Skip to main content
Log in

Buffon, Species and the Forces of Reproduction

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Journal of the History of Biology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Throughout the Histoire naturelle Buffon was ever aware of epistemological issues involving the reproduction of species, the only beings in nature. By the 1760s he had come to believe that empirical evidence, the source of all human knowledge, revealed that reproduction was a physical process, involving a common living (minute, active, and lively) matter and material forces, all of which he traced to the foundational force of gravitational attraction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Buffon’s thirty-six volumes of the Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière (Paris: l’Imprimerle Royale, 1749–1789) has four large divisions: Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière, avec la description du cabinet du Roi (15 volumes, 1749–1767), Histoire naturelle des oiseaux (9 volumes, 1770–1783), Supplément à l’Histoire naturelle (7 volumes, 1774–1784), and the Histoire naturelle des minéraux (5 volumes, 1783–1788). References will be cited by the title of the division, the division volume number, and the page number. Abbreviations for the different divisions of the Histoire naturelle are as follows:

    HN Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière, avec la description du cabinet du Roi;

    HNM Histoire naturelle des minéraux; and

    HNS Supplément à l’Histoire naturelle.

    The Histoire naturelle des oiseaux is not cited.

    Unless otherwise indicated, citations are taken from the reproduction of the original Histoire naturelle at http://www.buffon.cnrs.fr, editors Thierry Hoquet and Pietro Corsi. Pietro Corsi is the original editor of this website. The website is password-protected, but a login request can be made at the contact address, buffon@huma-num.fr. The same edition of the HN (volumes 2, 4, 12, 13 & 14 cited herein) is also available online in scanned PDF format from the Numistral Bibliothèque numérique patrimoniale (https://www.numistral.fr/fr). The same edition of the HNS (volumes 1, 4 & 5 cited herein) is also available online in scanned PDF format from Gallica (https://gallica.bnf.fr/accueil/fr/content/accueil-fr), the online digital library of the Bibliothèque nationale de France. The same edition of the HNM (volume 1 cited herein) is also available in scanned PDF format from Numelyo - bibliothèque numérique de Lyon (https://numelyo.bm-lyon.fr/). Among the most readily available sources for many of Buffon’s better known writings is Oeuvres philosophiques de Buffon edited by Jean Piveteau (1954). All translations are mine.

    On Buffon’s notion of species as successive lineages, see several of Phillip Sloan’s fine works (1972, 1976, 1979, and 1981). On all aspects of Buffon’s views, Jacques Roger’s works are indispensable (1963, 1989, and 1997). Thierry Hoquet’s works (2005, 2010) on what Buffon meant by natural history and thus the nature of species are remarkably insightful. The new edition of the Histoire naturelle, edited by Stephane Schmitt, with the collaboration of Cédric Crémière is wonderful. The biographical introductions to the volumes so far are extremely informed, erudite, cogent and eloquent.

  2. After he had already completed the major part of his theory of reproduction, in his microscopic studies (1748), Buffon found organic molecules in various organic entities and in the seminal fluids of males and females (Buffon believed that there are no eggs in reproduction) of several species. (Buffon HN 2: p. 258)

    Phillip R. Sloan contends that this does not alter the fact that Buffon’s investigations with Needham were sophisticated and careful. Sloan writes: “Buffon was a critical and self-reflective scientific methodologist whose sophistication in this area has rarely been appreciated. His unusual scientific methodology involved the dual process of formulation of hypotheses, followed by the testing of these through recurrent observations on concrete phenomena” (Sloan 1992, p. 417).

    In a relatively recent work, Marc J. Ratcliff (2009) states that in the Histoire Buffon claimed he used a compound microscope in his microscopic studies. But, Ratcliff writes, the magnifications measurements he included in the paper, “Decouverte de la liqueur séminale dan les femelles vivipares et du réservoir qui la contient,” which he sent to the Académie Royale des Sciences in 1748, are exactly the same as those in a work by Henry Baker (1698–1774) entitled “An Account of Mr. Leeuwenhock’s Microscope,” which was published in the Philosophical Transactions for 1744. And Baker had used a simple microscope. Ratcliff infers from this that “[e]ither [Buffon] first used a simple microscope and changed his mind later, or he used Needham’s double microscope and, in 1748, wanted to impress people with computations” (Ratcliff 2009, p. 162). At any rate, Ratcliff implies Buffon was deceptive and disingenuous.

    Phillip R. Sloan argues that Buffon never claimed he used a compound microscope. Buffon stated in the Histoire that he used a “double” microscope, meaning, according to Sloan, that he probably used Needham’s simple microscope—a James Wilson [c. 1665–1730] model, built by John Cuff (1708–1772), which had a second lens used to focus light. The tables of magnification by Baker were used to show the superiority of the microscope Buffon used over those used by Antoni van Leeuwenhoek (Sloan 1992, pp. 415–438).

  3. In 1740 Abraham Trembley (1700–1784) discovered the amazing fact that two distinct polyps developed from a single polyp cut into two parts (Ratcliff 2009, pp. 103–123; Ratcliff 2004, pp. 555–575; Roe 1975, pp. 167–190; Vartanian 1950, pp. 259–280). Leeuwenhoek had observed the strange behavior of polyps; however, until the work of Trembley, this observation remained relatively unknown (Leeuwenhoek 1703, pp. 1304–1311).

    Buffon’s belief that the simplest beings were organized uniformly throughout their bodies allowed him to explain the remarkable behavior of polyps: every part of these beings was exactly alike; hence, the two separate parts are able to grow and develop.

References

  • Buffon, Georges-Louis Leclerc. 1954. Oeuvres philosophiques de Buffon, ed. Jean Piveteau. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon, Georges-Louis Leclerc. 1971. Correspondance générale [de] Buffon. 2 vols., ed. H. Nadault de Buffon. Paris, 1885; reprint edition, Genève: Slatkine Reprints. Available at http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k260553/f361.item.

  • Buffon, Georges-Louis Leclerc. 2007a. Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière avec la description du Cabinet du Roy Tome I (1749), Tome II (1749), eds. In Stephane Schmitt and Cédric Crémière, Paris: Champion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon, Georges-Louis Leclerc. 2007b. Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière, eds. Thierry Hoquet and Pietro Corsi. Paris: l’Imprimerie Royale, 1749–1789. Available at http://www.buffon.cnrs.fr

  • Daston, Lorraine, and Peter Galison. 2010. Objectivity. Brooklyn, NY: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diderot, Denis. 1966. Oeuvres complètes de diderot, revues sur les éditions originales, comprenant ce qui a été publie a diverses époques et les manuscrits inédits, conservés à la Bibliotheque de l’Ermigate, notices, notes, table analytique. Nendeln Liechtenstein: Kraus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heilbron, John L. 1979. Electricity in the 17th and 18th centuries: A study in early modern physics. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hoquet, Thierry. 2005. Buffon: histoire naturelle et philosophe. Paris: Champion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoquet, Thierry. 2010. History without time: Buffon’s natural history as a nonmathematical physique. Isis 101: 30–61. https://doi.org/10.1086/652688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larson, James L. 1994. Interpreting nature: The science of living form from Linnaeus to Kant. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, John, and Phillip R. Sloan. eds. 1981. From natural history to the history of nature: Readings from Buffon and his critics. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Newton, Isaac. 1952. Opticks; or a treatise of the reflections refractions inflections & colours of light; based on the 4th ed. London 1730. London: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliff, Marc. 2004. Abraham Trembley’s strategy of generosity and the scope of celebrity in the mid-eighteenth century. Isis 95(4): 555–575. https://doi.org/10.1086/430649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliff, Marc. 2009. The quest for the invisible: Microscopy in the enlightenment. Farnham UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riskin, Jessica. 2002. Science in the age of sensibility: The sentimental empiricists of the enlightenment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Roe, Shirley A. 1975. The development of Albrecht Von Haller’s views on embryology. Journal of the History of Biology 8(2): 167–190. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00130437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roger, Jacques. 1963. Les sciences de la vie dans la pensée française du XVIIIe siècles: la génération des animaux de descartes a l’Encyclopedie. Paris: Armand Colin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roger, Jacques. 1989. Buffon: un philosophe au Jardin du Roi. Paris: Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roger, Jacques. 1997. Buffon: A life in natural history, Trans: Sarah Lucille Bonnefoi, ed. L. Pearce Williams. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Shank, John B. 2008. The Newton wars and the beginning of the french enlightenment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, Phillip R. 1972. John Locke, John Ray, and the problem of the natural system. Journal of the History of Biology 5(1): 1–53. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02113485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, Phillip R. 1976. The Buffon-Linnaeus controversy. Isis 67(3): 356–375. https://doi.org/10.1086/351629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, Phillip R. 1979. Buffon, German biology, and the historical interpretation of biological species. The British Journal for the History of Science 12(2): 109–153. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007087400017027.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, Phillip R. 1992. Organic molecules revisited. In Buffon 88: Proceedings of the international Buffon conference, ed. J. Gayon, 415–437. Paris: Vrin.

  • Sloan, Phillip R. 2020. Metaphysics and “vital” materialism: Émilie du Châtelet and the origins of French vitalism. In Philosophy of biology before biology, ed. Cecilia Bognon-Kuss, and Charles T. Wolfe. 48–65. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Leeuwenhoek, Antonie. 1703. Concerning green weeds growing in water, and some animalcula found about them. Philosophical Transactions 283(23): 1304–1311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vartanian, Aram. 1950. Trembley’s polyp, La Mettrie, and eighteenth-century french materialism. Journal of the History of Ideas 11(3): 259–286. https://doi.org/10.2307/2707732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Several people have aided in the completion of this essay. I am especially indebted to Mark A. Eddy for his help in locating first edition reproductions of the Histoire, and in helping to format the manuscript. Julie M. Jones-Eddy also contributed substantially to the editing and formatting of this work. I sincerely thank the reviewers and editors for their excellent comments and valuable suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John H. Eddy.

Ethics declarations

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to declare. No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Eddy, J.H. Buffon, Species and the Forces of Reproduction. J Hist Biol 56, 479–493 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-023-09722-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-023-09722-y

Keywords

Navigation