Skip to main content
Log in

Formation of Parties and Coalitions in Multiple Referendums

  • Published:
Group Decision and Negotiation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We consider a thought experiment in which voters could submit binary preferences regarding each of a pre-determined list of independent relevant issues, so that majorities could be tallied per issue. It might be thought that if such voting became technically feasible and widespread, parties and coalitions could be circumvented altogether and would become irrelevant. In this paper, we show, however, why and how voters would spontaneously self-organize into parties, and parties would self-organize into coalitions, prior to elections. We will see that such coordination is possible, even assuming very limited capabilities of communication and coordination. Using both analytical and empirical methods, we show that the average voter in a majority coalition would gain more than if no parties were formed, but the average voter overall (in or out of the coalition) would be worse off. Furthermore, the extent of these gains and losses is inversely proportional to the degree to which voters line along a unidimensional left–right axis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A number of recent studies deal with the nature and necessity of parties and political coalitions given current technology (e.g., Landis 2017; Warren 2017), including the question of changes in degrees of participation (Gibson and Cantijoch 2013). In addition, “cooperation among egoists” in social and political environments has been investigated in the modern political science literature at least since (Axelrod 1981) (e.g. Cronk and Leech 2012).

  2. On the assumption of binary choices, see the work of Brams and Fishburn (2007) on multicandidate problem.

  3. A number of empirical and theoretical studies focused not on political coalitions but on electoral mergers between political parties (Ibenskas 2016).

  4. Note that it is common in the literature to refer to a coordinated set of voters as a “coalition” and the word “party” is reserved for a particular type of institution with a governance structure. Nevertheless, we wish to distinguish here between a coordinated set of individual voters, which we call a “party” and a coordinated set of parties, which we call a “coalition”.

  5. The proofs for all the theorems appear in “Appendix”.

  6. In this context one should bear in mind the theoretical and empirical studies that focused on intracoalitional conflicts (e.g. Bowler et al. 2016).

References

  • Abramson PR, Aldrich JH, Diamond M, Diskin A, Levine R, Scotto T (2004) Strategic abandonment or sincerely second best? The 1999 Israeli prime ministerial election. J Polit 66:706–728

    Google Scholar 

  • Abramson P, Aldrich JH, Blais A, Diamond M, Diskin A, Indridason I, Lee DJ, Levine R (2010) Comparing Strategic Voting under FPTP and PR. Comp Polit Stud 43:61–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Aknine S, Pinson S, Shakun MF (2004) A multi-agent coalition formation method based on preference models. Group Decis Negot 13(6):513–538

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich JH (1995) Why parties? The origin and transformation of political parties in America. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich J (2011) Why parties? A second look. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe GE (1976) On frustration of the majority by fulfilment of the majority’s will. Analysis 4:161–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R (1981) The emergence of cooperation among Egoists. Am Polit Sci Rev 75(2):306–318

    Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee S, Konishi H, Sönmez T (2001) Core in a simple coalition formation game. Soc Choice Welfare 18(1):135–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler S, Indridason IH, Brauninger T, Debus M (2016) Let’s just agree to disagree: dispute resolution mechanisms in coalition agreements. J Polit 78(4):1264–1278

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Fishburn PC (2007) Approval voting. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Kilgour DM, Zwicker WS (1998) The paradox of multiple elections. Soc Choice Welfare 15(2):211–236

    Google Scholar 

  • Brill M (2018) Interactive democracy. In: Richland S (ed) Proceedings of the 17th international conference on autonomous agents and multiagent systems (AAMAS ’18), (pp 1183–1187)

  • Campbell A, Converse PE, Warran ME, Stokes DE (1960) The American voter. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Cho S-J (2014) Voting equilibria under proportional representation. Am Polit Sci Rev 108(2):281–296

    Google Scholar 

  • Christoff Z, Grossi D (2017) Binary voting with delegable proxy: an analysis of liquid democracy. TARC

  • Cronk L, Leech BL (2012) Meeting at Grand Central: understanding the social and evolutionary roots of cooperation. Princeton University Press, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • De Swaan A (1973) Coalition theories and cabinet formations. Elsevier Scientific, Amsterdam/London/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodd L (1976) Coalitions in parliamentary government. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Downs A (1957) An economic theory of democracy. Harper and Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan PJ (2014) Do something’ politics and double-peaked policy. J Polit 76(2):333–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Genin T, Aknine S (2010) Coalition formation strategies for self-interested agents in task oriented domains. In: Web intelligence and intelligent agent technology (WI-IAT) (vol 2, pp 205–212)

  • Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result‏. Econom J Econom Soc 587–601

  • Gibson R, Cantijoch M (2013) Conceptualizing and measuring participation in the age of the internet: Is online political engagement really different to offline? J Polit 75(3):701–716

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruszczyk W, Kwasnicka H (2008) Coalition formation in multi-agent systems—an evolutionary approach. In: Computer science and information technology (pp 125–130)

  • Ibenskas R (2016) Marriages of convenience: explaining party mergers in Europe. J Polit 78(2):343–356

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahng A, Mackenzie S, Procaccia AD (2018) Liquid democracy: an algorithmic perspective. In: Proc. 32nd AAAI conference on artificial intelligence. https://www.aaai.org/ocs/index.php/AAAI/AAAI18/paper/download/17027/15797

  • Klusch M, Gerber A (2002) Dynamic coalition formation among rational agents. IEEE Intell Syst 17(3):42–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Laffond G, Lainé J (2000) Representation in majority tournaments. Math Soc Sci 39(1):35–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Laffond G, Lainé J (2006) Single-switch preferences and the Ostrogorski paradox. Math Soc Sci 52(1):49–66

    Google Scholar 

  • Laffond G, Lainé J (2009) Condorcet choice and the Ostrogorski paradox. Soc Choice Welfare 32(2):317–333

    Google Scholar 

  • Landis JE (2017) Whither parties? Hume on partisanship and political legitimacy. Am Polit Sci Rev 1–12

  • Laver M, Schofield N (1990) Multiparty government: the politics of coalition in Europe. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarsfeld PF, Berelson B, Gaudet H (1948) The peoples choice: how the voter makes up his mind in a presidential campaign. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • MacQueen J (1967) Some methods for classification and analysis of multivariate observations. In: The fifth Berkeley symposium on mathematical statistics and probability (vol 1, no 14, pp 281–297)

  • Nermuth M (1992) Two-stage discrete aggregation: the Ostrogorski paradox and related phenomena. Soc Choice Welfare 9(2):99–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi H (1988) Voting paradoxes and referenda. Soc Choice Welfare 15(3):333–350

    Google Scholar 

  • Ordeshook PC (1986) Game theory and political theory: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne MJ, Rubinstein A (1994) A course in game theory. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rae DW, Daudt H (1976) The Ostrogorski paradox: a peculiarity of compound majority decision. Eur J Polit Res 4(4):391–398

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan T, Michalak TP, Wooldridge M, Jennings NR (2015) Coalition structure generation: a survey. Artif Intell 229:139–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Rajat D, Kelsey D (1987) On constructing a generalized Ostrogorski paradox: necessary and sufficient conditions. Math Soc Sci 14(2):161–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray D (2007) A game-theoretic perspective on coalition formation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker WH (1962) The theory of political coalitions. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanders D, Clarke HD, Marianne SC, Whiteley P (2011) Downs, stokes and the dynamics of electoral choice. Br J Polit Sci 41(2):287–314

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandholm T, Larson K, Andersson M, Shehory O, Tohmé F (1998) Anytime coalition structure generation with worst case guarantees. arXiv preprint

  • Satterthwaite MA (1975) Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. J Econ Theory 10(2):187–217

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaupp CL, Carter L (2005) E-voting: from apathy to adoption. J Enterp Inf Manag 18(5):586–601

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger J (1991) Political parties and the winning of office. University of Michigan Press, Michigan

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen S, Biswas A, Debnath S (2000) Believing others: pros and cons. In: Proceedings of the international conference on multi-agent systems (pp 279–286)

  • Shehory O, Kraus S (1998) Methods for task allocation via agent coalition formation. Artif Intell 101(1–2):165–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes DE (1963) Spatial models of party competition. Am Polit Sci Rev 57(2):368–377

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Dijk JA (2012) Digital democracy: vision and reality. Public Adm Inf Age 19(1):49–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren ME (2017) A problem-based approach to democratic theory. Am Polit Sci Rev 111(1):39–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Yang J, Luo Z (2007) Coalition formation mechanism in multi-agent systems based on genetic algorithms. Appl Soft Comput 7(2):561–568

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Meir Kalech.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

Proof of Theorem 1

To prove the theorem, we first define intra-party regret, a measure of voters’ dissatisfaction with their respective parties.

Definition 5 [Intra-party regret]

Given a partition P, for each party \( p \in P \), let \( \langle p\rangle \) be the (not necessarily natural) profile of p.The intra-party regret for a party p is \( ir(p,\langle p\rangle) = \sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {d(v,\langle p\rangle)} \). Let \( \langle p\rangle \) represent the set of profiles of parties in P. The total intra-party regret of the partition P is \( ir(P,\langle P\rangle) = \sum\nolimits_{p \in P} {d(p,\langle p\rangle)} \).

It is important to distinguish between intra-party regret, which is the dissatisfaction of voters with their respective parties, and total regret, which is the dissatisfaction of voters with the outcome of an election.

We will show that Procedure 1 converges to a stable partition. The key idea is that each step of the procedure decreases the value of \( ir(P,\langle P\rangle) \). Since \( ir(P,\langle P\rangle) \) is bounded from below, the process must converge. Furthermore, since at the last step, we require that the party be natural and the voters be stable, the final result is a stable partition.

It remains to show that \( ir(P,\langle P\rangle) \) diminishes at each step.

First, we show that each application of Step 2 diminishes \( ir(P,\langle P\rangle) \). Specifically, we must show that intra-party regret is diminished when each voter joins the nearest party. For a given voter v, let pj(v) be the party of v prior to Step 2 and let p*(v) be the party of v subsequent to Step 2. Then, p*(v) is the nearest party to v. Let P be the partition prior to Step 2 and let P′ be the partition that results from Step 2. Note that in Step 2, voters switch parties but the party profiles remain fixed. Then we have:

$$ ir(P^{{\prime}},\langle P\rangle) = \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in V} d(v,\langle P^{*(v)} \rangle) \le \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in V} d(v,\langle P^{j(v)} \rangle) = ir(P,\langle P\rangle) $$

Now we show that each application of Step 3 diminishes \( ir(P,\langle P\rangle) \). In Step 3, we change the profile of each party to its natural profile, but we do not change the membership of any party. For a party p, let its profile prior to Step 3 be \( \langle p\rangle \) and let its profile subsequent to Step 3 be \( \langle p\rangle^{*} = sign\left({\sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {\langle v\rangle}} \right) \). We need to show that:

$$ ir(P,\langle P\rangle^{*}) = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} d(v,\langle p\rangle^{*}) \le \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} d(v,\langle p\rangle) = ir(P,\langle P\rangle) $$

To see this, consider each issue i separately. Let \( v_{i} \in \{1, - 1\} \) be the ith element in the profile of v. That is, it represents the preference of voter v regarding issue i. Likewise, for a party p, let \( p_{i} \in \{1, - 1\} \) and \( p_{i}^{*} \in \{1, - 1\} \) be the ith element in \( \langle P\rangle \) and \( \langle P\rangle^{*} \), respectively. Regarding issue i, the preference of the majority of voters in p is \( sign\left({\sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {v_{i}}} \right) \) and the difference between support for the majority and minority preference is \( m_{i} = \left| {\sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {v_{i}}} \right| \). The intra-party regret for p is thus:

$$ \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} d(v_{i},p_{i}) = \left\{{\begin{array}{*{20}l} {\frac{{\left| p \right| - m_{i}}}{2},} \hfill & {p_{i} = sign\left({\mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} v_{i}} \right) = p_{i}^{*}} \hfill \\ {\frac{{\left| p \right| + m_{i}}}{2},} \hfill & {otherwise} \hfill \\ \end{array}} \right. $$

We now have the following inequality:

$$ ir(P,\langle P\rangle) = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} d(v,\langle p\rangle) = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} d(v_{i},p_{i}) = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} d(v_{i},p_{i}) = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \frac{{\left| p \right| \pm m_{i}}}{2} \ge \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \frac{{\left| p \right| - m_{i}}}{2} = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} d(v_{i},p_{i}^{*}) = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} d(v_{i},p_{i}^{*}) = \mathop \sum \limits_{p \in P} \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in p} d(v,\langle p^{*} \rangle) = ir(P,\langle P^{*} \rangle) $$

Proof of Theorem 2

Consider each issue i separately. Let \( v_{i} \in \{1, - 1\} \) be the ith element in the profile of v. That is, it represents the preference of voter v regarding issue i. Regarding issue i, the natural outcome of the individualist partition is \( sign\left({\sum\nolimits_{v \in V} {v_{i}}} \right) \) and the difference between support for the majority and minority preference in V is \( m_{i} = \left| {\sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {v_{i}}} \right| \). Since for the individualist partition each issue is decided in favor of the majority of voters, the overall regret of voters for the individualist partition regarding issue i is \( \frac{{\left| V \right| - m_{i}}}{2} \). For any other partition, each issue is decided either in favor of the majority or the minority, so the overall regret of voters regarding issue i is either \( \frac{{\left| V \right| - m_{i}}}{2} \) or \( \frac{{\left| V \right| + m_{i}}}{2} \). Thus we have for any partition \( P:\;r(P) = \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \frac{{\left| V \right| \pm m_{i}}}{2} \ge \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \frac{{\left| V \right| - m_{i}}}{2} = r(I) \)

Proof of Theorem 3

As in the proof of Theorem 2, consider each issue i separately and let \( v_{i} \in \{1, - 1\} \) be the ith element in the profile of v. Let \( n_{i} = \sum\nolimits_{{p_{j} \ne p}} {p_{i}^{j}} \) and let \( t_{i} = \sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {v_{i}} \). Then the outcome of the vote for issue i when the members of party p vote as individuals is sign(ni + ti). The outcome of the vote for issue i when the members of party p vote as a party is sign(ni+ sign(\( \sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {v_{i}} \))|p|). Denote the regret of members of p for issue i by ri(p, P) when they vote as a party and by ri(p, P/p) when they vote as individuals. If sign(ni)= sign(ti) or if |ti| > |ni|, the outcome accords with the majority preference in p, whether the members of p vote as a party or as individuals; ri(p, P) = ri(p, P/p)= \( \frac{{\left| p \right| - m_{i}}}{2} \), where \( m_{i} = \left| {\sum\nolimits_{v \in p} {v_{i}}} \right| \). Otherwise, if |p| < |ni|, then the outcome accords with the minority preference in p, whether the members of p vote as a party or as individuals; ri(p, P) = ri(p, P/p)= \( \frac{{\left| p \right| + m_{i}}}{2} \). Finally, if |p| > |ni|, the outcome accords with the majority preference of p if and only if they vote as a party. In this case ri(p, P/p) = \( \frac{{\left| p \right| + m_{i}}}{2} \) and ri(p, P) = \( \frac{{\left| p \right| - m_{i}}}{2} \) . Thus, for every i, ri(p, P/p) ≥ ri(p, P) so that r(p, P/p) = ∑iri(p, P/p) ≥ ∑iri(p, P) = r(p, P). □

Proof of Theorem 4

Consider each issue i separately. Regarding any issue i, the outcome given a majority coalition C is according to the majority preference within C. That is, \( o(P/C) = sign\sum\nolimits_{v \in C} {v_{i}} \). The difference between support for the majority and minority preference within the coalition is \( m_{i} = \left| {\sum\nolimits_{v \in C} {v_{i}}} \right| \). Thus, the overall regret of voters in the coalition regarding issue i is \( \frac{{\left| C \right| - m_{i}}}{2} \). For the individualist partition, each issue is decided in favor of the majority of all voters, which might be the same as the majority of coalition members or not. Thus, the overall regret of coalition members regarding issue i is either \( \frac{{\left| C \right| - m_{i}}}{2} \) (when the majority of voters share the preference of the majority of coalition members) or \( \frac{{\left| C \right| + m_{i}}}{2} \) (otherwise). Thus, we have,

$$ \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in C} d(o(I),v) = \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \frac{{\left| C \right| \pm m_{i}}}{2} \ge \mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{q} \frac{{\left| C \right| - m_{i}}}{2} = \mathop \sum \limits_{v \in C} d(o(P/C),v). $$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kalech, M., Koppel, M., Diskin, A. et al. Formation of Parties and Coalitions in Multiple Referendums. Group Decis Negot 29, 723–745 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10726-020-09675-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10726-020-09675-1

Keywords

Navigation