Skip to main content
Log in

What is Original in Merleau-Ponty’s View of the Phenomenological Reduction?

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Despite the recent increase of interest in the work of Merleau-Ponty there is still a persistent tendency to overlook the uniqueness of the philosophical position he advances in Phenomenology of Perception. In this article I present a reading of Merleau-Ponty’s account of the phenomenological reduction that explains how it is original. I do this by contrasting his presentation of the reduction with that of the early Husserl, highlighting how his emphasis on the phenomenology of the ‘perceived world’ leads him to reject Husserl’s conception of phenomenology as a ‘philosophical science,’ and the Kantian language in which the this account is framed. I go on to critically discuss the interpretations of the reduction advanced by Stephen Priest and Joel Smith as examples of readings that fail to fully grasp Merleau-Ponty’s account of the ‘natural attitude’ as resting on the inherent objectivizing structure that is built into perception itself. The way that these authors misinterpret Merleau-Ponty helps to make maximally clear the profound philosophical significance that he places on the phenomenology of the ‘perceived world’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I also draw on his further elaborations of this method in later texts, primarily: Merleau-Ponty(1964a, b).

  2. Merleau-Ponty also refers to this as ‘objectivism’ (Merleau-Ponty 2002: xxii). I use the two interchangeably.

  3. e.g., ‘The word ‘here’ applied to my body does not refer to a determinate position in relation to other positions or to external coordinates, but the laying down of the first co-ordinates … the situation of the body in face of its tasks’ (Merleau-Ponty 2002: 115).

  4. Although Heidegger’s ‘in-der-Welt-sein’ is also rendered as ‘being-in-the-world’ in the Macquarie and Robinson translation (Heidegger 1962), we should not automatically assume that Merleau-Ponty’s term is identical to Heidegger’s. In the original French Merleau-Ponty’s term is ‘être au monde’, and it is a translation of this term that is intended here. Donald A. Landes discusses this translation issue in Landes (2014: xlix).

  5. See, e.g., Merleau-Ponty (1963: pp. 188–189, 2002: 102).

  6. This formulation captures Merleau-Ponty’s concept of transcendental philosophy as ‘radical reflection,’ as Madison has pointed out (2004: 21). This theme is also emphasized in Langer (1989) and Dorfman (2007).

  7. As a result, Merleau-Ponty reconceives ‘eidetic reduction’ as a procedure that is only able to facilitate claims that are ultimately “contingent a priori” or “historical a priori” (see, e.g., Margolis 1991). Merleau-Ponty takes eidetic reduction to be a separate methodological procedure whose epistemic contribution is crucially derivative on the epoché and reduction. This is because they facilitate access to the ‘phenomenal field,’ which lays out the scope and limit of possible knowledge claims. I therefore view the interesting and important question of Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation of ‘eidetic reduction’ as outside the scope of this article.

References

  • Dorfman, E. (2007). Freedom, perception and radical reflection. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), Reading Merleau-Ponty: On “phenomenology of perception” (pp. 139–151). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, J. J. (2007). Historical dictionary of husserl’s philosophy. Lanham: Scarecrow Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, S. (2015). Merleau-Ponty’s transcendental theory of perception. In S. Gardner & M. Grist (Eds.), The transcendental turn (pp. 294–323). UK: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row.

  • Husserl, E. (1970). Crisis of the European sciences and transcendental Phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy (D. Carr, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Phenomenology (Encyclopaedia Brittanica article). In R. Zaner & D. Ihde (Eds.), Phenomenology and existentialism. New York: G.P. Putnam’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1982). Cartesian meditations (D. Cairns, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, First Book: General introduction to a pure phenomenology (F. Kersten, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, Second Book (R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Landes, D. A. (2014). Translator’s introduction. In M. Merleau-Ponty. phenomenology of perception (D.A. Landes, Trans.) (pp. xxx- li). London: Routledge.

  • Langer, M. (1989). Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology of perception: A guide and commentary. Basingstoke: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Madison, G. B. (1977). Phenomenology and existentialism: Husserl and the end of idealism. In F. A. Elliston & P. McCormick (Eds.), Husserl: Expositions and appraisals (pp. 238–268). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madison, G. B. (2004). The interpretive turn in phenomenology: A philosophical history. Symposium, 8(2), 397–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (1991). Phenomenology and metaphysics: Husserl, Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty. In M. C. Dillon (Ed.), Merleau-Ponty vivant (pp. 153–182). Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (2010). Pragmatism’s advantage. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1963). The structure of behaviour (A. L. Fisher, Trans.). Boston: Beacon Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (Ed.) (1964a). Phenomenology and the sciences of man. In The primacy of perception and other essays on phenomenological psychology, the philosophy of art, history and politics (pp. 43–95). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (Ed.) (1964b). The philosopher and his shadow. In Signs. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964c). Sense and non-sense. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the invisible. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2007). What is phenomenology? (T. Toadvine and L. Lawlor, Trans.). In T. Toadvine & L. Lawlor (Eds.), The Merleau-Ponty reader (pp. 55–68). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Priest, S. (1998). Merleau-Ponty. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (2005). Merleau-Ponty and the phenomenological reduction. Inquiry: An interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 48(6), 553–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2001). Husserl and transcendental intersubjectivity. Ohio: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher Pollard.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pollard, C. What is Original in Merleau-Ponty’s View of the Phenomenological Reduction?. Hum Stud 41, 395–413 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-018-9471-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-018-9471-y

Keywords

Navigation