Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Free Choice and Patient Best Interests

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In medical practice, the doctrine of informed consent is generally understood to have priority over the medical practitioner’s duty of care to her patient. A common consequentialist argument for the prioritisation of informed consent above the duty of care involves the claim that respect for a patient’s free choice is the best way of protecting that patient’s best interests; since the patient has a special expertise over her values and preferences regarding non-medical goods she is ideally placed to make a decision that will protect her interests. In this paper I argue against two consequentialist justifications for a blanket prioritisation of informed consent over the duty of care by considering cases in which patients have imperfect access to their overall best interests. Furthermore, I argue that there are cases where the mere presentation of choice under the doctrine of informed consent is detrimental to patient best interests. I end the paper by considering more nuanced approaches to resolving the conflict between informed consent and the duty of care and consider the option of permitting patients to waive informed consent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These two consequentialist arguments for the prioritisation of informed consent are by no means exhaustive. A third consequentialist argument for the prioritisation of informed consent, for instance, emphasises the importance of informed consent procedures for facilitating patient trust [19, 28]. Informed consent procedures have been argued to be instrumental to promoting the patient’s trust in medical institutions and practitioners because only those who ‘understand what is proposed and who are in a position to refuse or choose in light of that understanding’ (as required by the doctrine of informed consent) are able to give their trust [40: 18]. The challenges to trust-promotion arguments for informed consent are explored in great detail in Eyal [19]. The unique focus of this paper will be on the arguments from epistemic privilege (“The Argument from Epistemic Privilege” section) and the argument from therapeutic benefit (“The Argument from Therapeutic Benefit” section). I would, however, like to thank [BLINDED] for indicating this third possibility.

  2. See also, O’Neill [40: 32].

  3. For instance, it is widely claimed that: “…the exercise of patient autonomy is contingent on the ability to understand relevant information and on the receipt of such information” [25: 417–418], and that: “The only way physicians in the future will be able to approximate knowledge of what serves their patients’ interests is to ask them…the patients themselves are likely to be the most reliable source physicians have of knowing their patients’ interests” [59: 707]. For instance, the Nuremberg code requires that the potential research subject: “…should have sufficient knowledge and comprehension of the elements of the subject matter involved as to enable him to make an understanding and enlightened decision. This latter element requires that before the acceptance of an affirmative decision by the experimental subject there should be made known to him the nature, duration, and purpose of the experiment; the method and means by which it is to be conducted; all inconveniences and hazards reasonably to be expected; and the effects upon his health or person which may possibly come from his participation in the experiment” [38]. Likewise, the department of health states that: “The provision of information is central to the consent process. Before patients can come to a decision about treatment, they need comprehensible information about their condition and about possible treatments/investigations and their risks and benefits (including the risks/benefits of doing nothing)” [15: 17]. It is thus argued that fully informed consent requires that: “… a person must have all the [medical] information required to form a final decision” [57: 1.3].

  4. For a comprehensive overview see Thaler and Sunstein [56] and White [61].

  5. For example, see Slovic [50, 51]. For a dispute of these findings see Wright et al. [64: 1118].

  6. For a comprehensive overview of this debate, see: Ost [41], Harris and Keywood [25], Malpas [34], Rhodes [42]; See Bortolotti [7] for a response.

  7. The dialectic of this paper would thereby reflect the more general collapse of rule consequentialism into act utilitarianism as presented by Smart [52].

References

  1. Appelbaum, P. S., Lidz, C. W., & Meisel, J. D. (1987). Informed consent: Legal theory and clinical practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Beauchamp, T. L. (2003). Methods and principles in biomedical ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29, 269–274.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  3. Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress, J. F. (1989). Principles of biomedical ethics (3rd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Birchley, G. (2013) Deciding together? Best interests and shared decision-making in paediatric intensive care. Health care analysis (online version).

  5. Blanchard, C., Labrecque, M. S., Ruckdeschel, J. C., & Blanchard, E. B. (1988). Information and decision-making preferences of hospitalised adult cancer patients. Social Science and Medicine, 27(11), 1139–1145.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  6. Blumenthal-Barby, J. S. (2013). Choice Architecture: A Mechanism for Improving Decisions While Preserving Liberty. In C. Coons & M. Weber (Eds.), Paternalism: Theory and practice (pp. 178–196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  7. Bortolotti, L. (2013). The relative importance of undesirable truths. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 16(4), 683–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Bortolotti, L., & Widdows, H. (2011). The right not to know: The case of psychiatric disorders. Journal of Medical Ethics, 37(11), 673–676.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  9. Botti, S., & Iyengar, S. S. (2006). The dark side of choice: When choice impairs social welfare. Journal of Public Policy and Marketing, 25(1), 24–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Bullock, E. C. (2010). Informed consent as waiver: The doctrine rethought? Ethical Perspectives, 17(4), 531–558.

  11. Cassell, E. J. (1977). The function of medicine. The Hastings Center Report, 7(6), 16–19.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Cohen, F., & Lazarus, R. S. (1973). Active coping processes, coping dispositions, and recovery from surgery. Psychosomatic Medicine, 35, 375–389.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Declaration of Helsinki. (2008). Ethical Principles for research involving human subjects: (1964; amended 2008). http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/. Accessed 10.11, 2008.

  14. Denger, L. F., & Sloan, J. A. (1992). Decision making during serious illness: What role do patients really want to play? Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 45(9), 941–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Department of Health. (2001). Good practice in consent implementation guide: Consent to examination or treatment. Crown Copyright.

  16. Ende, J., Kazis, L., Ash, A., & Moskowitz, M. A. (1989). Measuring patients’ desire for autonomy: Decision making and information seeking preferences among medical patients. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 4(1), 23–30.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  17. English, V., Romano-Critchley, G., Sheather, J., & Sommerville, A. (2004). Medical ethics today: The BMA’s handbook of ethics and law (2nd ed.). London: BMJ Books.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Erbay, H., Sultan, A., & Kadıoğlu, S. (2010). A case study from the perspective of medical ethics: Refusal of treatment in an ambulance. Journal of Medical Ethics, 36(1), 652–655.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Eyal, N. (2014). Using informed consent to save trust. Journal of Medical Ethics, 40, 437–444.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  20. Faden, R. R., & Beauchamp, T. L. (1986). A history and theory of informed consent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Gatrad, A. R., & Sheikh, A. (2001). Medical ethics and Islam: Principles and practice. Archives of Disease in Childhood, 84(1), 72–75.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  22. General Medical Council (2008) Consent: Patients and doctors making decisions together. http://www.gmc-uk.org/static/documents/content/Consent_-_English_0414.pdf. Accessed May, 2014.

  23. Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (2002). Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Greene, M. F. (2001). Vaginal delivery after caesarean section—Is the risk acceptable? The New England Journal of Medicine, 345, 54–55.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. Harris, J., & Keywood, K. (2001). Ignorance, information and autonomy. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 22(5), 415–436.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  26. Hippocratic Oath (Classic version). http://www.nlm.nih.gov/hmd/greek/greek_oath.html. Accessed 08.02, 2012.

  27. International Code of Ethics for Nurses. (2006). http://www.icn.ch/images/stories/documents/about/icncode_english.pdf. Accessed May, 2011.

  28. Jackson, J. (2001). Truth, trust and medicine. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Katz, J. (1984). The silent world of doctor and patient. London: The John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Levinson, W., Kao, A., Kuby, A., & Thisted, R. A. (2005). Not all patients want to participate in decision making. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 20(6), 531–535.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  31. Lloyd, A. J. (2001). The extent of patients’ understanding of the risk of treatments. Quality in Health Care, 10.I, i14–i18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T., & Rabin, M. (2003). Projection bias in predicting future utility. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118(4), 1209–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Maclean, A. (2006). Autonomy, consent and persuasion. European Journal of Health Law, 13, 321–338.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Malpas, P. (2005). The right to remain in ignorance about genetic information—can such a right be defended in the name of autonomy? Journal of the New Zealand Medical Association, 118, 1220.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Manson, N. C., & O’Neill, O. (2007). Rethinking informed consent in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  36. Mill, J. S. (2008). On liberty. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Miller, S. M., & Mangan, C. E. (1983). Interacting effects of information and coping style in adapting to gynaecologic stress: Should the doctor tell all? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45(1), 223–236.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  38. Nuremberg Code; Directives for Human Experimentation. (1949). http://ohsr.od.nih.gov/guidelines/nuremberg.html. Accessed November 2, 2008.

  39. Nursing and Midwifery Council Code. (2008). http://www.nmc-uk.org/Nurses-and-midwives/Thecode/The-code-in-full/. Accessed May, 2011.

  40. O’Neill, O. (2002). Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  41. Ost, D. E. (1984). The ‘right’ not to know. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 9(3), 301–312.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  42. Rhodes, R. (1998). Genetic links, family ties, and social bonds: Rights and responsibilities in the face of genetic knowledge. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 23, 10–30.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  43. Rispler-Chaim, V. (1989). Islamic medical ethics in the 20th century. Journal of Medical Ethics, 15(4), 203–208.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  44. Robinson, A., & Thomson, R. (2001). Variability in patient preferences for participating in medical decision making: Implication for the use of decision support tools. Quality in Health Care, 10, i34–i38.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  45. Sandman, L., & Munthe, C. (2009). Shared decision-making and patient autonomy. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 30, 289–310.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  46. Sandman, L., & Munthe, C. (2010). Shared decision making. Paternalism and Patient Choice Health Care Analysis, 18, 60–84.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  47. Savulescu, J. (2003). Is the sale of body parts wrong? Journal of Medical Ethics, 29(3), 138–139.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  48. Schneider, C. E. (1998). The practice of autonomy; patients, doctors and medical decisions. New York: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Shiavone, G., De Anna, G., Mameli, M., Rebba, V., & Boniolo, G. (2014). Libertarian paternalism and health care policy: A deliberative proposal. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 17, 103–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Slovic, P. (1987). Perception of risk. Science, 236(4799), 280–285.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  51. Slovic, P. (1999). Trust, emotion, sex, politics, and science: Surveying the risk-assessment battlefield. Risk Analysis, 19(4), 689–701.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  52. Smart, J. J. C. (1956). Extreme and restricted utilitarianism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 6(25), 344–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Strull, W., Lo, B., & Charles, G. (1984). Do patients want to participate in medical decision making? JAMA, 252(21), 2990–2994.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  54. Tabak, N., & Zvi, M. R. (2008). When parents refuse a sick teenager the right to give informed consent: The nurse’s role. Journal of Advanced Nursing, 25(3), 106–111.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Tännsjö, T. (1999). Coercive care: The ethics of choice in health and medicine. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  57. The Report of The Royal Liverpool Children’s Inquiry. (2001). http://www.rlcinquiry.org.uk/download/chap11.pdf. Accessed 02.09, 2012.

  58. Ubel, P. A., Loewenstein, G., Hershey, J., Baron, J., Mohr, T., Asch, D. A., et al. (2001). Do non-patients underestimate the quality of life associated with chronic health conditions because of a focusing illusion? Medical Decision Making, 21(3), 190–199.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  59. Veatch, R. M. (2000). Doctor does not know best: Why in the new century physicians must stop trying to benefit patients. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25(6), 701–721.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  60. Vick, S., & Scott, A. (1998). Agency in health care. Examining patients’ preferences for attributes of the doctor-patient relationship. Journal of Health Economics, 17(5), 587–605.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  61. White, M. D. (2013). The manipulation of choice: Ethics and libertarian paternalism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  62. Widdows, H. (2011). Localized past, globalized future: Towards an effective bioethical framework using examples from population genetics and medical tourism. Bioethics, 25(2), 83–91.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  63. Williams, Z. (2010). When the physician says you have to have the shot, but mommy says no: The cases of Taige Mueller and Daniel Hauser, and how the state may force parents to accept unwanted medical treatment for their children. Indiana Health Law Review, 8, 119–228.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Wright, G., Bolger, F., & Rowe, G. (2002). An empirical test of the relative validity of expert and lay judgments of risk. Risk Analysis, 22(6), 1107–1122.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers and a number of friends and colleagues for their comments on earlier drafts. In particular, Philip Goff, Heather Widdows and Iain Law. I would also like to thank the attendees of the Royal Institute of Philosophy seminar at Queen's University Belfast, and the 5th Interdisciplinary Workshop in the Philosophy of Medicine: Medical Knowledge, Medical Duties at King's College London for their invaluable input.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emma C. Bullock.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bullock, E.C. Free Choice and Patient Best Interests. Health Care Anal 24, 374–392 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-014-0281-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-014-0281-8

Keywords

Navigation