Skip to main content
Log in

Relational Formulation of Quantum Measurement

  • Published:
International Journal of Theoretical Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Quantum measurement and quantum operation theory is developed here by taking the relational properties among quantum systems, instead of the independent properties of a quantum system, as the most fundamental elements. By studying how the relational probability amplitude matrix is transformed and how mutual information is exchanged during measurement, we derive the formulation that is mathematically equivalent to the traditional quantum measurement theory. More importantly, the formulation results in significant conceptual consequences. We show that for a given quantum system, it is possible to describe its time evolution without explicitly calling out a reference system. However, description of a quantum measurement must be explicitly relative. Traditional quantum mechanics assumes a super observer who can instantaneously know the measurement results from any location. For a composite system consists space-like separated subsystems, the assumption of super observer must be abandoned and the relational formulation of quantum measurement becomes necessary. This is confirmed in the resolution of EPR paradox. Information exchange is relative to a local observer in quantum mechanics. Different local observers can achieve consistent descriptions of a quantum system if they are synchronized on the information regarding outcomes from any measurement performed on the system. It is suggested that the synchronization of measurement results from different observers is a necessary step when combining quantum mechanics with the Relativity Theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Traditional quantum mechanics does not provide a theoretical description of Process 1. In the Copenhagen Interpretation, this is considered as the “collapse’ of the wave function into an eigenstate of the measured observable. The nature of this wave function collapse has been debated over many decades. Recent interpretations of quantum theory advocate that the wave function simply encodes the information that an observe can describe on the quantum system. Therefore, it is an epistemic, rather than ontological, variable. In this view, the collapse of wave function is just an update of the observer’s description on the condition of knowing the measurement outcome. For example, Quantum Bayesian theory [17, 18] formulates how Bayesian theorem can be utilized to describe such process. The relational argument of the wave function “collapse” is presented in Section 3.

  2. See Section 2.3 for the definition of entanglement.

  3. However, there is speculation that quantum mutual information should be defined as I(S,A) = H(ρS) − H(ρSA), see remark in Ref. [22]

  4. From (16), the reduced density operator of S is \(\hat {\rho }=Tr_{A}(|{\Psi }_{1}\rangle \langle {\Psi }_{1}|)={\sum }_{m}\hat {M}_{m}|\psi _{0}\rangle \langle \psi _{0}|\hat {M}_{m}^{\dag }={\sum }_{m} p_{m}|\psi _{m}\rangle \langle \psi _{m}|\). Thus \(H(R^{\prime })=-Tr(\hat {\rho }ln(\hat {\rho }))=-{\sum }_{m}p_{m}ln(p_{m})\).

  5. Note that if \(R_{ij}=c^{\prime }_{i}d^{\prime }_{j}\), \(\varphi ^{\prime }=d^{\prime }c^{\prime }_{i} \ne \varphi \). We do not prove \(R_{ij}=c_{i}d^{\prime }_{j}\) here but only show it is a possible decomposition. The proof is not necessary because our goal is to show it is possible to describe S without calling out A.

  6. One may argue that if we include the observer herself into the composite system S + A + O, the entire composite system can be treated as an isolated system and described as going through a unitary process. However the inclusion of O into the described system means there is yet another apparatus is involved that can measure the S + A + O composite system, thus it means a change of observer by definition. Furthermore, such approach still cannot explain why a single outcome is selected at the end of measurement. In fact, the decoherence theory follows such reasoning by considering O as environment of the apparatus. But the decoherence theory does not explain why at the end of a measurement a single outcome is singled out from all possible outcomes after decoherence takes place. The Quantum Bayesian Theory models Process 1 as a probability update after additional data is collected. Obviously, the Bayesian probability update is not a unitary process.

  7. The role of a privileged observer is also proposed in Ref [10] in the effort to resolve the classical and quantum world separation issue in the Copenhagen Interpretation. This privileged system is similar to the super observer (or, super-apparatus) contains collection of “all the macroscopic objects around us” [10].

  8. Note that \(|\alpha _{l}\rangle =\frac {1}{\sqrt {2}}(|\alpha _{u}\rangle +|\alpha _{d}\rangle )\) and \(|\alpha _{r}\rangle =\frac {1}{\sqrt {2}}(|\alpha _{u}\rangle -|\alpha _{d}\rangle )\)

  9. Such an approximation may not be always possible if the interaction from the environment cannot be isolated. Suppose the observed system S is interacting with the environmental system E. Changing the boundary to include E, we have S + E. But S + E is interacting with a larger surrounding environmental system E, and so on. One cannot describe the composite system as unitary process unless extending the boundary to the whole Universe.

References

  1. Bohr, N.: Quantum mechanics and physical reality. Nature 136, 65 (1935)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Bohr, N.: Can quantum mechanical description of physical reality be considered completed? Phys. Rev. 48, 696–702 (1935)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Jammer, M.: The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics: The Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics in Historical Perspective Chapter, vol. 6. Wiley-Interscience, New York (1974)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Everett, H.: Relative state formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 29, 454 (1957)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Wheeler, J. A.: Assessment of everett’s “relative state” formulation of quantum theory. Rev. Mod. Phys. 29, 463 (1957)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. DeWitt, B. S.: Quantum mechanics and reality. Phys. Today 23, 30 (1970)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Zurek, W. H.: Environment-induced superselection rules. Phys. Rev. D 26, 1862 (1982)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  8. Zurek, W. H.: Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical. Rev. Mod. Phys. 75, 715 (2003)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Schlosshauer, M.: Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretation of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 76, 1267–1305 (2004)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  10. Rovelli, C.: Relational quantum mechanics. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 35, 1637–1678 (1996)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Smerlak, M., Rovelli, C.: Relational EPR. Found. Phys. 37, 427–445 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Transsinelli, M.: Relational quantum mechanics and probability. Found. Phys. 48, 1092–1111 (2018)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Yang, J. M.: A relational formulation of quantum mechanics. Sci. Rep. 8, 13305 (2018). arXiv:1706.01317

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  14. Yang, J.M.: A relational approach to quantum mechanics part III: path integral implementation. arXiv:http://arXiv.org/abs/1807.01583

  15. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N.: Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47, 777–780 (1935)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Von Neumann, J.: Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics, Chap. VI. Princeton University Press, Princeton Translated by Robert T. Beyer (1932/1955)

  17. Fuchs, C. A.: Quantum mechanics as quantum information (and only a little more). arXiv:quant-ph/0205039 (2002)

  18. Fuchs, C. A., Schark, R.: Quantum-Bayesian coherence: the no-nonsense version. Rev. Mod. Phys. 85, 1693–1715 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  19. Nielsen, M. A., Chuang, I. L.: Quantum Computation and Quantum Information. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Horodecki, R., Horodecki, P., Horodecki, M., Horodecki, K.: Quantum entanglement. Rev. Mod. Phys. 81, 865–942 (2009)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Hayashi, M., Ishizaka, S., Kawachi, A., Kimura, G., Ogawa, T.: Introduction to quantum information science, page 90, 150, 152, vol. 197. Springer, Berlin (2015)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Nielsen, M. A., Chuang, I. L.: Quantum computation and quantum information, page 366, vol. 564. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Allahverdyan, A. E., Roger Balian, R., Nieuwenhuizen, T. M.: Understanding quantum measurement from the solution of dynamical models. Phys. Rep. 525, 1–166 (2013)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Breuer, H.-P., Petruccione, F.: The theory of open quantum systems. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2007)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Rivas, A., Huelga, S. F.: Open Quantum System, an Introduction. Springer, Berlin (2012)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Smolin, L.: Three Roads to Quantum Gravity. Basic Books, New York (2017)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jianhao M. Yang.

Appendices

Appendix A: Theorem 1

Theorem 1

H(R) = 0 if and only if the matrix elementRijcan be decomposed asRij = cidj,wherecianddjare complex numbers.

Proof

According to the singular value decomposition, the relational matrix R can be decomposed to R = UDV, where D is rectangular diagonal and both U and V are N × N and M × M unitary matrix, respectively. This gives ρ = RR = U(DD)U. If H(R) = 0, matrix ρ is a rank one matrix, therefore DD is diag{1, 0, 0...}. This means D is a rectangular diagonal matrix with only one eigenvalue eiϕ. Expanding the matrix product R = UDV gives

$$ R_{ij}=\sum\limits_{nm}U_{in}D_{nm}V_{mj}=U_{i1}e^{i\phi}V_{1j}. $$
(A1)

We just choose ci = Ui1 and dj = eiϕV1j to get Rij = cidj. Conversely, if Rij = cidj, R can be written as outer product of two vectors,

$$ R = \left( \begin{array}{llll} c_{1} & c_{2} & {\ldots} & c_{n} \end{array}\right)^{T} \times \left( \begin{array}{llll} d_{1} & d_{2} & {\ldots} & d_{m} \end{array}\right). $$
(A2)

Considering vector C1 = {c1,c2,…,cn} as an eigenvector in Hilbert space \(\mathcal {H}_{S}\), one can use the Gram-Schmidt procedure [19] to find orthogonal basis set C2,…,Cn. Similarly, considering vector D1 = {d1,d2,…,dm} as an eigenvector in Hilbert space \(\mathcal {H}_{A}\), one can find orthogonal basis set D2,…,Dm. Under the new orthogonal eigenbasis, R becomes a rectangular diagonal matrix D = diag{1, 0, 0...}. Therefore R = UDV where U and V are two unitary matrices associated with the eigenbasis transformations. Then ρ = RR = U(DD)U, and DD = diag{1, 0, 0...} is a square diagonal matrix. Since the eigenvalues of similar matrices are the same, the eigenvalues of ρ are (1, 0, ...), thus H(R) = 0. □

Appendix B: Decomposition of the Unitary Operator of a Bipartite System

If there is interaction between S and A, and the initial state of S + A is a product state, the global unitary operator can be decomposed into a set of measurement operators that satisfies (16). The proof shown here closely follows idea from Ref. [22]. Denote the initial state is product state, |Ψ0〉 = |ψ0S|ϕ0A. First we change the eigenbasis for A through a local unitary operator \(I_{S}\otimes \hat {U}_{A}\) such that ϕ0 is the first eigenvector of the orthogonal eigenbasis, i.e., \((I_{S}\otimes \hat {U}_{A})|\psi _{0}\rangle _{S} \otimes |\phi _{0}\rangle _{A} = |\psi _{0}\rangle _{S}\otimes |a_{0}\rangle _{A}\), and {|am〉} forms an orthogonal eigenbasis of A. The global unitary operator is changed to \(\hat {U}_{SA}^{\prime } = \hat {U}_{SA}(I_{S}\otimes \hat {U}_{A}^{\dag })\). Define a linear operator \(\hat {M}_{m} = \langle a_{m}|\hat {U}_{SA}^{\prime }| a_{0}\rangle \). The set of operators \(\{\hat {M}_{m}\}\) is what we are looking for, since we can verify it satisfies (16),

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \hat{U}_{SA}|\psi_{0}\rangle|\phi_{0}\rangle & =&\hat{U}_{SA}^{\prime}|\psi_{0}\rangle|a_{0}\rangle \\ & =& \sum\limits_{m} |a_{m}\rangle\langle a_{m}| \hat{U}_{SA}^{\prime}|\psi_{0}\rangle|a_{0}\rangle \\ & =& \sum\limits_{m}\hat{M}_{m}|\psi_{0}\rangle|a_{m}\rangle. \end{array} $$
(B1)

The completeness condition can also be verified,

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \sum\limits_{m}\hat{M}_{m}^{\dag}\hat{M}_{m} & =& \sum\limits_{m}\langle a_{0}|\hat{U}_{SA}^{\prime\dag}|a_{m}\rangle\langle a_{m}|\hat{U}_{SA}^{\prime}|a_{0}\rangle \\ & =& \langle a_{0}|\hat{U}_{SA}^{'\dag}\hat{U}_{SA}^{\prime}|a_{0}\rangle = I_{S}. \end{array} $$
(B2)

Appendix C: Theorem 2

Theorem 2

Applying operator\(\hat {Q}\otimes \hat {O}\)overthe composite systemS + Ais equivalent to change the relational matrix R toR = QROT,where the superscript T represents a transposition.

Proof

Denote the initial state vector of the composite system as \(|{\Psi }_{0}\rangle ={\sum }_{ij}R_{ij}|s_{i}\rangle |a_{j}\rangle \). Apply the composite operator \(\hat {Q}(t)\otimes \hat {O}(t)\) to the initial state,

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} |{\Psi}_{1}\rangle & =& (\hat{Q}\otimes \hat{O}) \sum\limits_{ij} R_{ij} |s_{i}\rangle \otimes |a_{j}\rangle \\ & =& \sum\limits_{ij}R_{ij}\hat{Q}|s_{i}\rangle\otimes \hat{O}|a_{j}\rangle \\ & =& \sum\limits_{ij}\sum\limits_{mn}R_{ij}Q_{mi}O_{nj}|s_{m}\rangle\otimes |a_{n}\rangle \\ & =& \sum\limits_{mn}(\sum\limits_{ij}Q_{mi}R_{ij}O^{T}_{jn})|s_{m}\rangle\otimes |a_{n}\rangle \\ & =&\sum\limits_{mn}(QRO^{T})_{mn}|s_{m}\rangle|a_{n}\rangle \end{array} $$
(C1)

where T represents the transposition of matrix. Compared the above equation to (7) for the definition of |Ψ1〉, it is clear that the relational matrix is changed to R = QROT. □

Appendix D: Probability in Selective Measurement

Given the composite system S + A is described by (15), the reduced density matrix of S can be defined

$$ \begin{array}{ll} {\displaystyle}\hat{\rho}_{S} &{\displaystyle} =Tr_{A}|{\Psi}\rangle\langle{\Psi}| = \sum\limits_{ii^{\prime}}(\sum\limits_{k}R_{ik}R^{*}_{i^{\prime}k})|s_{i}\rangle\langle s_{i^{\prime}}| \\ &{\displaystyle} =\sum\limits_{ii^{\prime}}(RR^{\dag})_{ii^{\prime}}|s_{i}\rangle\langle s_{i^{\prime}}| \end{array} $$
(D1)

and the probability of finding event |si〉 occurred to S is calculated by (10). Similarly, the probability of event |aj〉 occurred to A is \({p^{A}_{j}}={\sum }_{i}p_{ij}={\sum }_{i}|R_{ij}|^{2}\). This can be more elegantly written by introducing a partial projection operator \(I^{S}\otimes \hat {P}_{j}^{A}\) where \(\hat {P}_{j}^{A}=|a_{j}\rangle \langle a_{j}|\). It is easy to verify that

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} {p_{j}^{A}} & =&\langle{\Psi}|I^{S}\otimes \hat{P}_{j}^{A}|{\Psi}\rangle \\ & =&\langle{\Psi}|a_{j}\rangle\langle a_{j}|{\Psi}\rangle =\sum\limits_{i}|R_{ij}|^{2}. \end{array} $$
(D2)

Appendix E: Open Quantum System

The measurement theory described in this paper is consistent with the open quantum system (OQS) theory. OQS studies the dynamics when a quantum system interacts with its environment E [19, 24, 25]. Such interaction can result in entanglement and information exchange between the quantum system S and the environment system E. Recall the definition of apparatus in Section 2.1 includes the interacting environment as one type of apparatus, if we replace the environment system E with the apparatus system A, the OQS theory gives the same formulations as shown in Section 3.

First, we give a brief review of the OQS theory. Suppose the initial composite state for the quantum system and environment is described by a density matrix ρSE, the interaction between S and E changes the density matrix \(\rho _{SE} \rightarrow \hat {U}\rho _{SE}\hat {U}^{\dag }\). The resulting density matrix of S is \(\rho ^{\prime }_{S} = Tr_{E}(\hat {U}\rho _{SE}\hat {U}^{\dag })\). Denote the orthogonal eigen basis of the environment {|ek〉}. Since the orthogonal eigenbasis of the environment is not necessary the same eigenbasis that diagonalizes ρE, we further denote the spectral decomposition of ρE as \(\rho _{E} ={\sum }_{m}\lambda _{m}|\tilde {e}_{m}\rangle \langle \tilde {e}_{m}|\). Assumed the initial state of the quantum system plus environment is a product state, i.e., ρSE = ρSρE, the density operator of S after the interaction with the environment is

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \rho^{\prime}_{S} & =& {\Lambda} (\rho_{S}) \\ & =& \sum\limits_{mk}|\lambda_{m}|^{2} \langle e_{k}| \hat{U}(\rho_{S}\otimes |\tilde{e}_{m}\rangle\langle \tilde{e}_{m}| )\hat{U}^{\dag}|e_{k}\rangle \\ & =& \sum\limits_{mk}E_{mk}\rho_{S} E_{mk}^{\dag}. \end{array} $$
(E1)

where \(E_{mk}=\lambda _{m}\langle e_{k}| \hat {U}|\tilde {e}_{m}\rangle \) and satisfies the completeness condition \({\sum }_{mk}E_{mk}E_{mk}^{\dag } =I\). Equation (E1) is the Kraus representation of the linear map Λ. It is proved that Λ can be a Kraus representation if and only if it can be induced from an extended system with initial condition ρSE = ρSρE [25]. If ρE = |e0〉〈e0| is a pure state, the linear map is further simplified to \({\Lambda } (\rho _{S})={\sum }_{k}E_{k}\rho _{S} E_{k}^{\dag }\) and \(E_{k}=\langle e_{k}| \hat {U}|e_{0}\rangle \). The operator set {Ek} forms a POVM, and Λ(ρS) is a Complete Positive Trace Preserving (CPTP) map [21]. To connect to the measurement theory, suppose the measurement outcome m corresponds to an orthogonal state |ϕm〉 of E, and represented by a projection operator \(\hat {P}_{m}=|\phi _{m}\rangle \langle \phi _{m}|\),

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} {\rho_{S}^{m}} & =&{\Lambda}_{m} (\rho_{S}) \\ & =& \sum\limits_{k}\langle e_{k}| \hat{P}_{m}\hat{U}\rho_{S}\otimes |\tilde{e}_{0}\rangle\langle \tilde{e}_{0}| \hat{U}^{\dag}\hat{P}_{m}^{\dag}|e_{k}\rangle \\ & =& \langle\phi_{m}|\hat{U}|\tilde{e}_{0}\rangle\rho_{S}\langle \tilde{e}_{0}| \hat{U}^{\dag}|\phi_{m}\rangle{\sum}_{k}\langle k|\phi_{m}\rangle\langle\phi_{m}|k\rangle \\ & =& \hat{M}_{m}\rho_{S} \hat{M}_{m}^{\dag} \end{array} $$
(E2)

where \(\hat {M}_{m}=\langle \phi _{m}|\hat {U}|\tilde {e}_{0}\rangle \) is the operator defined on \(\mathcal {H}_{S}\). The probability of finding outcome m is \(p_{m}=Tr({\Lambda }_{m} (\rho _{S}))=Tr(\hat {M}_{m} \hat {M}_{m}^{\dag }\rho _{S})\).

It is evident that if we replace the environment system E with the apparatus system A, the OQS theory gives the same formulations as shown in Section 3. In the case of initial product state, (21) versus (E2) are effectively the same. Let’s consider the case of initial entangled state in the OQS context. Denote the initial system plus environment state as pure bipartite state |Ψ0〉. After the global unitary operation \(\hat {U}\) and subsequent projection \(I^{S}\otimes \hat {P}_{m}^{E}=I^{S}\otimes |\phi _{m}\rangle \langle \phi _{m}|\), the composite state becomes \(|{\Psi }_{1}\rangle =(I^{S}\otimes \hat {{P_{m}^{E}}})\hat {U}|{\Psi }_{0}\rangle \), take the partial trace over E, we get

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} {\rho^{S}_{m}} & =&Tr_{E}(|{\Psi}_{1}\rangle\langle{\Psi}_{1}| \\ & =& \langle\phi_{m}|\hat{U}_{SA}|{\Psi}_{0}\rangle\langle{\Psi}_{0}|\hat{U}_{SA}^{\dag}|\phi_{m}\rangle \\ & =& |\psi_{m}\rangle\langle\psi_{m}|. \end{array} $$
(E3)

This implies the resulting state for S is \(|\psi _{m}\rangle =\langle \phi _{m}|\hat {U}_{SA}|{\Psi }_{0}\rangle \), which is equivalent to (28). Taking a similar approach in deriving (29), we can express |ψm〉 in the eigenbasis derived from the Schmidt decomposition of |Ψ0〉. The result is \(|\psi _{m}\rangle = 1/\sqrt {p^{\prime }_{m}} {\sum }_{i} \hat {M}_{mi}|\tilde {s}_{i}\rangle \), where the definitions of \(\hat {M}_{mi}\) and \(p^{\prime }_{m}\) are the same as those in (29) except replacing the apparatus system A with the environment system E. The reduced density operator for S, \({\rho ^{S}_{m}}\), is given by

$$ {\rho_{S}^{m}} = \frac{1}{p^{\prime}_{m}}\sum\limits_{ij}\hat{M}_{mi}|\tilde{s}_{i}\rangle\langle \tilde{s}_{j}|\hat{M}_{mj}^{\dag} $$
(E4)

Equation (E4) can be considered as a generalization of (E2) when the initial state is entangled. There is no simple form of map Λm such that \({\rho _{S}^{m}}={\Lambda }_{m}(\rho _{S})\) where ρS is the initial density matrix of S. A different representation of \({\rho _{S}^{m}}\) can be derived by rewriting the initial state ρSE = ρSρE + ρcorr where ρcorr is a correlation term [25].

Appendix F: Mutual Information

Entanglement between the two systems is measured by the parameter E(ρ) as defined by (13). In Section 3, we also use the mutual information variable to measure the information exchange between the measuring system and the measured system. The mutual information between S and A is defined as I = H(ρS) + H(ρA) − H(ρSA), where H(ρSA) is the von Neumann entropy of the composite system S + A. For a composite system S + A that is described by a single relational matrix R, these two variables differ only by a factor of two. However, for a composite system of S + A that is described by an ensemble of relational matrices, the two variables can be very different. This is illustrated by two examples described below.

Case 1

S + A is in an entangled pure state described by \(|{\Psi }\rangle _{SA}={\sum }_{i}\lambda _{i}|s_{i}\rangle |a_{i}\rangle \) in Schmidt decomposition, where {λi} are the Schmidt coefficients. Subsystem S is in a mixed state. The entanglement measure is \(E(\rho _{S})= -{\sum }_{i}{\lambda _{i}^{2}}ln({\lambda _{i}^{2}})\) and the mutual information is \(I=-2{\sum }_{i}{\lambda _{i}^{2}}ln({\lambda _{i}^{2}})\).

Case 2

S + A is in a mixed state described by \(\rho _{SA}={\sum }_{i}{\lambda _{i}^{2}}|s_{i}\rangle |a_{i}\rangle \langle s_{i}|\langle a_{i}|\). In the case, \(H(\rho _{S})=H(\rho _{SA})=H(\rho _{diag})=-{\sum }_{i}{\lambda _{i}^{2}}ln({\lambda _{i}^{2}})\). ρSA is a separable bipartite state [20, 21]. There is no entanglement but there is mutual information since \(I=-{\sum }_{i}{\lambda _{i}^{2}}ln({\lambda _{i}^{2}})\). Essentially the composite system is a mixed ensemble of product states \(\{{\lambda _{i}^{2}}, |s_{i}\rangle |a_{i}\rangle \}\). One can infer that S is in |si〉 from knowing A is in |ai〉, however such mutual information is due to classical correlation. The probability of finding S in an eigenvector |si〉 is just the classical probability \({\lambda _{i}^{2}}\).

Although the reduced density operator for S, \(\rho _{S} = {\sum }_{i}{\lambda _{i}^{2}}|s_{i}\rangle \langle s_{i}|\), is the same in Case 1 and Case 2, the mutual information is different. More information is encoded in the pure bipartite state in Case 1. When S + A is described by \(|{\Psi }\rangle _{SA}={\sum }_{i}\lambda _{i}|s_{i}\rangle |a_{i}\rangle \), besides the inference information between S and A, there is additional indeterminacy due to the superposition at the composite system level. For instance, one cannot determine the composite system S + A is in |s0〉|a0〉 or |s1〉|a1〉 before measurement. More indeterminacy before measurement means more information can be gained from measurement. This also explains that in the EPR experiment, when Alice measures particle α, she does not only gain information about α, but also gain information about the composite system. Thus, she can predict the state of particle β. On the other hand, such indeterminacy does not exist when S + A is described by a mixture of product state as in Case 2. Since such indeterminacy is for the composite system as a whole, the reduced density operator for a subsystem S, ρS, cannot reflect the difference, therefore it appears the same in Case 1 and Case 2.

These two examples show that mutual information variable can substitute the entanglement measurement only when the composite system S + A is described by a single relational matrix R. To quantify change of quantum correlation during a measurement, the entanglement measurement is a more appropriate parameter.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yang, J.M. Relational Formulation of Quantum Measurement. Int J Theor Phys 58, 757–785 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10773-018-3973-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10773-018-3973-2

Keywords

Navigation