (condition A: (s1, s2) ∈|st|). Therefore, the impossible idea of a transformation in toto, without any residue, must be abandoned. Furthermore, also the exclusion of the hypothesis expressed sub *[35] and *[36] inevitably follows. Since this first variant of C-Hy is inadmissible, a sort of continuity has to be admitted; thus, it is false that every specimen of sattā is always and in every aspect determined by kālatva. It is now clearer what the provisional formula [40] has already expressed: |tt|∩|Vs1| = ∅, or (∀x, ∃y | Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩∉V), which is clearly incompatible with *[35], for (~∀x, ∀y | ~Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈V), and *[36], for (∀x, ∀y | Tx, Sy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈V), because there is at least an instance of sattā which is not limited by time.

For the time being, formulae *[37] and [39] are the last two hypothesis still standing. Nevertheless, *[37] tVst simultaneously suggests that there is at least one instance of sattā free from time determinations, as well as a temporality without reference to Being. It follows that:

*[37a] tV\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)

yathā yā tat-kāla-niṣṭha-viśeṣaṇatā sā asattā-nirūpitā, tathā yā tad-avastu-viśeṣa-niṣṭha-viśeṣyatā sā kālatva-nirūpitā; ‘Just as the relational abstract qualifier-ness, conditioned by non-Being (\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)), is limited at least by one temporal determination, so the relational abstract qualified-ness, conditioned by temporality, is limited at least by one occurrence of non-Being’; that is, (t)‘Some temporal determinations qualify some non-beings’; iff |tt||V\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)| ≠ ∅ ∧ |\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)||V−1tt| ≠ ∅ (‘The intersection between the extension of the property temporality and the set Qualifiers of non-Being is not empty, since there is at least one temporal determination qualifying non-Being; in parallel, ‘The intersection between the extension of the property non-Being and the set What temporality qualifies is not empty, since there is at least one specimen of non-Being qualified by temporality); in s.n. (~∀x, ~∀y | ~Tx, ~\(\overline{S}\) y) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈V). Regarding the term avastu, cf. supra fn. 2.

Assertion *[37a] must necessarily result from *[37]; if not—that is, if temporality would not qualify any specimen of non-Being (for |tt||V\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)| = ∅)—formula *[37] would then be reducible to [39], for |tt||Vst|—that is, there are specimen of Being not qualified by temporality, but any temporal coordinates of what is not. Consequently, asserting *[37] would necessarily imply, according to its corollary *[37a], that:

  1. A.

    t1s1, for s1|st|; i.e., ‘s1 is limited by time t1’;

  2. B.

    t2\(\overline{{s}^{2}}\), for \(\overline{{s}^{2}}\) ∈|\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)|; that is ‘A non-being (such as a hare’s horn), occurrence of What is not, is determined by a temporal coordinate’).

Yet, condition B is a flat nonsense, since at time t2 there is no such hare’s horn that could possibly be qualified by it. Ergo, *[37a] is false because it is false that |tt||V\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)| ≠ ∅, since only |tt||V\(\overline{{s}_{t}}\)| = ∅ can be true. It follows that *[37] cannot be true. Consequently, kālatvaṃ sattā vyāpnoti (cf. supra), as expressed in [39], has proven to be the only option not yet contradicted.

Hypothesis of Continuum. Partial Transformation with Distinction (2.2.1)

If transformation cannot be total (cf. § 2.1), VM suggests, it might be only partial. This means that, once transformation in toto has been ruled out, according to the hypothesis of partial transformation (ekadeśa-pariṇāma), a single aspect, at the very least, must persist throughout the process. Now, in the case of partial transformation, VM wonders, is the part in evolution distinct or not distinct from the part that, on the contrary, does not evolve? If there is distinction (bhinnatva) between the part in transformation and the non-evolving part of that subject in partial transformation, which in toto does not evolve, can it be argued that it is that very same non-evolving subject to evolve and not another, since what transforms has been explicitly defined as distinct from what does not?Footnote 6

The hypothesis under examination imposes that s1 possesses at least two aspects or parts, say s1(A) and s1(B). Of this two parts, s1(A) does not evolve, whereas s1(B) is the evolving aspect. The unchanging part s1(A) will remain, by definition, at time t2 identical to what it was at time t1. In NL:

[41] (t2s1(A)) . I ⌞ (t1s1)

yā tatkāla-avacchinna-tadvastv-ekadeśa-niṣṭha-tādātmyatā pūrva-kāla-avacchinna-tad-vastu-nirūpitā; ‘Identity occurs in a single part of a particular being, limited by this particular temporal coordinate and is conditioned by the very same particular being limited by a temporal coordinate preceding the former’; iff t1 ≠ t2 and (t2s1(A)) ∈|I⌞(t1s1)|; i.e., ⟨s1, s1(A)⟩ ∈I (s1 is identical to s1(A)).

The two aspects of s1, s1(A) and s1(B) have been defined to be distinct (bhinna) qua opposite—since, respectively, non-evolving and evolving. How to conceive this distinction? In the light of what precedes (cf. P2.§9), bheda might be usefully reinterpreted, salva veritate, as a generic negation of the relation of coreferentiality (sāmānādhikaraṇya, ). The distinction between s1(A) and s1(B) can therefore be expressed in NL as:

[42] (t2s1(A)) . −1 ⌞ (⌞ (t2s1(B)))

yā tat-kāla-avacchinna-tad-vastv-ekadeśa-niṣṭha-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sā sāmānādhikaraṇyatā-nirūpitā, saiva sāmānādhikaraṇyatā tat-kāla-avacchinnaitad-vastv-ekadeśa-nirūpitā; ‘Constant absentee-hood, conditioned by coreferentiality in turn conditioned by this single part (s1(B)) of a particular being (s1) limited by that temporal coordinate (t2), occurs in that single part (s1(A)) of the [very same] particular being (s1) limited by the [very same] temporal coordinate (t2)’; that is, (t)‘Qua parts of being s1, s1(A) and s1(B) are, at time t2, distinct’; iff (t2s1(A))∉|⌞(t2s1(B))| (i.e., ‘At time t2, part s1(A) of being s1 does not belong to the set What is coreferential to part s1(B) of being s1 at time t2’).

Nevertheless, considering both [41] and [42], it necessarily follows:

[43] (t2s1) . −1⌞ (⌞(t2s1(B)))

yā tat-kāla-avacchinna-tad-vastu-niṣṭha-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sā sāmānādhikaraṇyatā-nirūpitā, saiva sāmānādhikaraṇyatā tat-kāla-avacchinnaitad-vastv-ekadeśa-nirūpitā; ‘Constant absentee-hood, conditioned by coreferentiality, in turn conditioned by this single part (s1(B)) of a particular being (s1) limited by that temporal coordinate (t2), occurs in that [very same] particular being (s1) limited by the [very same] temporal coordinate (t2)’; that is, (t)‘Being s1 and its own part s1(B) are, at time t2, distinct, qua non-coreferential’.

The reason is that, if ⟨s1, s1(A)⟩∈I (i.e., s1 and s1(A) are identical; cf. [41]) and (t2s1(A))∉|⌞(t2s1(B))| (i.e., s1(A) and s1(B) are distinct at time t2; cf. [42]), then (t2⌝ (⟨s1, s1(A)⟩∈I)) ∉|⌞(t2s1(B))| (i.e., s1 and its part s1(A) are both distinct, qua identical, from s1(B) at time t2). Therefore, the transforming part s1(B) turns out to be different, by absence of coreferentiality, from the being which is supposed to transform (i.e., s1). If the transforming being is a distinct being, then the subject of transformation is not transforming, since another thing is been transformed. VM labels this fallacy as ‘over-application’ (atiprasaṅga)Footnote 7 of the concept of transformation, according to which it is first and foremost the subject of transformation to be supposed to transform and not other. It is this clay which may eventually transform into a pot, surely not that horse. By virtue of formulas [41]-[43] the hypothesis of the partial transformation of a distinct aspect also has to be discarded.

Hypothesis of Continuum. Partial Transformation Without Distinction (2.2.2)

Once transformation in toto and partial transformation with distinction have both been excluded, it might be the case of a partial transformation without distinction (abhinna). Yet, if the evolving and non-evolving parts are non-distinct, how to distinguish one from another? The issue is straightforward and the VM’s discussion the most concise. Either there is a distinction between evolving and non-evolving parts, or there is not. If there is a distinction, then there is nothing but partial transformation with distinction (cf. §2.2.1); if there is no distinction, this new solution simply falls back into the previous case of the transformation in toto (cf. §2.1).

Hypothesis of Continuum. Conclusive Refutation (2.3)

VM opens his analysis by laying down the radical alternative between ‘permanency as immutability’ (kūṭastha-nityatā; P-Hy) and ‘permanency in transformation’ (pariṇāmi-nityatā; C-Hy). The third possibility, impermanency tout court (I-Hy), is simply expunged: what is not permanent either is not and never will be, or it owes its existence to what is permanent. In other words, the contrast between permanency and impermanency is only apparent and it has been reduced to the most fundamental one between different forms of permanency. Nevertheless, since permanency in transformation inevitably generates contradictions, all that remains is permanency as immutability of that which, indefectible, never changes.

Difference and Non-difference. The Accepted Assumptions (3)

Since the possibilities of transformation in whole (§2.1) and in part, with (§2.2.1) or without (§2.2.2) distinction, have been definitely excluded, the subject in transformation paradoxically appears to be at once distinct and non-distinct from itself, according to the perspective from which it is observed (cf. infra). Simultaneously, the curd is no more and yet still milk, as well as a bracelet is and is not just gold. In P2 has been argued how, in the case of a golden bracelet, the gold of which the bracelet is made cannot in any manner whatsoever be said equivalent (E), equal (Q) or identical (I) to the bracelet itself. Nonetheless, it is no less true that this specimen of gold and this bracelet, coreferential (samānādhikaraṇa) to the former, are nothing but the very same object. This is the reason why they are said to be, stricto sensu, non-different (abhinna). Reshaping the definition of ‘unit’ as advanced by Gadādhara (1929, p. 167; eka as kaivalya), non-difference (abheda) has been defined in P2.§5 as ‘not being the counterpositive of a difference occurring in another coreferential property’. Regarding the case of a golden bracelet, formula P2.[27] , by virtue of that counterpositive structure (cf. P2.[34]), will therefore appear as:

[44]

yad atyantābhāvīyapratiyogitā-avacchedakāvacchinna-paryāptitvaṃ tad ekatva-nirūpitam; tatra yaiva atyantābhāvīyapratiyogitā hāṭaka-niṣṭha-kaṭaka-nirūpita-sāmānādhikaraṇyatā-avacchedakāvacchinnā sā anyonyābhāvīyapratiyogitā-nirūpitā, eṣaiva anyonyābhāvīyapratiyogitā kaṭaka-nirūpitā; tadviparyayeṇa ca; ‘The relational abstract constant absentee-hood (−1), limited by coreferenceness (), in turn conditioned by a bracelet (b) and occurring in a specimen of gold (h), is conditioned by mutual absentee-hood conditioned by the same bracelet, &vv; for a cardinality equal to one’; iff (i.e., ‘A specimen of gold coreferential to a bracelet does not belong to the set What is different from that bracelet’); that is, (i.e., ‘A specimen of gold belongs to the set What is coreferential to a bracelet’ and ‘The set What is coreferential to a bracelet is not a subset of What is different from that bracelet’), for card{h, b} = 1 (‘The cardinality of the set containing a specimen of gold and a bracelet is equal to one’), and clearly, as a general premise, h ∈(|ht|=H), b ∈(|bt|=B), H∩B ≠ ∅ (respectively: ‘A specimen of gold belongs to the set What is gold, extension of the property gold-ness’, ‘A bracelet belongs to the set Bracelets, extension of the property bracelet-hood’, ‘The intersection of the sets What is gold and Bracelets is not empty’, since at least one golden bracelet exists). Cf. infra §8, for a further discussion.

In the words of VM:

Whether that [subject, which is supposed to be in transformation, and which can yet transform neither in whole nor in part] is [said to be, consequently] distinct and non-distinct (a/bhinna), then, this will be non-distinct qua cause, and distinct qua effect; just as in the case of bracelets (kaṭaka) or other artifacts (ādi), which are non-distinct qua gold, but distinct qua bracelets or other artifacts. Nor [is it correct to say that], by contradiction (virodha) between difference and non-difference, it is not [possible] a relation of inherence (samavāya) in the very same locus (ekatra) [of these two aspects—that is, cause and effect, or gold and bracelet].Footnote 8

Indeed, inherence (samavāya)—reason for the contextual perception (pratyayahetu) of coreferential properties—is defined as the relation which occurs between an inherent (samaveta) and an inhered (samavāyin) qua indivisible (ayutasiddha), as in the examples of the quality and the qualified (a blue pot), the whole and its parts (a pot and its halves), the general kind and the individual (potness and pot), etc.Footnote 9 VM points here to the fact that the peculiar opposition of two distinct properties does not exclude their coreferentiality in singularity (ekatra) via inherence. Following VM, if the relation standing between gold and bracelet cannot unquestionably be reduced to reflexive identity stricto sensu (I; cf. P2 §3), for the time being it stands to reason that it can be described as ‘resembling’ (≅; cf. P2 § 4 and fn. 44) with ‘inherence’, as well as somehow consequently admitting a distinctive, structural, although dangerously paradoxical, ‘compatibility with difference’ (bhedasahiṣṇutva; cf. P2 fn. 58). And yet, one could ask, how is this bizarre juxtaposition conceivable? And where does it originate from?

Difference and Sources of Knowledge (4)

For our part, where [should] the right conception (saṃpratyaya), regarding the opposition (viruddha) [between different properties referring to the very same thing, be retraced]? This [opposition] occurs by reason of the [inevitable] ‘obversion’ (viparyaya) [operated] by the sources of knowledge (pramāṇa). Indeed, just as something is [correctly] understood by means of the [relative] source of knowledge, so is its [proper] condition (bhāva), [and not another]. [Let us consider, for instance, the cognition], ‘This earring is gold’: in [that distinctive] cognitive evidence (pratyaya) [which is said at once] syntactical homogeneity and coreferentiality (sāmānādhikaraṇya, ), both difference and non-difference clearly appear.Footnote 10

About what opposition (viruddha) is VM talking? Clearly, about the opposition between the properties gold-ness and bracelet-hood, which are certainly not one and the same. Nonetheless, in case of a golden bracelet, there is but one single being, yet considered from different perspectives. The opposition, that is, distinction, between the aforesaid properties is not a cause for contradiction about their coreferentiality. Therefore, to what does VM ascribe this irreducible opposition which, nonetheless, does not apparently generate any contradiction with respect to coreferentiality? To the epistemic process itself, answers VM. Is he possibly alluding to a knowing subject who mistakes mother-of-pearl for silver or a rope for a snake? Not at all. The subject correctly recognises here both the bracelet and the gold of which the former is made. Indeed, this bracelet can be worn, as well as the gold melted and reshaped. On the contrary, the mother-of-pearl mistaken for silver cannot ever be melted, just like a rope cannot bite or produce any effect different from those proper to a rope, such as tying or being mistaken for a snake. Gold and bracelet are here properly known and their presence or condition of existence (bhāva) is correctly defined as the result of the knowing processes (pramāṇa) of which they are objects (viṣaya).Footnote 11 According to TvN, “what possesses the property of being that, is that” (tadvattvaṃ tad eva). Consequently, to be the bracelet that it is, a bracelet (b) has to be cognized as possessing that particular property which makes it a bracelet and not something else; that is, bracelet-hood (bt). Otherwise, no bracelet would be cognized and the issue raised by VM would have never risen. Idem for gold. The determined cognition by means of which bracelet and gold are correctly cognized inevitably and simultaneously opposes them. It is not a matter of perceptual illusion or epistemic dysfunction, since the point is here far more serious. Placing itself to the opposing end of the knowing process and not being possible to grasp it otherwise, in which manner an object (prameya) is known via the respective source of knowledge (pramāṇa) so it is (bhāva). In other terms, the prameya’s ontological status appears to inevitably depend on the means of knowledge by which the former is known. Therefore, what is correctly known always relies on what I call a ‘refined definition’ (pariṣkāra-lakṣaṇa) supplied by a well-conducted knowing process; that is, a definition which thus turns out to be obstinately recurring regardless of how many times the analysis might be repeated. Here, then, is the opposition to which VM alludes. A consolidated epistemological triptych secures the ordered succession of uddeśa (the preliminary enunciation or denomination of what has to be known, the prameya); lakṣaṇa (the definition of the prameya by means of a peculiar feature, capable of distinguishing it, vyāvṛtti, from all the rest—tattvavyavacchedaka or tattvaparicchedaka); and the parīkṣā (the examination or assessment, by means of the relative knowledge source or pramāṇa, of the appropriateness of the advanced definition to the object under scrutiny).Footnote 12 In compliance with this triptych, lakṣaṇa cannot but precede the use of knowledge sources, since this use is committed to the endorsement of the former. On the contrary, I here intend to refer to this sort of ‘refined definition’ (pariṣkāra-lakṣaṇa), polished, validated, and therefore, having passed the test of parīkṣā, somehow conclusive. In this sense, pariṣkāra-lakṣaṇa necessarily follows the intervention of pramāṇas. At the end of the process of knowing, the prameya is revealed to be just what the pramāṇas have reported it to be. In the case of the golden bracelet correctly known, the sources of knowledge themselves unify and oppose two distinct properties in the very same locus. Therefore: etat kim? (‘What’s this?’); idaṃ kaṭakam (‘This is a bracelet’); idaṃ hāṭakam (‘This is gold’); idaṃ hāṭaka-kaṭakam (‘This is a golden bracelet’).

Reflexiveness, Mutual Absence and Locus Sharing (5)

In the light of the above, the terms of the question are at once plainly clear and utterly paradoxical. VM does emphasise their puzzling effect by juxtaposing both the extremes of the spectrum in a single comprehensive passage. The formal tools acquired in P1&P2 have fulfilled all the necessary conditions for the detailed analysis of the following passage, while definitely demonstrating the unviability of the evoked, more nuanced, partial solutions.

In case of an absolute (ātyantika) non-difference, the undesired outcome (prasaṅga) of a double occurrence (dviravabhāsa) [is inevitably determined] (cf. §5.1); [whether] an absolute distinction [is instead supposed, then there will be] no coreferentiality (sāmānādhikaraṇya) at all, as between a cow and a horse (cf. §5.2). [Moreover], no coreferentiality [can be given in the context of] a relation of substratum-superstratum (ādhāra-ādheya-bhāva; cf. §5.3.1), or of ‘residing in one locus’ (ekāśrayatva; cf. §5.3.2). [Nobody would say that] ‘A jujube (Ziziphus Jujuba) is the bowl’, [only on the grounds that the jujube is in that bowl]; as well as, regarding [the two friends] Caitra and Maitra, [who are sitting] on the same bench, that ‘Caitra is Maitra’.Footnote 13

Absolute Reflexive Non-difference (5.1)

VM starts his analysis facing the case of a possible absolute non-difference (ātyantika-abheda) ruling the relation between gold and bracelet. Yet, if the relation of absolute non-difference is interpreted as the complete impossibility of distinguishing between the two properties, then this entails their reduction to one and the consequent collapse of abheda into a tautological reflexive relation; that is, in the VM’s words, the ‘undesired event of a double appearance’ (dviravabhāsa-prasaṅga; cf. P1.§2). Therefore, the cognition ‘suvarṇam idaṃ kuṇḍalam’ (‘This earring is gold’) will turn into ‘kuṇḍalam idaṃ kuṇḍalam’ or ‘suvarṇam idaṃ suvarṇam’ (‘This earring is an earring’ or ‘This gold is gold’). The issue is straightforward: once any possibility of distinguishing between the relata has been negated by hypothesis, ST (Substitutivity Test), LL (Leibniz’s Law), and PII (Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles, although controversial) will find a proper application, and the relation will collapse into identity tout court. The impossible reduction of non-difference to identity—discussed in depth in P2.§4—finds here further confirmation.Footnote 14 Hereafter, in order to avoid any external reference to the NN framework, I propose to express a logical function roughly analogous to the one performed by LL through what I call tādātmīya-kāraṇa-naya (TKN) or the Identity Reduction Rule: tādātmye sati satataṃ samaniyatatva-ātyantikābhedav anubhātaḥ (‘Given identity, equality and perfect non-difference [in every respect] necessarily follow’). Let taddharmavattva (tdt) and etaddharmavattva (edt) be the generic properties, being that and being this, for t ∈|tdt| and e ∈|edt| (i.e., ‘t, is a specimen of being that, and belongs to the set What is that’; the same applies for edt). Thereby, it could be stated that:

[TKN] e . t

(e . edtI t . td t)⌝ℕ⌞(1t)


tad etad (bhavati) ity uktvā, tan-niṣṭha-taddharmavattvaitan-niṣṭhaitaddharmavattvayor tādātmyaikatve sati, taddharmavattvaitaddharmavattve samaniyata ity taddharmavattvaitaddharmavattve ’bhinna iti cānuvartateFootnote 15; whose purport is: (t)‘If that (t) is () this (e), in the meaning of a relation of identity (I), for a cardinality equal to one [since that and this are the very same object], then perfect equality (Q) and non-difference , between the property being that (tdt) and being this (edt) occurring in that (t) and this (e), necessarily follow’; iff:

  1. A.

    card() = 1; i.e., relation involves one single object;

  2. B.

    e ∈|edt| ∧ t ∈|tdt|, for TvN; viz., this and that are proper occurrences of the generic properties being this and being that, lest they be not what they are;

  3. C.

    e, t⟩ ∈I ; that is, ‘This and that are identical’;

  4. D.

    ‘e’ = ‘t’ , for (|edt| = ED) = (|tdt| = TD); i.e., the generic properties being that and being this are coextensive or, in other words, the same property (as in the case of: sāsnādimatī gauḥ, ‘A cow or the [animal] possessing dewlap, etc.’; cf. P2.§2); therefore, the terms by means of which these coextensive properties are expressed are reciprocally interchangeable (e.g., sāsnādimatī gauḥ or gaur gauḥ);

  5. E.

    dviravabhāsa-prasaṅgābhavaḥ; that is, ‘The undesired event of a double appearance does not occur’; in standard logic terms, all the expressions pass the Substitutivity Test, since the said double occurrence of a term does not affect the expression’s truth values and its overall meaning.Footnote 16

If it is true that the bracelet is gold or non-different from gold (cf. [44]), TKN definitely shows, on the contrary, how it is utterly false to say that the bracelet is stricto sensu identical to gold, since bracelet-hood and gold-ness are beyond any doubt not coextensive. The proper expression of the relation standing between these properties is, instead, a formula conveying the non-empty intersection between two sets (cf. infra, §5.2, [45a] and fn. 17).

Mutual Exclusion and Coreference Rule (DSN) (5.2)

As a second step, VM excludes by contradiction the hypothesis of difference (bheda) qua ‘mutual exclusion’ between properties reciprocally distinct (bhinna). If there were mutual exclusion, there would not be any coreferentiality between gold-ness and bracelet-hood, just as in the case of cow-hood and horse-hood. Yet, this is clearly not the case. Formula [44]—true for h∈|b|; i.e., ‘A specimen of gold belongs to the set What is coreferential to a bracelet’—asserts that gold-ness and bracelet-hood are coreferential, at least in one case: the golden bracelet under exam. In general terms and via reductio ad absurdum, let us prove by means of what I call Dharma-Sāmānādhikaraṇya-Naya (DSN; Properties Coreference Rule) that if two properties are coreferential at least in one case, they cannot be said to be mutually absent.

In the assertion ‘tad etad bhavati’ (i.e., ‘That is this’ or ‘t is e’), a single case of coreference () is premised:

[45] t . e

yā tan-niṣṭha-sāmānādhikaraṇyatā saitad-nirūpitā; that is, (t)t and e are coreferential’; iff:

  1. A.

    e ∈(|edt|=ED); for TvN, ‘e belongs to set ED, extension of the property edt (lest e not be e)’. Ergo: e = e . edt ; that is, etanniṣṭham etaddharmavattvam (‘Property e-hood occurs in e’).

  2. B.

    Regarding t, ditto;

  3. C.

    t|e|, i.e., ‘That (t) belongs to set What is coreferential to this (e)’.

Let us now analyse, in compliance with the truth conditions of [45] which only imposes at least one case of coreferentiality, the least onerous possible relation standing between the properties tdt and edt through the application of the operator ‘yathā-tathā’ (‘just like-so’, ⥯; cf. Anrò 2022: §4.3), capable of expressing a non-empty intersection between two sets:

[45a] tedt

yathā yā sāmānādhikaraṇyatā tanniṣṭhā saitaddharmavattva-nirūpitā, tathā yā viparīta-sāmānādhikaraṇyataitanniṣṭhā sā taddharmavattva-nirūpitā; that is, (t)‘Just like at least one occurrence of the property tdt is coreferential to edt, so at least one occurrence of the property tdt is coreferential to edt’; iff (t.edt) ∧ (e.−1tdt); i.e., t|edt|e|−1tdt|; ergo: (|tdt||edt| ≠ ∅) ∧ (|edt||−1tdt| ≠ ∅); i.e., ‘The intersection of the sets |tdt| and What is coreferential to the property edt is not empty’ or, roughly speaking, ‘There is at least one t which is e’; moreover, ‘The intersection of the sets |edt| and What is inversely coreferential to the property tdt is not empty’; that is, ‘There is at least one e which is t’; or T∩E ≠ ∅ (for |tdt|=T and |edt|=E); in s.n. (~∀x, ~∀y | ~TDx, ~EDy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈).

For instance, there are undoubtedly golden bracelets, yet not every bracelet is golden and gold is not always a bracelet.Footnote 17 Despite the above, the mutual absence (; here again expressed as: −1I−1, cf. P2.§3) between the properties tdt and edt be forcibly imposed:

*[45b] tdt−1 ⌞(I−1edt)

yā taddharmavattva-avacchedakāvacchinna-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sā tādātmyatā-nirūpitā, saiva tādātmyataitaddharmavattva-nirūpitā, tadviparyayeṇa ca; ‘Constant absentee-hood, limited by the property being that, is conditioned by mutual absentee-hood, in turn conditioned by the property being this, &vv’; that is, (t)‘Properties tdt and edt are completely distinct or mutually exclusive, since where there is the former, the latter is always absent, &vv’; iff |tdt|∩|I−1edt| = ∅, in other words, TD∩ED = ∅ (i.e., the intersection between the sets Extension of property tdt and Extension of property edt is empty); in s.n. (∀x, ∀y | TDx, EDy) (⟨x, y⟩ ∉ ) (for I, cf. P2.§5).

According to the NL syntax rules (cf. Anrò 2022, §5), a complex ‘consideration’ (parāmarśa; Bhattacharyya, 1987, pp. 178–182) can now be built by substitution, combining *[45b] with [45a]:

*[45c] (tedt) ⇌ −1 ⌞(I−1⌞ (tedt))

whose purport is (t)*‘Property tdt, which in its occurrence t is coreferential to edt, is completely distinct or mutually absent with respect to property edt, which in its occurrence e is coreferential to tdt’; iff TD∩ED ≠ ∅ (for [45a]) and TD∩ED = ∅ (for *[46b]); that is, *‘The intersection between the sets Extension of property tdt and Extension of property edt is both not empty and empty’.

Formula *[45c] is a downright contradiction in terms, violating the reciprocal semantical compatibility (yogyatā) of its own components; therefore, *[45c] is always false (⊥).Footnote 18 In general, it can now be stated:

DSN (t . e) ∧ (tdt ⇌ ∄−1 ⌞(I−1edt)) → ⊥

tdt−1⌞ (−1t ⌞(I−1edt))

tan-niṣṭha-sāmānādhikaraṇyatāyām etan-nirūpitāyāṃ satyāṃ yadi yā taddharmavattva-avacchedakāvacchinna-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sā tādātmyatā-nirūpitā, saiva tādātmyataitaddharmavattva-nirūpitā tadviparyayeṇa ca, tarhi virodhaḥ saṃbhavati; tataḥ pratiyogitā-a-bhāvaḥ; whose purport is: (t)‘Given the coreference between this and that, the mutual absence between the relative properties is no more possible and its assertion is always false (⊥). Therefore (∴), only the negation of this negation can be true’.Footnote 19

In conclusion, by virtue of DSN, whenever the coreferentiality between two occurrences of non-coextensive properties is premised, then it is always impossible to interpret the mutual distinction between these properties qua constant mutual absence (atyanta-anyonyābhāva).

The Fruit is Not the Bowl and the Bench of Caitra and Maitra (5.3.1)

Having excluded both the interpretations of coreferentiality () as identity (I; cf. §5.1) and mutual absence , VM now clears the ground from possible misinterpretations in terms of ādhāra-ādheya-bhāva (L). I call it ‘Hypothesis of substratum-superstratum’ (L-Hy). Let us first consider the classical relational paradigm of substratum-superstratum (L)—‘A pot (p) on the ground (g)’, as clearly distinct objects connected by contact:

[46] (g . Lp)⌝ℕ⌞(2t)

yad āśrayatā-avacchedakāvacchinna-paryāptitvaṃ tad dvitva-nirūpitam; yaiva bhūtala-niṣṭha-āśrayatā sā ghaṭa-nirūpitā; ‘The relational abstract locus-hood, limited by the ground, is conditioned by a pot, for card(L) = 2’; iff g|Lp| ∧ G∩P ≠ ∅ ∧ card(L) = 2 (respectively, ‘A certain ground belongs to the set Loci of a pot’; ‘The intersection between the sets Grounds and Pots is empty’, since grounds which are also pots do not exist; for the same reason, their cardinality is equal to two; that is, that ground plus one pot); in s.n. (∃x, ∃y | Gx, Py) (⟨x, y⟩ ∈L).

Yet, premise [44] must be reaffirmed, for h∈|b|, B∩H ≠ ∅, and card{h, b} = 1 (i.e., ‘A specimen of gold belongs to the set What is coreferential to a bracelet’; ‘The intersection of the sets What is gold and Bracelets is not empty’; ‘The cardinality of the set containing a specimen of gold and a bracelet is equal to one’). It clearly follows that L; that is, ‘The relation of coreferentiality is completely different from the relation of substratum-superstratum, since they do not share any common pairs’ (cf. P2.§4 and fn. 44). Therefore, L is never a valid interpretation of , being a special case of contact (saṃyoga-sambandha; ): for ( ≠ (L)) ⊆ V. If ‘There is a pot on the ground’ (bhūtale ghaṭaḥ; L() or L qua ), that does not imply that *‘The pot is the ground’ (*bhūtalaṃ ghaṭaḥ; ), just as, if there is a jujube in a bowl, it does not follow that the jujube is the bowl.Footnote 20 Also appealing to a possible ‘relation of sharing by contact the same basis’ (ekāśraya-saṃyoga-sambandha; 1L()) for a cardinality greater than one (card(1L()) 2) will be of no avail in this regard. In the words of VM, if Caitra and Maitra sit on the same bench (for card(1L())=3), this does not either turn Caitra into Maitra, or even less the two friends into their bench.Footnote 21

Mysterious Indeterminate Variables (5.3.2)

A second variant of this last hypothesis is subtler. Indeed, it could be objected that distinct properties might possibly share a single locus (eka-āśraya) not via contact (saṃyoga) and for an imposed cardinality equal to one (card (1L) = 1), solving in this manner the contradiction between their utter distinction and their joint manifestation. I call it, ‘Hypothesis of sharing a sole locus’ (1L-Hy). For instance, properties gold-ness and bracelet-hood, properly conceived in their distinctions and prerogatives, might occur in a further basis, locus, receptacle, or sub-ject (etymologically). This formulation, not unintentionally, displays many similarities with that which is commonly expressed in standard notation: (∃x | Hx ∧ Bx); that is, there is an unspecified variable x, acting in the capacity of sub-ject or ontological basis, able to collect a series of distinct properties, such as being gold and being a bracelet. Despite the Nāgārjuna’s ante litteram confutations, the general strategy is thus, first, to summon up a “bare particular” in order to subsequently attribute to it a collection of properties in coordination.Footnote 22 On that premise, VM asks, how to interpret this attribution of properties to a generic common basis?

Let us suppose the intervention of a common indeterminate basis ‘a’ (anirṇīta-sādhārana-āśraya) being the middle term between two distinct relata (here, being gold and being bracelet) via the ‘relation of sharing the same basis’ (ekāśraya-sambandha; 1L):

[47a] a . 1Lht

yā ekāśrayatā anirṇīta-sādhārana-āśraya-niṣṭhā sā hāṭakatva-nirūpitā; (t)‘Gold-ness occurs on/in a sole, common, indeterminate basis or sub-ject’; iff a|1Lht | (i.e., ‘The indeterminate, single, basis a belongs to the set What on/in which, qua sole basis, at least one instance of gold-ness occurs).

In parallel, being a, the common indeterminate sole basis of a bracelet too, according to 1L-Hy it must similarly be affirmed that:

[47b] a . 1L bt

yā ekāśrayatā anirṇīta-sādhārana-āśraya-niṣṭhā sā kaṭakatva-nirūpitā; (t)‘Bracelet-hood occurs on/in a sole, common, indeterminate basis or sub-ject’; iff a|1Lbt| (i.e., ‘The one and only indeterminate basis a belongs to the set What on/in which, qua sole basis, at least one instance of bracelet-hood occurs).

Composing, by substitution, [47a] and [47b] in a complex judgment (parāmarśa), the result would then be:

[47c] (a . 1Ltht)⌝ 1Lbt

yā ekāśrayatātva-avacchedakāvacchinna-ekāśrayatā sā kaṭakatva-nirūpitā; tad evaikāśrayatātvam anirṇīta-sādhārana-āśraya-niṣṭhaṃ hāṭakatva-nirūpitaṃ ca; ‘The relational abstract being a common locus (1L), conditioned by bracelet-hood (bt), is limited by the [same] relational abstract being a common locus, conditioned by gold-ness (ht), which in turn occurs on/in a sole, common, indeterminate basis or sub-ject (a)’; that is, (t)’Bracelet-hood occurs on/in an indeterminate single basis, which is the very same basis on/in which also gold-ness occurs’; iff (a|1Ltht|) ⊆ (|1Lbt|) (i.e., ‘The basis a belongs to the set What on/in which, qua sole basis, at least one instance of gold-ness occurs; the latter is in turn a subset of What on/in which, qua sole basis, at least one instance of bracelet-hood occurs’).Footnote 23

Now, which truth values should be attributed to [47c]? As the sole alternative (cf. §.5.3.1), the cardinality of the relation of ‘sharing the same basis’ (1L) has to be hypothesized as strictly equal to one (card (1L) = 1):

[47d] ((a . 1Lth)⌝ 1Lb) ⌝ℕ⌞(1t)


yat paryāptitvam ekāśrayatā-avacchedakāvacchinnaṃ tad ekatva-nirūpitam; saivaikāśrayatātva-avacchedakāvacchinnaikāśrayatā hāṭaka-nirūpitā; tad eva avacchedakaikāśrayatātvam anirṇīta-sādhārana-āśraya-niṣṭhaṃ hāṭaka-nirūpitaṃ ca; iff:

  1. A.

    (card (1L) = 1) ∧ (a|1Lth|) → (|1Lth| = {a}) ∴ (a = h) ; i.e., if the cardinality of relation of ‘sharing the same basis’ (1L) is equal to one and (∧) the one and only indeterminate basis a belongs to the set What on/in which, qua sole basis, a specimen of gold occurs, then (→) the set What on/in which, qua sole basis, a specimen of gold occurs must possess the basis a qua its sole element; therefore (∴), the basis a and the specimen of gold h are nothing but the same element.

  2. B.

    (card (1L) = 1) ∧ (a|1Lb|) → (|1Lb| = {a}) ∴ (a = b) ; i.e., if the cardinality of relation of ‘sharing the same basis’ (1L) is equal to one and (∧) the one and only indeterminate basis a belongs to the set What on/in which, qua sole basis, a bracelet occurs, then (→) the set What on/in which, qua sole basis, a bracelet occurs must possess the basis a qua its sole element; therefore (∴), the basis a and the bracelet b are nothing but the same element.

  3. C.

    A ∧ B ∴ (a = h = b), for card (1L) = 1; i.e., given conditions A and B, it follows that the basis a, the specimen of gold h, and the bracelet b are one and the same.

Truth conditions analysis reveals that this first interpretation of ekāśraya-sambandha (1L), for card (1L) = 1, is reducible to coreferentiality (sāmānādhikaraṇya; ) between three terms.

[47e] ((a . t (1L)h)⌝ (1L)b) ⌝ℕ⌞(1t)

yat paryāptitvaṃ sāmānādhikaraṇyatā-avacchedakāvacchinnaṃ tad ekatva-nirūpitam; saiva sāmānādhikaraṇyatātva-avacchedakāvacchinna-sāmānādhikaraṇyatā hāṭaka-nirūpitā; saiva avacchedaka-sāmānādhikaraṇyatātvam anirṇīta-sādhārana-āśraya-niṣṭhaṃ hāṭaka-nirūpitaṃ ca; whose purport is (t)‘A specimen of gold is the indeterminate basis a, by coreferentiality; a bracelet also is that very basis, since there is but a single object, for card()=1’.

This interpretation ((1L); i.e., as 1L, for card((1L)) = 1) correctly insists on the unity of the referent. Therefore, this common undefined basis which has been here summoned up—i.e., this ‘existing x’, according to the s.n. (∃x | Hx ∧ Bx)—is revealed to be a third linguistic device (vācārambhaṇa or vāgālambana) distinguishing what de facto is not distinct at all. An additional element of distinction (viz., an undefined basis or x) is introduced in an attempt to explain the radical unity of two properties. In other words, 1L-Hy, as a strategy to circumvent the conundrum about gold and bracelet, plays out a scenario which is even worse than the previous one, displaying three elements (instead of two) and two relations in coordination (instead of one). Worse still is the consequent proliferation (anavasthā) of relations. How, indeed, to connect the first property to its basis if not through another medium, and so on? Thus, 1L-Hy, in this last variation, turns out to be if not utterly faulty at least pointless, since the still intact issue of distinction in unity is merely shifted by one step back, ad infinitum. In broader terms, two distinct concurrent logical paradigms are here at stake. According to Nyāya, presuming that an undetermined x, qua basis of successive predications or qualifications, is a more primitive notion than an always qualified ‘dummy singular term’ (Matilal, 1968, p. 23) from which to extract the derived notion of ‘undetermined basis’, is entirely unjustified. Accordingly, the naiyāyika account requires a single relation only, instead of two, and no abstract particulars (i.e., variables), since only dummy singular terms are postulated, which de facto operate as restricted variables.Footnote 24

Transitional Considerations (6)

The following passage can be considered as a junction point in the much broader context of VM’s rigorous argumentative architecture. Despite all the conceptual difficulties which have been set out so far, a golden bracelet still appears to be a bracelet not less than gold. The relation of coreferentiality thus imposes itself as a primitive and ineliminable notion, both logical and linguistic, a foundational, inescapable, and cognitively irreducible gnoseological framework.Footnote 25 The open distinction of multiple properties in the unity of the referent cannot apparently be sublated. VM chooses to quote, at this crucial turning point, a passage from Brahma-sūtra-bhāskāra-bhāṣya. Yet let us not be deceived: this is not VM’s last word on the issue, but its reaffirmation in ever closer spiral movements.

It is this incontrovertible (abādhita), indubitable (asaṃdigdha), and universal (sarvajanīna), epistemic evidence (pratyaya) of coreferentiality which establishes difference and non-difference between cause and effect. Thereby, since the effects [possess] the same nature (ātman) as their causes, as well as [every] cause always and in every case persists as existent, there is non-difference of the effect—[that is], the phenomenal manifestation—with respect to the reality [of the cause], [not less than] difference [when the former] is considered as effect, such as ‘[being] a cow, or a pot, etc.’ Indeed, it has been said: “Multiplicity qua effect, non-difference qua cause; just as there is non-difference with respect to the gold, but distinction (bhidā) with respect to the earring, and so on”.Footnote 26

Definition of Difference (7)

In this respect, it might be said anew: what is this, which is termed difference and should occur in the very same locus (ekatra) together with non-difference? If it [were conceived as] mutual absence (parasparābhāva), would it stand between effect and cause; that is, between bracelet and gold, or would it not? If not, then there would be simple singularity (ekatva), and no difference [at all] (§7.1). [On the contrary], in case of [mutual absence between bracelet and gold], there would be [full] difference and any [form of] non-difference. Moreover, there would be a [flagrant] contradiction (virodha) between presence and absence: [once that bracelet and gold have been declared as mutually excluding, their] co-presence (saha-avasthāna) is [clearly] impossible (asaṃbhava) (§7.2.1). Alternatively, in the case [the co-presence of mutually exclusive properties were said to be] possible, the undesired consequence (prasaṅga) of an in rem (tattva) non-difference between a bracelet and a vardhamāna [would inevitably follow], due to the lack of contradiction between difference and non-difference (§7.2.2).Footnote 27

VM here examines in detail the features of difference (bheda) as mutual absence (parasparābhāva or ). A pot, for instance, is mutually absent with respect to a cloth simply because where there is a pot there is not a cloth, and vice versa (for G∩P = ∅, i.e., ‘the intersection between Pots and Cloths is empty). Now, VM sharply asks, does this mutual absence—which is reducible, salva veritate, to the constant or absolute absence of identity (tādātmya-atyantābhāva, ∄(I); cf. P2.§3.[19]-[21])—also occur between non-identical coreferential properties, such as gold-ness and bracelet-hood?

Absence of Difference as Mutual Exclusion (7.1)

In a first case, VM suggests, difference qua mutual absence (anyonyābhāva) might be straightforwardly negated; that is, declared as absolutely absent (atyantābhāva). Provided that hāṭakaṃ kaṭakam (‘The bracelet is gold’), its negation should in turn be negated, i.e., hāṭakaṃ na kaṭakam ity na (‘It is false that a bracelet is not gold’):

[48a] h−1⌞(−1t ⌞(I−1b))

yā hāṭaka-niṣṭha-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sā atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitātva-nirūpitā, saiva atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitātvaṃ tādātmyatā-nirūpitam, saiva tādātmyatā kaṭaka-nirūpitā, tadviparyayeṇa ca; ‘Constant absentee-hood, conditioned by being constant absentee-hood in turn conditioned by identity conditioned by a bracelet, occurs in a specimen of gold, &vv’; that is, (t)‘A bracelet is not not-gold’; iff h|−1⌞(I−1b)|b|−1⌞(I−1h)|; i.e. ‘A specimen of gold does not belong to the set What is absent with respect to identity with a bracelet, &vv’.

In a second step, provided that (i.e., tādātmyātyantābhāva = anyonyābhāva; cf. supra), by means of the transition formula [48b] , the counterfactual formula is then newly obtained and reconfirmed, expressing the relation of non-difference between gold and bracelet: , i.e., (t)‘A specimen of gold is not the counterpositive of a difference with regard to a bracelet, being the former coreferential to the latter, for a cardinality equal to one’—clearly matching the model of Gadādhara’s definition of unity (ekatva; cf. P2 f.[22]-[24], [34]). Let us deepen further the analysis of its truth conditions:

  1. A.

    , i.e, ‘A specimen of gold does not belong to the set What is different from a bracelet, &vv’; ergo: ; that is, ‘h does not belong to the complement of B′ (for B′ = {b}; the singleton ‘A certain bracelet’ containing b only)’; in parallel, b does not belong to the complement of H′ (for H′ = {h}; the singleton ‘A certain specimen of gold’ containing h only)’; therefore, the linguistically divergent expressions ‘h’ and ‘b’ refer to the same referent or singular extension (h = b, according to the distinction arthataḥ and śabdataḥ, or names vs. mentions; cf. P2.§3), for (h, b) ∈B′ and card(B′) = 1, or (h, b) ∈H′ and card(H′) = 1.

  2. B.

    If condition A, then: h ∈B′ (for B′ = {b}) ∧ b ∈H′ (for H′ = {h}); i.e., ‘h belongs to the singleton containing b only’, as well as ‘b belongs to the singleton containing h only’. Conditions A and B clearly show that [44] is indeed a perfect case of sāmānādhikaraṇya, for card() = 1 and V(): B ↦ V()[B] and V()[B] ⊆ B, in virtue of SVN (cf. P1.§4, P2.§4).

  3. C.

    Nevertheless: (⟨‘h’, ‘b’⟩ ∉Q) ∧ (⟨h, b⟩ ∉I); that is, the terms ‘h’ and ‘b’ as mentions are linguistically divergent, being expressions of distinct (i.e., not coextensive) properties (for H≠B, and H∩B ≠ ∅) (cf. P2.[28]). Thus, by the application of TKN (cf. §5.1), the occurrences h and b of the properties |ht|=H and |bt|=B cannot be said stricto sensu to be identical (since the plexus of properties, in case of identity, must appear indiscernible). Indeed, [44] is neither ruled by LL (Leibniz’s Law), nor can pass the ST (substitutivity Test) (cf. P2.§4).

The first hypothesis analysed by VM, i.e., the negation of difference qua reciprocal absence, turns out to be an attestation of unity (ekatva) between the relata. It should also be noted how VM cautiously and subtly employs the term ‘unity’ and avoids awkwardly evoking here the term ‘identity’ (tādātmya; cf. P2.§4).

Difference as Mutual Exclusion (7.2.1)

The discussion of the second possibility is far easier. As it has already been said, if there is mere mutual exclusion between bracelet (b) and gold (h), there will be simple difference between them; in other words, any form of non-difference, just as in the case of cow-hood and horse-hood (cf. §5). On the model of P2.[21], a relation of mutual exclusion regarding b and h—highlighting its cardinality and again interpreting difference as absence of identity qua case of coreferentiality ((I); i.e., as I, for I)—can be expressed in NL as:

*[49a] (h . −1⌞((I)b))⌝ℕ⌞(2t)

yat paryāptitvaṃ atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā-avacchedakāvacchinnaṃ tad dvitva-nirūpitam, saiva hāṭaka-niṣṭha-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sāmānādhikaraṇyatā-nirūpitā, saiva sāmānādhikaraṇyatā kaṭaka-nirūpitā; whose purport is (t)‘A specimen of gold (h) and a bracelet (b) are different, namely, non-coreferential, since they are two distinct objects’; iff h ∈(|ht|=H) ∧ b ∈(|bt|=B); h ∉|b| (i.e., ‘h does not belong to the set What is coreferential to b’); card({h, b})=2 (i.e., ‘The set containing h and b as its elements has a cardinality equal to two’); in s.n. (∃x, ∃y | Hx, By); that is, ‘There is a specimen of gold, as well as, there is a bracelet’.

Nevertheless, formula *[49a] is utterly false, since in plain contradiction with the adopted premise (cf. [44]) according to which a golden bracelet is a radically single object. In the words of VM, whether golden bracelet and gold were conceived as mutually excluding, “there would be a [flagrant] contradiction between presence and absence”, since their co-presence (saha-avasthāna) would be simultaneously possible and impossible. In sum, if it is false that *⟨h, b (i.e., ‘h and b do not constitute an ordered pair of mutual absence relation’); yet, salva veritate, it is true that: (i.e., ‘The relation of absence of mutual absence shares the same ordered pairs with the relation of absence of absence of identity; that is, non-difference’). Therefore: ⟨h, b⟩ ∈ (i.e., ‘h and b constitute an ordered pair of the relation of absence of mutual absence, or absence of absence of identity, or non-difference).

Coexistence in Difference as Mutual Absence (7.2.2)

VM then introduces a further slight change of perspective according to which the properties gold-ness and bracelet-hood are said to be forcefully coexistent (sahāvasthāna), i.e., coreferential (), despite the fact that they have been here considered as reciprocally absent by hypothesis (cf. §7.2.1). In other words, VM argues, it could still be argued that these two properties might somehow be forced to coexist despite their neat reciprocal distinction.Footnote 28 In a complementary manner, this line of argumentation is premised on the assumption that the supposedly coreferential properties gold-ness and bracelet-hood could appear, nevertheless, as mutually absent. Thus, generalizing *[49a], the following universal assertion will first be obtained:

*[49b] ht−1⌞(I−1bt)

yā hāṭakatva-avacchedakāvacchinna-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sā tādātmyatā-nirūpitā, saiva tādātmyatā kaṭakatva-nirūpitā, tadviparyayeṇa ca; that is, (t)‘Every specimen of gold and every bracelet is mutually absent’; iff *((|ht||bt|) = *(H∩B)) = ∅ (‘The intersection between Gold and Bracelets is empty’); in s.n.: (∃x, ∃y | Hx, By) (‘There is a specimen of gold and a bracelet’).

In the same manner, let us now consider the relation standing between the properties bracelet-hood (bt) and being a vardhamāna (vardhamānatva, vt). Whatever a vardhamāna is—whether it is a golden ornament or a completely different thing, such as a castor-oil plant (cf. fn. 27)—it must be said to be distinct from a bracelet beyond any doubt, since there is no bracelet which is also a vardhamāna and vice versa. Therefore:

[49c] vt−1⌞(I−1bt)

yā vardhamānatva-avacchedakāvacchinna-atyantābhāvīya-pratiyogitā sā tādātmyatā-nirūpitā, saiva tādātmyatā kaṭakatva-nirūpitā, tadviparyayeṇa ca; that is, (t)‘Bracelets and vardhamānas (v) are always mutually absent’; iff b ∈(|bt|=B) ∧ v ∈(|vt|=V) ∧ (B∩V = ∅) (‘The intersection between Bracelets and Vardhamānas is empty’); in s.n.: (∃x, ∃y | Bx, Vy) (i.e., ‘There is a bracelet and there is a vardhamāna’).

Under this hypothesis it must, in parallel, be admitted that gold and bracelet are forcefully coexistent (sahāvasthāna). That means that coreferentiality () must stand between them as an imposed condition. As already expressed in [44] , it must be admitted that: h∈|b| (‘A specimen of gold belongs to the set What is coreferential to a bracelet’), h ∈(|ht|=H), b ∈(|bt|=B), and H∩B ≠ ∅. Now, following VM here, the patent contradiction between the respective truth conditions (viz., *[49b] for H∩B=∅ and [44] for H∩B≠∅) be momentarily left aside, to firstly focus on the fact that *[49b] ht−1⌞(I−1bt) and [49c] vt−1⌞(I−1bt) are formally identical. Therefore, once it has been accepted that gold and bracelet can be said to be forcefully coexistent (sahāvasthāna, via ; in compliance with [44]) despite the fact that their respective properties are mutually absent (in compliance with *[49b]), how then might it be possible to prevent that a bracelet and a vardhamāna could also be coreferential in the same manner, although it is patently absurd (as stated in [49c]) that a bracelet could also be a vardhamāna, and vice versa? To put it another way, if *[49b] ht−1⌞(I−1bt), and nevertheless h∈|b| (as in [44]) then also *b∈|v|, for B∩V≠∅, despite the fact that [49c] vt−1⌞(I−1bt), for B∩V=∅. As expected, VM says the hypothesis under §7.2.2 cannot but lead to the “undesired consequence of an in rem (tattva) non-difference between a bracelet and a vardhamāna”. In other words, if the principle is accepted according to which difference qua mutual absence can be compatible, no matter how, with non-difference qua coreferentiality, nothing could then prevent the application of this very same relation to any other property. Each property might thus be said to be coexistent with every other. Therefore, if gold-ness and bracelet-hood are clearly distinct properties, their manner of not being equal and identical (i.e., coextensive, cf. P2) is never reducible to that existing between bracelet-hood and vardhamānatva (i.e., anyonyābhāva); or, roughly speaking, a bracelet differs from the gold of which it is made in a different way from the manner a pot differs from a horse. VM definitely shows that an imposed compatibility, coordination, or coexistence in mutual absence cannot apply to abheda, since this latter would then be jeopardized by the definitional flaw of over-application (ativyāpti-doṣa-lakṣaṇa; cf. fn. 7). This unreflecting form of irenic non-contradiction between difference and non-difference, according to which mutually exclusive properties can supposedly coexist, being applicable to every case of difference, cannot but generate an unstoppable general escalation of “undesired consequences”. Since coexistence occurs only under certain conditions (e.g., between pot and clay, but never between lake and fire) the alleged solution of an unspecified coexistence of bhedābheda—‘bheda together with abheda’, respectively conceived as mutual absence and negation of mutual absence—is unavoidably dismissed.Footnote 29

The Undesired Obliteration of Every Concurrent Property (8)

Moreover, in [the hypothesis where] a bracelet is not different from the gold [of which it is made, not being the former the counterpositive of a mutual absence with respect to the latter], [also all other golden] bracelets, crowns, earrings, etc., should not be distinguishable from gold. In the same manner, they could never be distinguished from [that first] bracelet, [as well as one from another], by virtue of their [acknowledged] non-difference from gold. Consequently, [according to this hypothesis], gold only [could be properly assessed as the unquestionable] reality of [all those] beings (vastu-sat), [and surely] not [their ‘being] bracelets’, and so on, [that we are instead forced to acknowledge as gold solely]. [This is simply] because difference, [so conceived], would not appear [in any form between gold and golden artifacts, as well as between golden artifact and golden artifact]. It follows that, [along these lines, we are once again brought back to the starting point]: there is non-difference only with respect to the gold, [but] not with respect to the bracelet—since this latter is [undoubtedly] different from an earring, etc.Footnote 30

In this passage VM has again slightly changed his perspective through the introduction of a multiplicity of distinct specimens of gold. A first strand of objections has been completely exhausted. Indeed, since the mutual absence between gold and bracelet, as well as the coexistence of their mutual absence with their coreferentiality, have both been dismissed, it only remains to accept their non-difference; that is, the negation of their mutual absence (anyonyābhāva-atyantābhāva; ; cf. §7). Thus, it is here no longer a matter of distinguishing the bracelet from the gold of which it is made, but of possibly differentiating one golden artifact from another one, in consideration of the fact that they are all nothing but gold. In the light of the fact that the gold is neither identical nor mutually absent with regard to the bracelet, what is the relation between a golden bracelet and a golden crown?

In order to answer this question, let us first consider in more detail the truth values of formula P2.[44] , (t)‘A bracelet (b) is non-different from a specimen of gold (h)’:

  1. A.

    h\(\overline{{B}^{^{\prime}}}\) ; i.e., ‘A specimen of gold does not belong to the complement of the singleton A certain bracelet’, for ; i.e., ‘The complement of the singleton A certain bracelet = What is not identical to a certain bracelet’;

  2. B.

    h\(\overline{{B}^{^{\prime}}}\) → h ∈B′, for card(B′) = 1, since B′ = {b}; that is, ‘If condition A, then a specimen of gold belongs to the singleton A certain bracelet, for cardinality equal to one, since the singleton A certain bracelet possesses only a certain bracelet as its element’;

  3. C.

    *⟨h, b⟩∈I ∧ (h, b)∈B′, for card(B′) = 1; i.e., ‘A specimen of gold and a bracelet do not satisfy the relation of identity; nevertheless, being the very same object, they both belong to the same singleton’.

Nonetheless, it is likewise true that other gold artifacts do exist indeed, such as crowns (m). It will be thus symmetrically obtained:

[50a]

yad atyantābhāvīyapratiyogitā-avacchedakāvacchinna-paryāptitvaṃ tad ekatva-nirūpitam; tatra yaiva atyantābhāvīyapratiyogitā hāṭaka-niṣṭha-mukuṭa-nirūpita-sāmānādhikaraṇyatā-avacchedakāvacchinnā sā anyonyābhāvīyapratiyogitā-nirūpitā, eṣaiva anyonyābhāvīyapratiyogitā mukuṭa-nirūpitā, tadviparyayeṇa ca; (t)‘A crown (m) is not the counterpositive of a difference with respect to a specimen of gold’; iff:

  1. A.

    h1 ∈(|ht| = H) ∧ m ∈(|mt| = M), for TvN; that is, ‘A specimen of gold belongs to the set Gold’, and ‘A crown belongs to the set Crowns’;

  2. B.

    h1\(\overline{{M}^{^{\prime}}}\); i.e., ‘A specimen of gold does not belong to the complement of the singleton A certain crown’ (for , ‘The complement of the singleton A certain crown = What is not identical to a certain crown’);

  3. C.

    h1\(\overline{{M}^{^{\prime}}}\) → h1 ∈M′, for card(M′) = 1, since M′ = {m}; that is, ‘If condition B, then a specimen of gold belongs to the singleton A certain crown, for cardinality equal to one, since the singleton A certain crown possesses only a certain crown as its element’;

  4. D.

    *⟨h1, m⟩∈I ∧ (h1, m)∈M′; i.e., ‘A specimen of gold and a crown do not satisfy the relation of identity; nevertheless, being the very same object, they both belong to singleton A certain crown’.

In order to make all the features of this new perspective explicit, along with all its related difficulties, the notion of cardinality of a relation will once again prove helpful. At its simplest, the key point regarding the preceding provisional premises—[44] and [50a]—is that two alternative scenarios are here at stake: ultimately, either it comes down to the admission that there is only one indistinguishable occurrence of gold (i.e., h = h1), which is nonsensical, or that there are distinct and distinguishable ones (i.e., hh1).

‘This Very Same Thing’ (8.1)

In a first possibility, let us assume that the gold—which is non-different from the crown, being the latter nothing but gold—is also not-differentiable from a bracelet, which is equally made of gold. Thereby, nothing less and nothing more than an instance of gold, not further specified, is here referred to. According to this first configuration, through the combination of [44] and [50a] truth values, the following will be obtained:

  1. A.

    (*) h = h1; in the meaning of: ⟨h, h1⟩∈I, that is, ‘h and h1 are identical, being the very same specimen of gold’, since no other property is here available in order to make a further distinction;

  2. B.

    (*) ; respectively: ‘A specimen of gold does not belong to the complement of the singleton A certain bracelet (for: complement of singleton A certain bracelet = What is not identical to a certain bracelet)’; in parallel, ‘A specimen of gold does not belong to the complement of the singleton A certain crown’ (for: complement of singleton A certain crown = What is not identical to a certain crown)’;

  3. C.

    (*) (h\(\overline{{B}^{^{\prime}}}\)h1\(\overline{{M}^{^{\prime}}}\)) (h ∈B′∧ h1 ∈M′) (for: card(B′) = 1, B′ = {b}; and card(M’) = 1, M′ = {m}); i.e., if condition B, then ‘A specimen of gold belongs to the singleton A certain bracelet’ (for a cardinality equal to one, since this singleton contains only one bracelet); in parallel, ‘A specimen of gold belongs to the singleton A certain crown’ (for a cardinality equal to one, since this singleton contains only one crown);

  4. D.

    (*) (h ∈B′∧ h1 ∈M′) ((h, b)∈B′∧ (h1, m)∈M′); that is, if condition C, then ‘A specimen of gold and a certain bracelet belong to the same singleton A certain bracelet’; in parallel, ‘A specimen of gold and a certain crown belong to the same singleton A certain crown’;

  5. E.

    (*) (h = h1) ∧ ((h, b)∈B′ ∧ (h1, m)∈M′) ((h = h1), b, m) ∈(M′ = B′); i.e., if condition A and condition D, then ‘A specimen of gold, a bracelet and a crown belong the to the singleton A certain crown, which coincides with the singleton A certain bracelet’.

In other words, if the specimen of gold which is not the counterpositive of a difference with respect to a bracelet (since, according to , it is the same single object) is indistinguishable from the specimen of gold which in turn is not the counterpositive of a difference with respect to a crown, then nothing can prevent that the bracelet and crown themselves turn out to be one and the same: ; that is, *‘A bracelet is not the counterpositive of a difference with respect to a crown’. Thereby, mukuṭaṃ kaṭakam (*m.Ṇb, or *‘A bracelet is a crown’), which is plainly absurd. As expected, under this hypothesis, every relatum collapses into the identity of a single object. If that were the case, the state of affairs termed as ‘double occurrence’ (cf. §5.1) would reappear in a possibly even more arguable version: so to speak, in a sort of ‘double double occurrence’ or dvidviravabhāsa. In point of fact, the only acknowledgeable difference would be here the introduction of a third element, the crown, qua relational medium between gold and bracelet. Thus, according to the pattern of a repeated double occurrence: if *⟨h, b⟩∈I, then ⟨h, h⟩∈I; if *⟨h, m⟩∈I, then ⟨h, h⟩∈I; ergo, *⟨b, m⟩∈I, since anew ⟨h, h⟩∈I. That is: [a] a bracelet is non-different from a specimen of gold, it is thus *identical to that specimen of gold; therefore, a specimen of gold is identical to a specimen of gold; [b] a crown is non-different from a specimen of gold, it is thus *identical to that specimen of gold; thereby, a specimen of gold is thus identical to itself; [c] starting from these premises, it follows that *‘A bracelet is identical to a crown’, by virtue of the fact that ‘A specimen of gold is identical to itself’. Nevertheless, as with the options already discarded, there is no more room for any supposed substitutivity between indiscernibles or for a generic application of transitivity (cf. TKN; § 5.1).

Distinct Specimens of Gold (8.2)

In a second possibility, that gold which is non-different from the bracelet is more suitably said not to be the very same gold of which the crown is made. Since two distinct specimens of gold are here at stake, the cardinality of the relata under exam consequently increases to two. It follows that:

  1. A.

    hh1; i.e., h and h1, in formulae [44] and [50a], are distinct specimens of gold;

  2. B.

    h\(\overline{{{\text{B}}}^{^{\prime}}}\) (cf. § 8.1, condition B);

  3. C.

    (h\(\overline{{{\text{B}}}^{^{\prime}}}\)h1\(\overline{{{\text{M}}}^{^{\prime}}}\)) (h ∈B′∧ h1 ∈M′); for: card(B′) = 1, B′ = {b}, and card(M’) = 1, M′ = {m} (cf. § 8.1, condition C);

  4. D.

    (hh1) ∧ (h ∈B′ ∧ h1 ∈M′) (b ∈B′) ≠ (m ∈M′); that is, if h and h1 are distinct specimens of gold which respectively belong to the singletons A certain bracelet and A certain crown, then the bracelet which belongs to the singleton A certain bracelet is different from the crown which belongs to the singleton A certain crown;

  5. E.

    (b ∈B′) ≠ (m ∈M′) b, m⟩∉ ; that is, if the bracelet which belongs to the singleton A certain bracelet is different from the crown which belongs to the singleton A certain crown, then the bracelet and the crown are not coreferential;

  6. F.

    b, m⟩∉ Ṇ → card(B′, M′) = 2; that is, the bracelet and the crown are not coreferential, the cardinality of the singletons A certain bracelet and A certain crown is equal to two.

In the case where the bracelet and the crown appear as distinct occurrences of the property gold-ness, then those very bracelet and crown, which in themselves are nothing but instances of gold, turn out to be two distinct objects, reciprocally disjunct and not coreferential at all. This condition, in point of fact, opens a new scenario. Although not mutually coreferential, both the bracelet and the crown are not to be considered the counterpositive of a difference with respect to the property gold-ness (cf. [44] and [50a]). From this, it might be provisionally deduced that only gold is what exists here (vastusat), by reason of the obliteration or “lack of manifestation” (a-pratibhāsana) of every other concurrent qualification, with respect to the two occurrences of gold-ness which are here at stake. In consideration of the fact that solely the property gold-ness is involved for the time being, the following state of affairs clearly emerges: (b ∈(|ht| = H)) ∧ (m ∈(|ht| = H)), for H ={m, b, h3, …, hn}; that is, ‘A crown (m) and a bracelet (b) both belong to the set Gold, qua proper occurrences of the property gold-ness, along with many others (h3, …, hn)’. It should be noted that the proper elements m and b of the set Gold are first exclusively defined by their own sole property which is here described; that is, gold-ness, and not otherwise. Crown and bracelet are consequently only proper names of two elements of the set Gold, this latter being here the sole reality (vastusat). Under this perspective—according to which m and b are nothing but gold, although not the very same specimen of gold—the crown and the bracelet, along with all the other elements of the set Gold, turn out to be stricto sensu equivalent (E, tulyatva) occurrences of the same property, hāṭakatva. On the model of P2.§2, formulae [8]–[11], it might thus be stated that:

[50b] (b . htE ⌞(m . ht))⌝ ℕ ⌞(≥ 2t)

yat paryāptitvaṃ tulyatvāvacchinnaṃ tad dvitvādi-nirūpitam, etad eva tulyatvaṃ ca kaṭaka-niṣṭha-hāṭakatva-avacchinnaṃ mukuṭa-niṣṭha-hāṭakatva-nirūpitaṃ ca; (t)‘A bracelet and a crown are equivalent occurrences of the property gold-ness’; iff (mb) ∧ ((m, b) ∈ (|ht| = H)) ∧ card(H) 2; that is, ‘A bracelet and a crown are distinct occurrences of gold-ness, thereby they both belong to the set Gold, which in turn must have a cardinality at least equal to two’.

The hypothesis under consideration—while aiming at expanding the provisional result according to which there is no difference, that is, mutual exclusion, between bracelet and crown, since only gold is real (vastusat)—entails, as an unintended consequence (prasaṅga), the obliteration (a-pratibhāsana) of every concurrent property. Thereby, every occurrence of gold-ness ends up with being merely equivalent (E) and consequently indistinguishable (“na bhidyeran”) from one another. Assertion [50b] is undoubtedly true: indeed, a gold bracelet and a gold crown, along with all the other proper elements of the set Gold, are equivalent with respect to the property gold-ness. Nevertheless, once [50b] has been accepted, it does not allow any further distinction within those true occurrences of gold as sole reality. The said occurrences might be then melted, sold or exchanged, observed as incorruptible or resistant to chemical reactions, etc., according to what can be broadly done with gold in its indeterminate aspect. Yet, how could it be possible to identify any different functions or properties of these gold occurrences, such as being an artifact, and not a nugget, designed to be put upon the head, and not worn on the wrist? Even though it is an established fact that assertion [50b] is not false in any respect, it remains no less true that it discards a considerable amount of crucial information. As a rule, in order for a bracelet to be worn as indeed it is, the property bracelet-hood must not be ignored—lest also an ingot be worn on the wrist. Indeed, if the property bracelet-hood never appeared, every possible effect of gold-ness would collapse into the indistinguishableness of the common cause qua sole reality. Consequently, VM notes, we are again pushed back to the original starting point: if there is non-difference with respect to the cause—that is, the gold—yet difference still appears to stand regarding the effects—such as crowns or bracelets. Apropos, VM sharply remarks that:

“in reason of the recurrence (anuvṛtti) of the property Being (sattā), which [necessarily] occurs (anugam) in every single existent (sarvavastu)Footnote 31, [if that property were considered solely], there would not be [any possibility] of distinction (vibhāga) [by means of assertions such as] ‘This one here, not that one; [or] ‘This [appears] in such a manner, not that’Footnote 32, due to the absence of every discriminative (viveka) prover (hetu) concerning any object, anywhere, any time, in any way. In the same manner, in case gold were recognized from a distance [qua gold solely], then its [possible further] particularizations (viśeṣa)—such as earrings, etc.—would not be the object of any desire of knowledge, by reason of their non-difference from gold, which [instead, has already been fully] known”.Footnote 33

Just like ‘Bachelors are unmarried men’ and ‘All bodies are extended’, so sattayā sarvavastūni, or ‘By [reason of] Being, every being is [something rather than nothing]’. The property sattā allows us to conclusively identify real beings from unreal ones, such as a hare’s horn, but never to distinguish any element within the domain of real, due to the obliteration of every further distinctive property. It follows that defining a golden crown solely as an occurrence of the property sattā constitutes, once more, a clear instance of ativyāpti; that is, over-application: ‘What is a crown?’, *‘Something existent’. In parallel, with respect to a golden crown qua gold solely, it could be thus improperly concluded that: *hāṭaka-mukuṭasya hāṭakatvavattvam eva asādhāraṇadharmam iti, ato hāṭaka-mukuṭasya ākaraja-tejo-dravyavattvam eva asādhāraṇadharmam iti ativyāpti-doṣa-lakṣaṇam; *‘Goldness, is the peculiar property defining a golden crown, that is, being a substance of the mineral fire kind; [yet], this is a loose definition, for over-application’.Footnote 34

In the Manner of a Conclusion (9)

Making use of the tools which have been refined in P1&P2, some significant results have been highlighted here and secured by VM’s dialectical spiral movements. Whereas there is no possibility, in VM’s view, of instantaneous apparitions (I-Hy) and transformational continua (C-Hy), only permanence tout court (P-Hy) still stands its ground. NN logic has then proved able to escape in its expressions from the conceptual trap of the structural reference to a ‘third man’ and to be a valid alternative to the standard contemporary logic. Moreover, TKN and DSN have definitively excluded the appeal both to identity and difference—along with all their compromise variations, mediations, coordinations, and juxtapositions—as viable strategies to give an account of the golden crown microsimulation model. As SVN imposes (cf. P1.§4, P2.§4), when we are talking about a golden crown, we are talking about crowns. Everything else is just contradictory. The introduction of the additional label of ‘refined definition’ (pariṣkāra-lakṣaṇa) in epistemological taxonomy secures the now inescapable truth value of qualified cognition regarding that crown. Therefore, whilst acknowledging that bracelets and crowns have to be correctly known to be properly worn, it can thus be concluded that—in compliance with the counterfactual definition of non-difference as expressed in P2.[34]—whenever a further property is correctly known as coreferential to another one, although to different levels of generality, the former can no longer be illegitimately obliterated, lest a considerable amount of information become lost and contradictions be generated. This outcome calls for a redefinition of causality and opens new possibilities of complex considerations in which plexuses of properties are involved in the most rigorous non-difference—which will cast new light on the heuristic potential non-dualistic accounts. This is a crucial issue that will need to be handled with great clarity in the last section of this project.