Skip to main content
Log in

Event Semantics: A Husserlian Critique

  • Published:
Husserl Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Event semantics is concerned with the formal structure of sentences which appear to describe an event of some kind, e.g. ‘Brutus kills Caesar,’ or ‘My tooth fell out.’ Phenomenologists should be interested in work in this field, if they hope to rescue Husserl’s phenomenology of judgment from its narrow focus on copular judgments of the form ‘S is p.’ An adequate phenomenology of judgment must ultimately develop an account of judgments whose intentional correlates seem to be events, rather than states of affairs, since such judgments are ubiquitous. For this endeavor, existing work on the formal structure of event sentences provides a crucial foothold. However, phenomenologists cannot simply import semantic theories for their own use, without first evaluating them for phenomenological plausibility. This concern is particularly acute in the case of the widely-adopted “Davidsonian” approach, according to which the logical structure of event sentences diverges radically from natural language syntax. The Davidsonian form introduces a “covert” variable, which stands in for an event. Thus, the sentence ‘Brutus kills Caesar’ becomes, ‘There is an event e that is a killing of Caesar by Brutus.’ Such a theory, if correct, would have decisive consequences for the phenomenology of event sentences, and even of events themselves. Yet the introduction of covert variables in turn introduces—I argue—a covert intentional object, without assessing this idea for phenomenological plausibility. Building on Husserl’s phenomenology of predication, I develop a criterion for evaluating this hypothesis, and argue that the Davidsonian approach, as it stands, is phenomenologically untenable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Zlatev (2010) however, for a discussion of some deficiencies in the conception of phenomenology employed in “mainstream” cognitive linguistics.

  2. It is not self-evident that modifier-dropping entailments should be a matter of logical form. For contrary views and discussion, see Cresswell (1974) and Thomason & Stalnaker (1973).

  3. Such mechanisms have been proposed, of course. See Graves (1993), and Beaver and Condoravdi (2007).

  4. For arguments that we can, in fact, limit standby positions in a principled way, see Schwartz (1975) and Stanosz (1978).

  5. Whether we represent this as suggested, or as ʻWith(a knife, e),’ or in some other way, does not bear on the point at issue here, namely the use of event variables to explain entailment relations. Throughout the paper I will adopt the simplest possible Davidsonian forms.

  6. Landman (2000, pp. 2–15) provides a useful and thorough discussion of the parallels between the “classical semantic theory” for adjectives and the Davidsonian approach to adverbs.

  7. ʻThere is an event e which is a building of a house by Mary; and there is a time which is earlier than now, and which is the time when that event culminated.’

  8. ʻThere is an event which is a run by Mary, and which is holding now.’

  9. See Sect. 4, however, for discussion of a deficiency in Parsons’ proposal that arises precisely because it fails to capture apparent entailment relations.

  10. This is what Husserl describes “as an elucidation and clarification, as a more precise determination of what is indeterminate in the horizon-form” (1939, p. 140; 1973, p. 124).

  11. It is “bound to the immediate intuition of the substrate, whether this intuition is self-giving or reproductive” (1939, p. 231; 1973, p. 197).

  12. ʻThere is an event e, such that e is a burning, and the agent of e is Agatha, and the patient of e is wood.’

  13. ʻFor every event e, if e is a burning, then oxygen is consumed.’

  14. See Rothstein (1998, p. 5) for a brief discussion of the dispensability of anaphoric evidence. See Landman (2000, pp. 18–19) for an argument that Parsons’ ‘burnings’ argument is dispensable.

  15. The last conjunct could be rendered ʻTo(top of the hill, e),’ or in some more complex way. See fn. 5.

  16. ‘For a minute’ is marginally acceptable for (21), but only if we understand ‘to the top of the hill’ to mean ‘towards the top of the hill’.

  17. I include ‘vigorous’ here in order to force the reading of ‘running’ as a nominal, rather than a verbal gerundive. The verbal gerundive is marginally acceptable, as in ʻWe observed Melanie’s vigorously running to the top of the hill.’ But this is irrelevant, as ‘running’ here does not function as a noun, as is evident from its modification by an adverb.

  18. A rough logical form would be as follows, with ʻΘ(e′, e)’ standing in for whatever constitutive or causal relation holds between the two events: ʻ(Ǝe)(Running(e) ∧ Agent(Melanie, e) ∧ Vigorous(e) ∧ (Ǝe′)(Θ(e′, e) ∧ Run(e′) ∧ To-the-top-of-hill(e′))).’

  19. Pustejovsky (1991) does propose a semantics which multiplies the event arguments introduced by a verb, in order to account for complexities in event structure (e.g. transitions from one state to another). Yet since his theory is primarily designed to elucidate lexical structure (rather than entailment relations or anaphora) it does not necessarily imply that these events be cognitively realized as predicative subjects.

  20. For example, one could respond to (26)–(31) by suggesting the underlying form should not directly predicate ‘To-the-top-of-the-hill’ of an event. Instead it should indicate that the event stopped at the top of the hill, using e.g. the predication ‘End(top of the hill, e).’ ‘Melanie’s running stopped at the top of the hill’ certainly poses no problems.

  21. For a proposal along these lines, see Roeper (1987). While Roeper’s approach can hardly be called phenomenological, it is worth noting that it is motivated in part by his “semantic intuitions,” namely that nouns are referring expressions while verbs are not.

References

  • Asher, N. (1993). Reference to abstract objects in discourse. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, v. 50. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

  • Beaver, D., & Condoravdi, C. (2007). On the logic of verbal modification. In Proceedings of the sixteenth Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 3–9).

  • Bennett, J. (1988). Events and their names. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2002). Indexicality, binding, anaphora and a priori truth. Analysis, 62, 271–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M. J. (1974). Adverbs and events. Synthese, 28(3/4), 455–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1985). The logical form of action sentences. In Essays on actions and events. New York: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press.

  • Graves, P. (1993). Argument deletion without events. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 34, 607–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hua. XIX/1. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Erster Teil. U. Panzer (Ed.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Logical investigations. Volume 2. J.N. Findlay (Trans.). New York: Routledge, 2000.

  • Hua. XIX/2. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Zweiter Teil. U. Panzer (Ed.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Logical investigations. Volume 2. J.N. Findlay (Trans.). New York: Routledge, 2000.

  • Husserl, E. (1939). Erfahrung und Urteil: Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik. L. Landgrebe (Ed.). Prag: Academia Verlagsbuchhandl. Experience and judgment: Investigations in a genealogy of logic. J. Churchill & K. Ameriks (Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973.

  • Krifka, M. (1989). Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics. In R. Bartsch, J. F. A. K. van Benthem, & P. van Emde Boas (Eds.), Semantics and contextual expression. Providence: Foris Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (2000). Events and plurality: The Jerusalem lectures. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, Vol. 76. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Langacker, R. (2008). Cognitive grammar: A basic introduction. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lascarides, A. (1988). A formal semantic analysis of the progressive. Dissertation. University of Edinburgh.

  • Parsons, T. (1991). Events in the semantics of English: A study of subatomic semantics. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradelle, D. (2012). The phenomenological foundations of predicative structure. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1991). The syntax of event structure. Cognition, 41, 47–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roeper, P. (1987). Principles of abstraction for events and processes. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 16, 273–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S. (1998). Events and grammar. Studies in linguistics and philosophy, Vol. 70. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.

  • Schwartz, T. (1975). The logic of modifiers. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4, 361–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanosz, B. (1978). Some comments on the problem of logical form. Studia Logica, 37, 79–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (2003). Toward a cognitive semantics. Vol 1: Concept structuring systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Thomason, R., & Stalnaker, R. (1973). A semantic theory of adverbs. Linguistic Inquiry, 4, 195–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev, J. (2010). Phenomenology and cognitive linguistics. In S. Gallagher & D. Schmicking (Eds.), Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science. Dordrecht; London: Springer.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Matthew Ally supplied crucially helpful feedback for an earlier draft of this paper. A shorter version was presented at the 2017 meeting of the Husserl Circle; I am grateful for the suggestions and encouragement I received from attenders, and especially for the excellent comments presented by Corijn Van Mazijk. Support for this project was provided by a PSC-CUNY Award, jointly funded by The Professional Staff Congress and The City University of New York.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrés Colapinto.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Colapinto, A. Event Semantics: A Husserlian Critique. Husserl Stud 34, 123–143 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-017-9222-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-017-9222-3

Navigation