Skip to main content
Log in

Substantial Goodness and Nascent Human Life

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many believe that moral value is—at least to some extent—dependent on the developmental states necessary for supporting rational activity. My paper rejects this view, but does not aim simply to register objections to it. Rather, my essay aims to answer the following question: if a human being’s developmental state and occurrent capacities do not bequeath moral standing, what does? The question is intended to prompt careful consideration of what makes human beings objects of moral value, dignity, or (to employ my preferred term) goodness. Not only do I think we can answer this question, I think we can show that nascent human life possesses goodness of precisely this sort. I appeal to Aquinas’s metaethics to establish the conclusion that the goodness of a human being—even if that being is an embryo or fetus—resides at the substratum of her existence. If she possesses goodness, it is because human existence is good.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Pasnau (2001), whose views we’ll consider below, prefers to avoid “subtle metaphysical distinctions between persons and human beings” in the context of the present debate. Relying on a particular interpretation of Thomas Aquinas, Pasnau argues that zygotes, embryos, and early fetuses are not human at all. The term “human” refers to a natural kind specified by the possession of rational powers. He writes that “actual human life does not begin until well after conception. The developing fetus does not count as a human being until it possesses a human soul, and this does not occur until the fetus has developed its brain and sensory systems to the point where it can support the distinctive intellectual capacities of the human being” (Pasnau 2001, p. 108). There is much to be said for this view. But since the audience for this paper is not limited to those interested in whether this view faithfully represents Aquinas’s account, I’ll not quibble too much about which term is the appropriate one to use. In fact, I’ll often use the terms “person” and “human” interchangeably. If my thesis is right, it would not be inappropriate to do so.

  2. On this particular point, I am indebted to the work of Oderberg (2000a, b), who provides a helpful corrective to a widespread failure to distinguish between (1) the developmental differences between human beings and (2) the essential or species-defining capacities those human beings possess in virtue of what they are. Those who wish to deny the full humanity and worth of nascent human beings often point the developmental differences between more mature beings and those who are less so. Yet for Odereberg, “it is hard to see how these distinctions make a metaphysical difference of the kind which supports a moral distinction” (2000b, pp. 35–36). For more recent defenses of this view, see Beckwith (2013) and Kaczor (2011).

  3. For a critique of Giubilini and Minerva’s argument concerning harm, see Beckwith (2013).

  4. This position is also endorsed by Jean Porter (1995), Shannon and Wolter (1990) and a host of others. The number of responses to it is considerable, too. For some recent responses see Eberl (2000, 2007); George and Tollesfen (2008); Haldane and Lee (2003a), pp. 273–274, n. 6; Kaczor (2011); Ramsay (2011).

  5. Again, being “human” for Pasnau means possessing a rational soul, and a condition for rational ensoulment is having the developmental architecture necessary for supporting rational thought. See fn. 1.

  6. I’m grateful to an anonymous reviewer calling my attention to this potential objection.

  7. This view is not new, and has been ably defended elsewhere. See, for example, Beckwith (2005), Haldane and Lee (2003a, b), Kaczor (2011), Moreland and Scott (2000), Oderberg (2000a, b).

  8. Perhaps the best account of Aquinas’s metaethics is Kretzmann and Stump's “Being and Goodness” (1988). My own understanding of Aquinas’s metaethics owes much to this paper.

  9. I am not suggesting that Aquinas understands natural kinds strictly in terms of the powers they have. For Aquinas, the powers a thing has are determined by the kind of thing it is and not the other way around. Speaking in terms of a thing’s properties rather than powers, Michael Loux explains the point in the following way:

    Kinds… cannot be reduced to properties. It is, of course, true that in virtue of belonging to a kind, a concrete particular will possess many properties….Aristotelians will concede all these facts; what they will deny is that a plant’s belonging to the kind geranium can be reduced to or analyzed in terms of its possessing these properties. As they see things, it is because it belongs to the kind that it possesses these properties and not vice versa. The kinds to which concrete particulars belong represent unified ways of being that cannot be reduced to anything more basic.

    See Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction (London: Routledge, 1998), p. 126. I am grateful to an anonymous reader for urging me to clarify these issues and calling my attention to this passage.

  10. This illustration was suggested by an anonymous reader.

  11. I am grateful to an anonymous reader for urging me to give this objection more careful attention.

  12. While I completed the majority of my paper prior to reading Kaczor’s book, I benefited from it while revising this section. It also introduced me to several articles I otherwise would not have found.

  13. I’m not aware that the writers discussed earlier use this term to describe their own view, but it does seem to be an appropriate descriptor.

  14. While Oderberg has Singer (1994) and Tooley (1983) in mind, his remarks have much wider applicability. This portion of my argument follows his critique.

  15. My description here relies on W. Norris Clarke’s account of human substances (1995, p. 105). I’m grateful to both Beckwith (2005) and Kaczor (2011) for calling my attention to Clarke’s account.

  16. I am fond of Oderberg’s way of parsing this point: we often point to the developmental differences between human beings in order to identify which beings are possessors of moral worth. But those distinctions fail to illuminate to any “metaphysical difference of the kind which supports a moral distinction” (2000b, pp. 35–36).

  17. I am grateful to Beckwith and two anonymous readers for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  • Aquinas, T. (1981). Summa Theologiae [ST]. (Fathers of the English Dominican Province, Trans.). (Vol. 1, pp. 1256–1272.). Westminster, MD: Christian Classics.

  • Beckwith, F. J. (2005). Of souls, selves, and cerebrums: A reply to Himma. Journal of Medical Ethics, 31, 56–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beckwith, F. J. (2013). Potentials and burdens: A reply to Giubilini and Minerva. Journal of Medical Ethics, 39, 341–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, W. N. (1995). Explorations in metaphysics. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Eberl, J. T. (2000). The beginning of personhood: A Thomistic biological analysis. Bioethics, 14, 134–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eberl, J. T. (2007). A Thomistic perspective on the beginning of personhood: redux. Bioethics, 21, 283–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floyd, S. D. (2007). Aquinas’s moral philosophy. In J. Fieser & B. Dowden (Eds.), The internet encyclopedia of philosophy. Martin: University of Tennessee.

  • Ford, N. M. (1991). When did I begin? Conception of the human individual in history, philosophy and science: Conception of the human individual in history and philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, R. P., & Tollefsen, C. (2008). Embryo: A defense of human life. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giubilini, A., & Minerva, F. (2013). After-birth abortion: Why should the baby live? Journal of Medical Ethics, 39, 261–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J., & Lee, P. (2003a). Aquinas on human ensoulment, abortion and the value of life. Philosophy, 78, 253–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J., & Lee, P. (2003b). Rational souls and the beginning of life (a reply to Robert Pasnau). Philosophy, 78, 521–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Himma, K. (2002). A dualist analysis of abortion: Personhood and the concept of self qua experiential subject. Journal of Medical Ethics, 41, 48–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaczor, C. (2011). The ethics of abortion: Women's rights, human life, and the question of justice. New York: Routledge.

  • Kretzmann, N., & Stump, E. (1988). Being and goodness. In Thomas Morris (Ed.), Divine and human action: Essays in the metaphysics of theism (281–312).  Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • MacDonald, S. (1991). Ultimate ends in practical reasoning: Aquinas’s Aristotelian moral psychology and Anscombe’s fallacy. Philosophical Review, 100, 31–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2008). Challenges to human equality. The Journal of Ethics, 12(1), 81–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreland, J. P., & Scott, B. R. (2000). Body & soul: Human nature & the crisis in ethics. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2000a). Moral theory: A case against consequentialism. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2000b). Applied ethics: A non-consequentialist approach. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2014). Being and goodness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51, 345–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. T. (1997). The human animal: Personal identity without psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, R. (2001). Thomas Aquinas on human nature: A philosophical study of Summa Theologiae, 1a 75–89. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, R. (2003). Souls and the beginning of life (a reply to Haldane and Lee). Philosophy, 78, 509–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Porter, J. (1995). Individuality, personal identity, and the moral status of the preembryo: A response to Mark Johnson. Theological Studies, 56, 743–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsay, M. (2011). Twinning and fusion as arguments against the moral standing of the early human embryo. Utilitas, 23, 183–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruddick, W. (1998). Medical ethics. In: L. C. Becker & C. B. Becker (Eds.), Encyclopedia of ethics (2nd ed.). Garland. Retrieved June 12, 2014, from http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/ruddick/papers/medethics.html.

  • Shannon, T. A., & Wolter, A. B. (1990). Reflections on the moral status of the pre-embryo. Theological Studies, 51, 603–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1994). Rethinking life and death: The collapse of our traditional ethics. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1997). Philosophical Self-Portrait. In Thomas Mautner (pp. 521–522). London: The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy.

  • Tooley, M. (1983). Abortion and infanticide. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shawn Floyd.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Floyd, S. Substantial Goodness and Nascent Human Life. HEC Forum 27, 229–248 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-015-9265-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-015-9265-9

Keywords

Navigation