The Schrödinger’s cat argument was published by Schrödinger’s in [1] and devised during a discussion with Einstein. It was a provocation to show that quantum effects cannot be naively hidden in the microscopic realm of photons and atoms but, through linearity and entanglement, they can affect also macroscopic systems such as cats, giving rise, in Schrödinger’s words, to “ridiculous cases”. While quantum mechanics is by now well established, the debate on its interpretation is still very much open: a huge number of competing interpretations [2] vie for an explanation of the quantum formulas. The Schrödinger cat is a perfect testbed for such explanations [3].

In this paper, we give a very simple interpretation to the cat, the “complementarity interpretation”, based on textbook concepts, namely on the Copenhagen interpretation. We then show how to use it to create a simulated experiment which is effective to communicate to the general public concepts such as the superposition principle and quantum complementarity. Even though our explanation could have been proposed by Bohr himself (who famously championed quantum complementarity), Bohr never explicitly addressed the cat [4]. In his discussions with Schrödinger [5], he did address classicality, but only limiting himself to the measurement apparatuses, which is not what Schrödinger’s argument embodies. Surprisingly, to our knowledge the proposal presented in this paper (Schrödinger’s cat through complementarity) has not appeared in the English literature previously [6].

Outline of the paper: In Sect. 1 we recall quantum complementarity and how it is embodied in quantum mechanics. In Sect. 2 we explain Schrödinger’s argument and show how quantum complementarity can be used to make sense of the superposition. In Sect. 3 we explore the implications of Bell’s theorem on complementarity. Finally, in the Appendix we detail how one can construct a simulation of Schrödinger’s experiment in a cardboard box controlled through an Arduino microcontroller with a simulated cat.

1 Quantum Complementarity

All systems are described by a collection of their properties. For example, the state of a featureless particle is described by two properties, its position and its momentum. A spin 1/2 is described by the components \(J_x,J_y,J_z\) of its angular momentum. A cat is described by a myriad of complicated properties (color, weight, furriness, position, etc.). One of these is its “being dead or alive”: it can have two distinct values ‘dead’ and ‘alive’ (we will neglect intermediate ‘moribund’ values).

Properties in quantum mechanics are described by observables, such as the position observable X. The states of quantum systems are described by vectors \(|\psi \rangle\), and the state of systems which have a definite value of a property are eigenstates \(|x\rangle\) of the observable. The corresponding eigenvalue x is the value of the property in such state. States are vectors because of the superposition principle: any state is a linear combination of eigenvectors of some observable. Also any eigenstate of an observable is a linear combination of eigenstates of other observables. The Born rule tells us that, if we prepare a system in a (nontrivial) superposition of eigenstates of the observable we are measuring, we will get a probabilistic answer (collapse of the state): that observable property is not well defined in that system state. [The probabilities are given by the square moduli of the linear combination coefficients. We discuss below whether such probabilities are due to ignorance of something, or to the fact that this something is undefined.]

Complementarity, hence, follows by joining superposition with the Born rule. Consider two properties: observable \({{\hat{H}}}\) and observable \({{\hat{S}}}\). Suppose that the \({{\hat{H}}}\) eigenstates are all nontrivial superpositions of \({{\hat{S}}}\) eigenstates and that the state of the system is in an eigenvector of the \({{\hat{S}}}\) observable. Then property \({{\hat{S}}}\) will have a definite value, but \({{\hat{H}}}\) will not. Complementarity [7, 8] can be loosely stated as: “if the value of one property is determined exactly, the values of some other properties will be undefined”. E.g. if the position of the particle is exactly known, its momentum is completely undefined: position eigenvectors are equal superpositions of all momentum eigenvectorsFootnote 1. Complementarity is usually vaguely defined in textbooks (if at all), but it is just an aspect of the superposition principle (which is similarly vaguely defined [9]).

2 The Cat Argument

Schrödinger suggests closing a cat in a perfectly isolated box, which contains an “infernal device” which opens a poison vial if an atom decays. He then suggest to use an atom that has a half-life of one hour and to wait for one hour. What will happen? Of course, the atom has probability one half of decaying, so the cat has probability one half of dying. At first sight, this is not paradoxical at all.

The paradox emerges if one analyzes more carefully the predictions of quantum mechanics: since the atom is a quantum system, it evolves through the Schrödinger equation which describes a deterministic evolution: after one hour the atom has an equal probability amplitude of being decayed or nondecayed. Namely, the state of the atom is an equally weighted superposition: \((|decayed\rangle +e^{i\varphi }|non\ decayed\rangle )/\sqrt{2}\) where \(\varphi\) is a phase that depends on the details of the evolution (we will choose \(\varphi =0\) for simplicity). Since the box is perfectly isolated, the evolution of the whole box can be described through the Schrödinger equationFootnote 2, and the cat (through the above device) inherits the properties of the atom. Namely, the box prepares the cat in a state

$$\begin{aligned} \tfrac{1}{\sqrt{2}}(|dead\rangle +|alive\rangle ) \;, \end{aligned}$$
(1)

where for simplicity of notation, the two kets \(|dead\rangle\) and \(|alive\rangle\) represent the (entangled) state of all the degrees of freedom in the box: all the atoms and photons that compose the cat, its fleas, the poison vial, the radioactive atom, the molecules of air in the cat’s lungs and in the rest of the box and so on.Footnote 3 This state is a superposed state (“smeared psi-function”, in the words of Schrödinger), which is a situation physically distinguishable from the situation in which the box contains a cat which is dead or alive with probability one half. This last situation is described by a mixed state of the form:

$$\begin{aligned} \tfrac{1}{2}(|dead\rangle \langle dead|+|alive\rangle \langle alive|) \;. \end{aligned}$$
(2)

The two states (1) and (2) are distinguishable only if one looks at a property that is complementary to “being dead or alive”, as discussed below. If, instead we only consider the property of “being dead or alive”: we cannot distinguish them, they both describe a box containing a cat that is dead or alive with probability one half.

Consider two complementary observables: the first observable “being dead or alive” \({{\hat{H}}}\) has the two orthogonal states \(|dead\rangle\) and \(|alive\rangle\) as eigenstates, corresponding to the two possible values of the cat’s health; the second observable \({{\hat{S}}}\) is defined as the one with eigenstates \(|+\rangle =(|dead\rangle +|alive\rangle )/\sqrt{2}\) and \(|-\rangle =(|dead\rangle -|alive\rangle )/\sqrt{2}\) and eigenvalues \(+1\) and \(-1\) respectively. For lack of better words, we will call this property “plus or minus”. The observable \({{\hat{S}}}\) can be measured by using some quantum interferometric experiment [13], where the \(|+\rangle\) and \(|-\rangle\) states refer to constructive and destructive interference respectively. Of course, the apparatus which measures such an observable will be insanely impractical (understatement) [13], but there is no in-principle reason why it cannot be built. The \({{\hat{S}}}\) property and the \({{\hat{H}}}\) property are complementary, since the eigenstates of one are superpositions of the eigenstates of the other, and viceversa.

Since the cat is in the state (1), the measurement of the “plus or minus” \({{\hat{S}}}\) observable will have outcome \(+1\) with certainty. Thus, the cat possesses a definite value (plus) of the \({{\hat{S}}}\) “plus or minus” property, which is complementary to \({{\hat{H}}}\) “being dead or alive”. Thus it is neither dead nor alive. As a figure of speech, it is customary to say that it is “dead AND alive at the same time” (since it is neither).

This is the paradoxical situation: we have experience of dead cats or of alive cats. We can even easily think of cats in a box of which we do not know if they are dead or alive, a situation described by (2). However, we cannot even imagine a quantum-superposed (“smeared”) cat that is neither dead nor alive, described by the state (1). It would not even remotely look like a cat: it would look like some interference pattern in an enormously complicated interferometer (even though it is a cat: the interferometer is showing a strange property of the cat that is complementary to its usual properties). It is so inconceivable to think of such a “cat” that we do not have appropriate words to describe the situation (except in the language of mathematics) and we resort to somewhat inappropriate “dead AND alive” statements. The reason we do not have experience of such cats is due to the incredible complexity of the experiment necessary to measure the \({{\hat{S}}}\) property in a cat. This, in turn, is due to decoherence: the almost unavoidable interaction with the environment of macroscopic systems such as a cat means that some of the cat’s properties (such as \({{\hat{H}}}\)) are evident, whereas others (such as \({{\hat{S}}}\)) are not. Why is there a difference between the property \({{\hat{H}}}\) and \({{\hat{S}}}\)? The most widely accepted explanation is due to the fact that interactions in physics are local [14]. Then, the interaction with the environment of a state where all the microscopic degrees of freedom are well localized (or approximately well localized) such as an \(|alive\rangle\) cat, will lead to a state where the environment just replicates (quantum Darwinism [14]) the information that the cat is alive \(|alive\rangle \rightarrow |alive\rangle |E_a\rangle\), where \(|E_a\rangle\) is the state of the environment coupled to an alive cat. To find the \({{\hat{H}}}\) property, one only needs to look either at the cat or at only one of these degrees of freedom of the environment. Instead, the environmental coupling to states localized in macroscopically different positions, such as a cat superposition \((|dead\rangle +|alive\rangle )/\sqrt{2}\), will lead to a state \((|dead\rangle |E_d\rangle +|alive\rangle |E_a\rangle )\sqrt{2}\) (with \(|E_d\rangle\) the environment state coupled to the dead cat) where the information about the \({{\hat{S}}}\) property of the cat has now become a joint property of the cat and of its environment. To access it, one would not only need to perform a quantum interference experiment on the cat (and the poison vial), but also on all the degrees of freedom of the environment. The structure of this entangled state (a “branching” state [14]) is such that the \({{\hat{S}}}\) property cannot be accessed anymore if only one of the huge number of degrees of freedom of the environment is lost (which leads to an effective “collapse” of the state). This is the modern view of the emergence of classicality from a quantum world. In other words, the reason why we never see superposed cats is, according to quantum mechanics, is only due to the practical difficulty in isolating a cat from its environment and in carrying out the appropriate interferometric experiment, and not because of any fundamental reason: sophisticated enough experiments can achieve it in practice [15, 16], although it would be vastly impractical on the scale of a cat [13].

Note that, if we have a cat in the mixed state (2), then, writing it in the \(|+\rangle ,|-\rangle\) basis we find \(\tfrac{1}{2}(|dead\rangle \langle dead|+|alive\rangle \langle alive|)=\tfrac{1}{2}(|+\rangle \langle +|+|-\rangle \langle -|)\). Namely, a measurement would return the outcome “plus” or “minus” with probability 1/2. This is not what happens with the Schrödinger cat state (1), where the outcome “plus” happens with probability 1: the Schrödinger cat is not a cat which is dead or alive with probability 1/2, as formalized by (2): a measurement of the complementary “plus/minus” observable shows that it is in a state (1). In other words, a superposition is distinguishable from a mixture through the measurement of an appropriate observable.

In summary, using quantum complementarity, the cat paradox is readily explained: There exist a property \({{\hat{S}}}\) “plus or minus” that is complementary to \({{\hat{H}}}\) “dead or alive”. Since the cat has a definite value of the “plus or minus” property (“plus”, in this case), then it cannot have a definite value of the complementary property “dead or alive”.

3 Complementarity and the Bell Theorem

One may be tempted to dismiss quantum complementarity by stating that a cat in the state \((|dead\rangle +|alive\rangle )/\sqrt{2}\) has also a definite value of the “dead or alive” property but, somehow, we are ignorant of it. Namely, we can argue that complementarity is not a limitation on the values of the properties that an object can possess, but rather on the fact that a quantum measurement can extract only one of them at a time (and, possibly, perturbs the values of the complementary ones).

In order to maintain such position, however, one needs to give up Einstein locality (technically the “no signaling condition”). Indeed, Bell’s theorem [17, 18] tells us that quantum mechanics is incompatible with local hidden (i.e. unknown) values. A simple exposition of Bell’s theorem and its implications is in [19]. This means that, if one wants to retain Einstein locality, values of complementary properties are not even defined in a quantum system. One cannot say that they are defined, but unknown. Of course, one could retain unknown values at the cost of locality, as is done in Bohmian mechanics, where the hidden variables are notoriously nonlocal (signaling)Footnote 4. In this paper we take the point of view of Copenhagen quantum mechanics.

In fact, by measuring complementary observables on entangled states, one can observe [25,26,27] correlations among the measurement outcomes which are incompatible (Bell’s theorem) with any possible prescription that assigns pre-determined values to these properties, unless one postulates that the measurement of one property somehow is able to nonlocally change the value of a property of the correlated distant system. Most physicists (not all [2, 20, 28, 29]) are unwilling to abandon Einstein locality, because of the causality problems that would emerge if one could access these hypothetical “instantaneously”Footnote 5 [30] propagating hidden variables and because one would have to introduce a preferred reference frame which would violate the postulate of relativity that all inertial frames are equivalent. Then, if one wants to retain locality, causality, and relativity, Bell’s theorem forces us to admit that if one observable is well defined, then the values of complementary ones are not even defined (what is sometimes, somewhat inappropriately, called an abandonment of realism). I emphasize that “undefined” is very different from “unknown”. While an undefined quantity is clearly also unknown (whence the probabilities of the Born rule), the opposite is not true. For Copenhagen, the state (1) represents a state where the “being dead or alive” property is undefined, whereas the state (2) represents a state where it is unknown.Footnote 6

Then the Schrödinger cat, thanks to complementarity, has an undefined value of whether it is alive or dead. A quite weird situation for the poor cat!

4 Conclusions

In conclusion, we have presented a simple interpretation of Schrödinger’s cat, based on quantum complementarity. The superposed cat has a definite value of a property \({{\hat{S}}}\) with eigenstates \((|dead\rangle \pm |alive\rangle )/\sqrt{2}\) which is, hence, complementary to the macroscopic property “being dead or alive” so that the value of the latter property is undefined. Such interpretation uses only standard textbook concepts. A simulated Schrödinger cat experiment is presented in the Appendix, together with the indications of how to cheaply replicate it. It has been tested with success in several science outreach occasions.