Skip to main content
Log in

Against Anti-Abortion Violence

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Jeremy Williams argues that both anti-abortion and pro-choice theories seem to justify two forms of anti-abortion violence – (1) violence against those that perform abortions, and (2) the subjugation of women seeking abortion. He illustrates this by way of his Death Camps analogy. However, Williams does not advocate such violence; rather he seems despondent over his conclusion. Here I argue Williams’ conclusion turns on confusion regarding the restrictivist position and a failure to adequately meet the challenge of Thomson’s Violinist case. The Death Camps analogy is incomparable to the practice of abortion because it fails to capture the risks, burdens, and rights relationships present in pregnancy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Davis, 2003, pp. 353–354.

  2. See Williams, 2021, p. 4.

  3. Ibid p. 3, p. 15–22.

  4. See Thomson, 1971, pp. 48–49.

  5. See Thomson’s Violinist Case, Tiny House, Burglar Case, and People Seeds Case. Ibid p. 48–49, 52, 58–60.

  6. See Leridon, 1977 and Boklage, 1990.

  7. See Marquis, 2007.

  8. See McMahan, 2002, 2007 and Parfit, 2012.

  9. See Mulder, 2013.

  10. See Lee & George, 2005; Beckwith, 2007, George & Tollefsen, 2008.

  11. See Marquis, 1989 and Blackshaw & Hendricks, 2020.

  12. See Warren, 1973 and English, 1975.

  13. See Thomson, 1971, pp. 56–57.

  14. See Boonin, 2002, pp. 164–167.

  15. See Williams, 2021, p.17.

  16. See Simkulet, 2020, p. 95.

  17. See Murphy, 1985 Ord, 2008; Lovering, 2013, 2014, 2017; Simkulet, 2016, 2017, 2020; Berg, 2017.

  18. See Marquis, 2002, 2010.

  19. See Simkulet, 2018, p. 14 and Marquis, 1989, p.186.

  20. See Davis, 1984, pp.175–176. For Davis, the restrictivist may believe abortion is defensible in some cases to preserve the mother’s life, but argues the restrictivist should either adopt a more moderate view, or a more extreme view. She also claims the permissivist may believe abortion is indefensible in some extreme circumstances, though she doesn’t go into detail about what these may be.

  21. See Thomson, 1971, p. 50.

  22. Some moderates might also be willing to exceptions for cases of (c) incest, or (d) when the fetus’s life is not worth living in some sense. Laura Purdy’s discussion on what constitutes a minimally satisfying life may help explain why one might make exception (d). See Purdy, 1995a, b. These latter exceptions are problematic; (c) seems to stem from confusion about incest, perhaps equivocating it with (a) or (d); however many children born of incest can live normal, healthy lives, and are not the result of rape.

  23. The view is named to evoke the idea that a woman’s right to abortion is derived from her right to liberty. See Simkulet, 2016, p. 374.

  24. I am hesitant to describe the permissivist view as extreme; rather I take it most permissivists likely do not believe the fetus is a person with rights, so their killing at any stage for any reason is largely unproblematic.

  25. See Manninen, 2019.

  26. For permissivists who believe fetuses lack moral status, the wrongness of abortion would need to be grounded elsewhere. George Harris argues that some abortions may be prima facie wrong because they violate a father’s morally legitimate interest in procreation. One might ground the extraordinary wrongness of abortion for such theorists in rights other than those possessed by the fetus. See Harris, 1986.

  27. For a discussion of similar arguments, see Colgrove et al. (forthcoming).

  28. Many anti-abortion theorists talk as though the telos of abortion is killing the fetus, rather than ending the pregnancy, but this is either hyperbole or uncharitable. To illustrate this, suppose physicians were able to teleport a fetus directly from the womb to an ectogenesis device that would allow the fetus to develop outside the mother’s womb. If we assume women seeking abortion believe that fetuses are persons, it strikes me as uncharitable to assume they’d choose abortion over teleportation ectogenesis.

    Remember, too, that most contemporary abortions are medication abortions that “merely” let the fetus die, rather than killing it, and that most surgical abortions can remove the fetus to let it die outside the womb, rather than kill it, albeit with much greater risk to the mother. It would be uncharitable to interpret most anti-abortion theorists as unaware of this, and it would be uncharitable to interpret them as primarily concerned with how abortion is performed, rather than if it should be performed at all. In light of this, anti-abortion claims that the telos of abortion is killing are likely hyperbolic.

  29. See Thomson, 1971, pp. 65–66.

  30. See Harris, 1986, pp. 595–596.

  31. See Thomson, 1973, p. 156.

  32. See Williams, 2021, pp. 16–19.

  33. See Colgrove, Blackshaw, and Rodger (forthcoming) for a discussion of practical, peaceful alternatives to AAV that abortion critics might first resort to.

  34. See Williams, 2021, p. 1.

References

  • Beckwith, F. (2007). Defending life: A moral and legal case against abortion choice. Cambridge University Press

  • Berg, A. (2017). Abortion and miscarriage. Philosophical Studies, 174, 1217–1226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackshaw, B. P., & Hendricks, P. (2020). Strengthening the impairment argument against abortion. Journal of Medical Ethics, 5(47), 515–518. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boklage, C. E. (1990). Survival probability of human conceptions from fertilization to term. International Journal of Fertility, 35(2), 75–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Boonin, D. (2002). A defense of abortion. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511610172

  • Colgrove, N., Blackshaw, B. P., & Rodger, D. (forthcoming). Prolife hypocrisy: Why inconsistency arguments do not matter. Journal of Medical Ethics, Epub ahead of print, 121020F20. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106633.

  • Davis, N. (1984). Abortion and self-defense. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13, 175–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. (2003). What’s philosophically interesting about engineering ethics? Science and Engineering Ethics, 9(3), 353–361. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-003-0032-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • English, J. (1975). Abortion and the concept of a person. Jane Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 5(2), 233–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • George, R. P., & Tollefsen, C. (2008). Embryo: A defense of human life. Doubleday

  • Harris, G. (1986). Fathers and fetuses. Ethics, 96(3), 594–603

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, P., & George, R. P. (2005). The wrong of abortion. In A. I. Cohen, & C. Health (Eds.), Contemporary debates in applied ethics. Blackwell

  • Leridon, H. (1977). Human fertility: The basic components. University of Chicago Press.

  • Lovering, R. (2013). The substance view: A critique. Bioethics, 27, 263–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovering, R. (2014). The substance view: A critique (part 2). Bioethics, 28(7), 378–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovering, R. (2017). The substance view: A critique (part 3). Bioethics, 31(4), 305–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manninen, B. A. (2019). Banning abortions won’t stop them: What the empirical data tells us. Daily Nous. Accessed December 5, 2021. https://dailynous.com/2019/06/10/philosophers-on-ethics-politics-abortion/#bmanninen

  • Marquis, D. (1989). Why abortion is immoral. Journal of Philosophy, 86(4), 183–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, D. (2002). A defence of the potential future of value theory. Journal of Medical Ethics, 28, 198–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, D. (2007). The moral-principle objection to human embryonic Stem cell research. Metaphilosophy, 38(2–3), 190–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, D. (2010). Manninen’s defense of abortion rights is unsuccessful. American Journal of Bioethics, 10(12), 56–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2002). The ethics of killing. Oxford University Press

  • McMahan, J. (2007). Killing embryos for stem cell research. Metaphilosophy, 38, 170–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulder, J. (2013). A short argument against abortion rights. Think, 12(34), 57–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, T. F. (1985). The moral significance of spontaneous abortion. Journal of Medical Ethics, 11, 79–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1976). Moral luck. Proceedings of the Aristotelian society supplementary volumes, 50, 137–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Ord, T. (2008). The scourge: Moral implications of natural embryo loss. American Journal of Bioethics, 8, 12–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2012). We are not human beings. Philosophy, 87, 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Purdy, L. M. (1995a). Loving future people. In J. Callahan (Ed.), Reproduction, ethics and the law. Indiana University Press

  • Purdy, L. M. (1995b). Genetics and reproductive risk: Can having children be immoral? In R. Munson (Ed.), Intervention and reflection (4th ed.). Wadsworth Publishing Co

  • Simkulet, W. (2016). A critique of Henrik Friberg-Fernros’s defense of the substance view. Bioethics, 30, 767–773.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simkulet, W. (2017). Cursed lamp: The problem of spontaneous abortion. Journal of Medical Ethics, 43, 784–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simkulet, W. (2018). The parenthood argument. Bioethics, 32, 10–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simkulet, W. (2020). Abortion and ectogenesis: Moral compromise. Journal of Medical Ethics, 46(2), 93–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1971). A defense of abortion. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1, 47–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1973). Rights and deaths. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 2, 146–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, M. A. (1973). On the moral and legal status of abortion. The Monist, 57(4), 43–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. (2021). On anti-abortion violence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12756. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Simkulet.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Simkulet, W. Against Anti-Abortion Violence. HEC Forum (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-024-09531-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-024-09531-8

Keywords

Navigation