Dewar and Weatherall recognise that (1) is elliptic, and thus cannot straightforwardly represent propagating solutions in the same sense as do
If we wish to be informed about dynamics, an elliptic system will not do. Given that the study of dynamics just is the study of processes evolving in time, it is to be expected that the mathematical tools designed for this purpose distinguish timelike directions, as hyperbolic PDEs do [22, p. 27].
hyperbolic equations.Footnote 4 Nevertheless, they claim that elliptic equations can still represent propagating solutions, in two (weaker) senses. The first is that the solutions of elliptic equations may nevertheless be ‘wavelike’; the second is that solutions of elliptic equations can be considered to be propagating waves insofar as they are obtained via the Newtonian limit of GR wave solutions. In the following two subsections, we consider these arguments in turn.
Wavelike Solutions to Elliptic Equations
Dewar and Weatherall’s first argument that there can be gravitational wave solutions of the geometrised Poisson equation (1) (and also, given Trautman geometrisation and recovery, to the Newton-Poisson equation) begins with the claim that the solutions of an elliptic equation
may [nevertheless] be “wavy”, in the sense of exhibiting some periodicity: e.g., \(\varphi = e^x e^y \sin \left( \sqrt{2} z \right) \) is a homogeneous solution to Poisson’s equation that is sinusoidal in the z direction [9, p. 574].
Dewar and Weatherall take the alleged ‘waviness’ of such solutions as indicating a sense in which these solutions should still count as propagating. In our view, there are several issues with this. First, it is not clear why a solution should count as wavelike just because it features oscillatory functions, such as (in the above case) a sine function of one (local) spatial coordinate. Generally, accepted forms of waves are after all functions of the form \(f\left( z \pm v\left( x,y,z,t\right) t\right) \) when expressed in an appropriately adapted coordinate system,Footnote 5 together with some constraints on the form of f and v.
Secondly, even if the (spatial) solutions to the Poisson equation are stacked onto each other over time with the appropriate boundary conditions imposed, they seem at first sight only to be associated with standing waves: the time component seems to only (if at all) oscillate independently of the spatial component—giving rise to standing wave solutions such as
$$ \Psi (x, y, z, t) = \sin (\omega t) e^x e^y \sin \left( \sqrt{2} z \right) . $$
More generally, an evolution of solutions to the vacuum gravitational Poisson equation over time can be given by a continuous piecewise function, each piece of which is a product of a temporal factor and a solution to the homogeneous Poisson equation (cf. [9, p. 574] and [33]), that is
$$ \Psi (x, y, z, t) = \sum _a f_a(t) \varphi _a, $$
where \(f_a(t)\) and \(\varphi _a\) are time-dependent functions and oscillatory solutions to the Poisson equation, respectively.Footnote 6
Thus considered, there is, in fact, a straightforward—albeit unorthodox—way of making spatial oscillatory functions ‘move’ over time: consider two spatial solutions oscillatory in the z-direction, with approximately the same (spatial) periodicity and amplitude, but one solution shifted by a small distance in z direction with respect to the other. A moving ‘wave’ can then be obtained by letting time functions appropriately weigh ‘neighbouring’ spatially oscillatory solutions such that neighbouring oscillatory solutions subsequently blend into one another. If this ad hoc construction of a moving wave is after all convincing, we have indeed found a sense in which NCT allows for propagating waves. That is, we can arbitrarily approximate travelling waves
$$ \Psi^{\prime} (x, y, z, t) = \sin (z-z_0(t)) $$
through the superposition of standing wave solutions
$$ \Psi (x, y, z, t) = \int da A(a, t) \sin (z-z^{\prime}_0(a)), $$
where A(a, t) is an appropriately-chosen modulating amplitude (essentially allowing for the blending of the oscillatory function \(\sin (z-z'_0(a))\) into \(\sin (z-z'_0(a'))\) over time), and a is a variable marking individual oscillatory functions, in particular their characteristic shift \(z'_0(a)\) and their aforementioned time-varying amplitudes A(a, t)).
It is important to stress that these wavelike potentials are not gauge artefacts, but empirically relevant insofar as the force field associated to the potential inherits its propagating nature; for instance, for the potential \(\Psi (x, y, z, t)\) above, the corresponding force field amounts to
$$ {\vec{F}}(x, y, z, t) := -{\vec\nabla} \Psi (x, y, z, t) = \int da A(a, t) \left( \begin{array}{c} \sin (z-z^{\prime}_0(a))\\ \sin (z-z^{\prime}_0(a))\\ - \cos (z-z^{\prime}_0(a))\\ \end{array} \right) . $$
This force field can be directly measured through point particle probes. Transitioning back to the geometric picture of Newton-Cartan gravity via the Trautman recovery theorem, such propagating changes in the potential/Newtonian force field correspond to moving ‘ripples’ of spacetime (which are just as well measurable through point particle probes).Footnote 7
Nevertheless, a straightforward reification of these individual standing waves making up the propagating wave, à la a naïve realist, seems to first of all speak against such a construction: there is no single wave moving here, but rather a conspiratorial evolution of individual standing waves. However, progress can be made by asking the following question: independently of the mathematical means of representation of a certain state of affairs, what is effectively expressed by the mathematical expressions under consideration? And here it seems without doubt that the right temporal modulation of spatially oscillatory functions can codify a moving pattern—even though, within our mathematical description, this looks like a conspiratorial set-up of standing-waves.Footnote 8 So, as long as we think of the mathematical language at play as first of all a toolkit, without premature attempts at direct reification, a set of appropriately modulated ‘standing’ waves can just as well be used to describe signal transport as an ordinary plane wave package.Footnote 9
Still, a propagating solution that is in any physically meaningful sense associable with information/signal transfer must, one might think, be linked to energy transfer. But standing waves are exactly those kind of waves that do not allow for energy transfer—why should some concerted movement of several standing waves be linked to energy transfer, then? Now, in response to this, one might (1) attack the view that information/signal transfer is necessarily associated with energy transfer as such, or one might (2) associate some notion of energy to the piecewise constructed propagating solution at an emergent level. In support of (1), one could say that it is only under the presupposition of a possibly-problematic energy-transfer account of causality that we arrive at this view; and that a physical notion of wave propagation is possible without such an energy-transfer account. In fact, Dewar and Weatherall express in the very same paper their concern about the status of gravitational energy in NCT. Thus, they should indeed, it seems, regard it as being problematic to attribute energy transfer to gravitational waves in NCT; they might then seek to extend this separation of the notions of information/signal transfer and energy transfer to all Newtonian contexts. One potential resource to which Dewar and Weatherall could appeal here is the work of Dürr on gravitational waves in GR: they exist, and can propagate to mediate information transfer, but they do not carry energy (cf. [10]).
What about option (2), given that a functionalist stance on signal propagation is arguably a natural inspiration for taking the relevant notion of energy at play to be a higher level functionalist concept as well?Footnote 10 We accepted a long time ago that a notion of energy at one level of description does not require a notion of energy at a lower level of description. This is because notions of energy are associated with notions of time-translation invariance which itself is a symmetry which can be realised at one level of description even if it is not realised at more or less fundamental levels of description. While we do not see ourselves in a position to calculate such a putative higher-level notion of energy explicitly in the current case, there is no clear sense in which this option is ruled out either; the objection can at least not be that there is no way to associate the piecewise-constructed wave functions to a sensible notion of energy transfer at a coarse-grained level.
Furthermore, it is worth pointing out that the current proposal for information-carrying solutions to the (purely spatial) Poisson equation(s) and an additional(!) temporal direction need not clash with any claim to the effect that elliptic equations are not informative in a preferred direction (cf. [22]). The temporal direction is not part of the elliptic geometric Poisson equation to begin with; rather, the information-propagating aspect is simply gained by suitable ‘stacking’ of solutions to the Poisson equation at each instant.
Newtonian Limits of Relativistic Waves
The second sense in which elliptic equations such as the Newton-Poisson equation can still, for Dewar and Weatherall, represent propagating solutions is articulated by considering the Newtonian limit of GR. In particular, they write that
we may think of Newtonian Weyl curvature as characterizing relativistic Weyl curvature–including gravitational waves–in the limit where the metric light cones flatten–and thus, the propagation velocity diverges. [Footnote suppressed.] In this limit, one would expect gravitational degrees of freedom to propagate instantaneously, in precisely the way described by an eliptic [sic] equation. [9, p. 575]
There are two possible interpretations of the solutions to the Poisson equation (1)Footnote 11—as representing either (i) no propagation, or (ii) instantaneous propagation—and, indeed, authors often vacillate between them.Footnote 12 Dewar and Weatherall, however, seek to break the symmetry in the Newtonian case with respect to gravitational radiation in that theory by considering the Newtonian limit of GR. To this, however, we would reply in the spirit of [11] as follows: the only way in which Dewar and Weatherall justify an interpretation of the Poisson equation as giving rise to gravitational waves is by reference to GR: but they thus do not establish that Newtonian gravity or NCT, considered on their own terms, in any clear and comprehensible manner features anything earning the name of a gravitational wave.
To make this point clear, note that the three-dimensional Newton-Poisson equation can be obtained from all sorts of differential equations, not just from hyperbolic partial differential equations, and in particular not just from the four-dimensional wave equations. For instance, it might just as well be obtained from a four-dimensional diffusion/heat equation: one simply need take the \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\) limit of
$$ \kappa \frac{\partial \psi }{\partial t} = \nabla ^2 \psi . $$
(2)
Without specific theory-relative information undergirding Dewar and Weatherall’s interpretation of the Poisson equation (1), there is no reason then why certain solutions should be read as idealised propagation processes akin to those described by a wave equation. Even if one upholds the posit that instantaneously-propagated physical effects are ultimately idealised descriptions of a finite propagation speed, nothing in NCT itself reveals whether the solutions to homogeneous equations describe propagation to begin with!
So, there are issues with using inter-theory relations to justify the existence of instantaneously-propagating gravitational waves in NCT. To bring these problems out further, consider the following reasoning, which would go through by analogy with Dewar and Weatherall’s own: is it the case that a point charge in NCT is (at times) a classical black hole—just because the former can be obtained from the latter in the course of the reduction of Schwarzschild spacetime to an NCT spacetime? Or: is the Newtonian mass a relativistic mass just because it comes out of the limit of a relativistic mass?Footnote 13
How might one respond on behalf of Dewar and Weatherall here? The following seems to us a reasonable line to take: although it is true that theories do, at least in part, ‘wear their interpretations on their sleeves’ (in, e.g., fixing their own senses of what is observable: see [30]), it is nevertheless the case that there are certain aspects of the interpretation of a theory which are determined only by pragmatic and contextual considerations regarding the application of that theory currently being made. For example, a simple harmonic oscillator equation might represent a block on a Hookean spring in one context, and an LC-circuit in another [16, §3.1]. Likewise, when we are discussing the Poisson equation as above, this may represent gravitational degrees of freedom in one context (in particular: when one is considering it qua limit of the field equations of GR), but not in another context (e.g.: when one is considering it qua limit of the diffusion equation). Thus, Dewar and Weatherall’s claims here are more defensible, if one backs away from a specific central conceit of the ‘semantic approach’ to scientific theories (cf. [32] for some classic discussion)—that models of a given theory may be interpreted ab initio as representing possible worlds, without further input contextual considerations—and moves towards a more ‘pragmatic’ approach to theory interpretation.Footnote 14 If one does so, then one is able to say that, since Dewar and Weatherall’s discussion is situated entirely in the context of considerations of gravitational physics, it is indeed appropriate to interpret terms in (1) in a way which is informed by limiting relations from other gravitational theories.
To summarise this section, then: Dewar and Weatherall maintain that solutions to the homogeneous Poisson equation in NCT can represent propagating gravitational degrees of freedom, and provide two arguments for this. First: it is possible to understand solutions to an elliptic equation as representing propagation. We have seen that Dewar and Weatherall’s own argument for this (in terms of oscillatory functions) is too fast—but that there does remain room to defend this claim, by appealing to piecewise-composed standing waves, together with a functionalist interpretation of these objects. (In addition, we have argued that concerns regarding the capacity of such objects to mediate energy transfer can be overcome.) Second: Dewar and Weatherall argue that one can interpret solutions of the homogeneous Poisson equation, when extended by an additional time direction, as mediating energy transfer by considering the Newtonian limit of GR—to which we respond that one has to be very careful with this style of reasoning, for it has the capacity to over-generate (as we will also see again in the next section); in our view, in making these claims, one has to be explicit about the theoretical context currently under consideration.