Now, before I advance my proposal for a dispositional account of GRW, I will analyse Frigg and Hoefer’s and Suárez’s proposals in the light of the different types of propensities that I have introduced so far, in order to show which problems emerge from their accounts once we spell it out in a clearer form.
Starting with Frigg and Hoefer [22], they have proposed a reading of GRW probabilities in terms of propensities, which is slightly more detailed than Dorato and Esfeld’s one. They argue that, according to this interpretation of GRW, physical systems possess two kinds of single-case propensities, which ground the corresponding random processes and their respective probabilities. They also highlight the fact that those two processes are coupled, because one provides the trigger for the other. On the one hand, they claim that the occurrence of hits is grounded by spontaneous propensities:
The occurrence of a localization […] does not seem to [have] a triggering condition […] There is a chance of \(\lambda dt\) for each elementary constituent to decay during \(dt\) […]. Hence [this random process] can be understood on the basis of the single case propensity view. (Frigg and Hoefer [22], p. 384).
On the other hand, regarding the localization processes, they claim that:
It seems natural to say that for every possible localization event \(H_{x}\) the wave function has a (single case) propensity to undergo this particular localization. (Ibid.).
However, they do not give further details about the structure of their propensity reading of GRW. In addition, I am going to show that—once we formalize this proposal—some issues emerge.
First of all, as we have seen, they claim that the dynamics of GRW embeds two coupled random processes, and that a propensity theory of probability should ground the probabilities assigned to those processes onto two kinds of propensities. Indeed, they seem to distinguish between those propensities which ground the hitting processes and those that underlie the localization processes.
Considering the first of the two quotes above, it seems that they want to characterize the objective chances embedded within the random hitting processes as spontaneous single-track propensities. Remember that I have defined these as follows: “If object O possesses spontaneous single-track propensity PS with manifestation M then: were O to instantiate PS during an infinitesimal interval of time \(dt\), during \(dt\) it would M with probability \(\lambda dt{ }\left( {0 \le \lambda dt{ } \le 1} \right)\).”. Thus, we can say that hitting processes are caused by the (spontaneous) triggering of spontaneous single-track propensities possessed by physical systems, whose manifestation M is the occurrence of the hit and whose probability \(\lambda dt{ }\) is determined by the value of the parameter \(\lambda\) postulated by GRW. Those propensities determine thus the Poisson distributions defined by the theory.
Passing now to the second kind of random processes within GRW—i.e. the localization processes—let us consider as our case study the simple superposed state \(\left| \psi \right\rangle\) of Sect. 3. According to Frigg and Hoefer, the occurrence of the first random process—the hit—triggers the localization process \({ }\left| \psi \right\rangle \mathop{\longrightarrow}\limits^{loc.}\frac{{\left| {\psi_{{\varvec{x}}}^{i} } \right\rangle }}{{\left\| {\left| {\psi_{{\varvec{x}}}^{i} } \right\rangle } \right\|}}.\) Thus, the quantum state \(\left| \psi \right\rangle\) localizes either in region A or in region B, with a probability given by \(P_{i} \left( x \right) = \left\| {\left| {\psi_{{\varvec{x}}}^{i} } \right\rangle } \right\|^{2}\), where \(x\) is where the localization takes place. Concerning the quantum system in our example, the same probability \(P_{i} \left( x \right) = 0.5\) is assigned to both the locations.
As I have already remarked, they claim that the most natural way to conceive this process is “to say that for every possible localization event \(H_{x}\) the wave function has a (single case) propensity to undergo this particular localization”. This seems to suggest to model those propensities as simple single-track propensities (“If object O possesses single-track propensity P with manifestation M then: were O to be in the appropriate circumstance C, it would M with probability \(p\left( {0 \le p \le 1} \right)\).”). More precisely, each system possesses a set of individual and distinct single-track propensities, one for every localization event \(H_{x}\): the appropriate circumstances are constituted by the occurrence of the hits, the localization events are the manifestations of those propensities—i.e. they are caused by them—and their probabilities are fixed by the probability function \(P_{i} \left( x \right)\).
To recap, the propensity account of the random processes in GRW proposed by Frigg and Hoefer can be stated as follows: spontaneous single-track propensities produce hits which, in turn, trigger single-track propensities whose manifestations are the localizations of the wave function.
In the following, I shall point out why I find this account unsatisfactory. First of all, I shall move what I consider to be a decisive objection against this specific propensity view. That is, I will claim that the model sketched by Frigg and Hoefer fails to secure the mutual exclusivity of the different possible localization events. Secondly, I will add some considerations concerning the fact that this account—as I have formalized it—embeds two distinct and coupled probabilistic dispositions.
Starting from the first point, we can raise the following objection against Frigg and Hoefer’s account of dispositions to localize. Consider the quantum state \(\left| \psi \right\rangle\) mentioned above. According to their account, the quantum system S described by \(\left| \psi \right\rangle\) possesses two distinct propensities P1 and P2:
-
(1)
S possesses the single-track propensity P1 such that: were there an occurrence of a hit, S would localize in the region A with probability \(p = 0.5\)
-
(2)
S possesses the single-track propensity P2 such that: were there an occurrence of a hit, S would localize in the region B with probability \(p = 0.5\)
Recall that localization events are produced by dispositions to localize. Now, suppose that system S undergoes a hit. Therefore, by the definition of single-track propensities P1 and P2, both those dispositions would be triggered. Each disposition would produce its manifestation—the localization event—only probabilistically. But, notice that the structure of those propensities would entail an unwelcomed result. In fact, a total of four combinations of outcomes are consistent with the nature of P1 and P2 so defined: in two of those occasions, only one of the two localization event takes place, but there would be also one situation where no localization is produced and one another where two localization events are displayed. But, of course, the last two situations are forbidden by the theory. In other words, this model fails to account for the mutual exclusivity of the two localization events.
I pass now to the second consideration that I want to point out concerning Frigg and Hoefer’s proposal. Looking at the formalism of the theory, the localization process postulated by GRW is governed by a single stochastic equation and is instantaneous and spontaneous. Because of this, it seems odd to say that the dynamics of GRW concerns two distinct coupled dispositions, one of which provides the triggering conditions for the other. The reason is the following.
Let’s assume that the manifestation of a disposition corresponds to a physical event. Then, according to the two-propensities model, we would have a first process—grounded by a spontaneous single-track propensity—whose manifestation is the hit. The hit, therefore, would be a physical event, and it would trigger the activation of a disposition to localize (let’s set aside here the problem of mutual exclusivity). Thus, the manifestation of the second disposition would correspond to the physical event which we actually measure, i.e. the localization of the system in a single region. Given this description, two puzzling aspects arise.
Firstly, it should be pointed out that the hit is not a physical event at all. The hit simply represent mathematically the fact that the wave function collapse. However, it would not make much sense to say that this description corresponds to a physical event, since it would mean that there is a collapse but nowhere in spacetime, given that—by definition—the actual localization is produced by the second disposition. In addition, we also have no reason to claim that only the manifestation which has physical meaning is the one of the second disposition, since that would commit one to say that two radically different kinds of dispositions are at play here, such that the nature of their manifestations is different. Secondly, and relatedly, this model seems to suggest that there is a temporal succession between the hit and the localization. However, this is not what GRW postulates. The process of localization is, on the contrary, instantaneous. The most natural interpretation would be therefore that the disposition underlying this process is a single propensity which has as its unique manifestation a spatially-localized event.
Admittedly, the strength of this objection depends on one’s view about dispositions. However, I believe that here I have at least made the case for believing that—all things being equal—we should prefer a propensity account of GRW which grounds the dynamics on the theory on one single disposition only, in place of a two-propensity model.
Let’s consider now Suárez’s [34] proposal. Similarly to Frigg and Hoefer, he has sketched a possible interpretation of the probabilities within GRW in terms of probabilistic dispositions. He claims that:
The localization process [of GRW] is at the very least compatible with the assumption that each quantum particle has an irreducible disposition to localize in an area given by d with frequency f. […] The dispositions that according to GRW each particle has to spontaneously reduce upon a region x of area d are propensities. (Suárez [34], p. 433)
Here the author is explicitly using the term ‘propensities’ to denote what I have called ‘single-track propensities’. But he also stresses that the propensities within GRW cannot have that exact form, since they are spontaneously triggered. At that point, however, Suárez does not propose a revised definition of propensities which can account for this feature. Thus, in order to spell out more precisely the account he is sketching, I shall take spontaneous single-track propensities as a charitable formulation of the kind of dispositions he is referring to.
Given what he says in the quote aforementioned, it seems natural to interpret his account as postulating that in GRW each ‘quantum particle’ possesses a set of spontaneous single-track propensities. Each of those propensities is characterized by its disposition to localize the particle in a different region of space.Footnote 23 In other words, the particle possesses a propensity for every region in which it can be localized. Taking again the superposed state \(\left| \psi \right\rangle\) of Sect. 3 as our example, in that case the system would possess both one propensity to localize in region A and one propensity to localize in region B. It is now quite easy to notice that a very similar objection to the one which I have raised against Frigg and Hoefer’s account can be proposed in this context as well. That is, since here we are talking about two distinct dispositions, nothing in the metaphysical structure of the account forbids the two spontaneous propensities to manifest together at the same time. Given that they are—so to say—uncorrelated, it is possible for them to spontaneously manifest together. This scenario is of course very unlikely, but its mere possibility is sufficient to threaten the account. Indeed, just as we have seen concerning Frigg and Hoefer’s account, a simultaneous manifestation is forbidden by the physics of GRW, and thus any metaphysical account of the theory have to rule out this scenario categorically.
To recap, starting from the reasons that I have put forward for rejecting the account proposed by Frigg and Hoefer and by Suárez, we can formulate a crucial desideratum that any propensity theory of GRW has to satisfy. That is, it should secure the mutual exclusivity of the possible localization events—and that exactly one of them is produced. Then, a second minor desideratum is arguably to avoid postulating a two-propensity model similar to the one envisaged within Frigg and Hoefer’s proposal.
I claim that if we adopt an account of GRW probabilities in term of spontaneous weighted multi-track propensities we can easily satisfy these desiderata. More precisely, we can claim that physical systemsFootnote 24 instantiate a single disposition—a spontaneous weighted multi-track propensity—which grounds both the random processes featured in GRW at once. On the one hand, the ‘spontaneous’ nature of those dispositions, which is formally represented by the disposition’s probability to be self-triggered during a specific interval of time, grounds the frequency \(\lambda\) for the hits to occur. On the other hand, those dispositions are probabilistic also because—when triggerred—they produce a “random” manifestation from a set of possible manifestations. However, since they are weighted multi-track propensities, by definition that outcome will not be completely casual. On the contrary, the very nature of those dispositions is to assign a distribution of probabilities over the set of their possible outcomes. And this is what grounds the objective probabilities linked to the localization process—i.e. the Born’s rule predictions. More precisely, the set of mutually exclusive manifestations of these propensities is the set of all the possible localizations events, while the probabilities \(p\left( {M_{i} } \right)\) for the localization events are the ones assigned by the function \(P_{i} \left( x \right) = \left\| {\left| {\psi_{{\varvec{x}}}^{i} } \right\rangle } \right\|^{2}\).
In sum, I claim that this propensity account for GRW fares better than its alternatives. First and foremost, thanks to its appeal to multi-track propensities, it is the only one—among the ones discussed—which secures the mutual exclusivity of the different localization events, thereby avoiding the objection which I have put forward in this section. I take this to be the most decisive advantage of this view. Secondly, I claim that—all this being equal—this account should be preferred, since it is more simple and ontologically parsimonious than the alternative ones suggested above. In fact, it postulates a single multi-track propensity to ground the localization process and the probabilities described by GRW. Thus, it is neither committed to the existence of whole sets of dispositions (one for each possible manifestation), unlike the two accounts which I have assessed, nor to the existence of two distinct kinds of dispositions, unlike Frigg and Hoefer’s view. In this sense, the account I proposed here is more parsimonious both in the number and in the kinds of the propensities that it assumes. Finally, it avoids the second of the two objections that I have moved against the account sketched by Frigg and Hoefer. In fact, within my account, the collapse and the localization are simultaneously realized by the same manifestation: once the spontaneous weighted multi-track propensity is (spontaneously) activated, it simply produces the localization of the system as its unique manifestation. As I said before, this is not by itself a decise point in favour of this proposal, and one could still insist that in practice the two-propensity model by Frigg and Hoefer does not differ substantially from my account, in this respect. However, ceteris paribus, I believe that a simpler model is to be preferred.
In conclusion, my proposal for a dispositionalist ontology of GRW is the following. Physical systems (in the appropriate conditions) instantiate spontaneous weighted multi-track propensities, which grounds the two probabilistic terms \(\lambda\) and \(P_{i} \left( x \right)\). The fundamental ontology of the world is composed by those dispositions, in addition to the primitive ontology of GRW. The primitive ontology is thus governed by them. Moreover, I side with Dorato and Esfeld [15] and Egg and Esfeld [16] concerning their interpretation of the wave function within GRW. Indeed, we can say that wave function “is a mathematical symbol essentially referring to such propensities”. The main aim of this paper has been to refine their account, by showing how to spell out a complete dispositional interpretation of the wave function in GRW which can also ground the objective probabilities postulated by the theory. Of course, in this paper I have not argued in favour of the dispositionalist view per se. However, what I want to urge is that, if one wants to endorse a dispositionalist view of GRW, this would be the best account available.