Skip to main content
Log in

Are Quantum Spins but Small Perturbations of Ontological Ising Spins?

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The dynamics-from-permutations of classical Ising spins is generalized here for an arbitrarily long chain. This serves as an ontological model with discrete dynamics generated by pairwise exchange interactions defining the unitary update operator. The model incorporates a finite signal velocity and resembles in many aspects a discrete free field theory. We deduce the corresponding Hamiltonian operator and show that it generates an exact terminating Baker–Campbell–Hausdorff formula. Motivation for this study is provided by the Cellular Automaton Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. We find that our ontological model, which is classical and deterministic, appears as if of quantum mechanical kind in an appropriate formal description. However, it is striking that (in principle arbitrarily) small deformations of the model turn it into a genuine quantum theory. This supports the view that quantum mechanics stems from an epistemic approach handling physical phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Denoting \(\mathcal OS\) by \(|A\rangle ,\; |B\rangle ,\; |C\rangle ,\; |D\rangle , \dots \), for example, such a dynamics could be simply this:

    $$\begin{aligned} |A\rangle \rightarrow |D\rangle \rightarrow |B\rangle \rightarrow \dots \;. \end{aligned}$$
    (1)

    This kind of evolution is the only possible one, unless the set of states itself changes, i.e., grows or shrinks. We do not consider a changing set of states here, however, this could be interesting when it comes to the evolving Universe.

  2. Diagonal operators on this basis are beables and their eigenvalues characterize physical properties of the states, corresponding to the labels \(A,\; B,\; C, \dots \) used in the previous footnote.

  3. The amplitudes that specify a \(\mathcal QS\) need interpretation, when describing experiments. By experience, relating amplitudes to probabilities has been extraordinarily useful. In this way, the Born rule is built in by definition! The Born rule can also be understood as a counting procedure related to a conserved two-time function of Hamiltonian cellular automata, which generalizes the norm of \(\mathcal QS\) [10]. It is is not forbidden by any element of quantum theory to abandon the proportionality between absolute values squared of complex amplitudes and probabilities, however, at the price of unnecessarily complicating its mathematical tools [1].

  4. Usually, they are thought to describe limiting situations of quantum mechanics, e.g. in presence of environment induced decoherence. They constitute the realm of classical physics.

  5. Using quantum superpositions of \(\mathcal OS\) to describe the initial state approximately, we obtain for an evolving \(\mathcal QS\) \(|Q\rangle \):

    $$\begin{aligned}&|Q\rangle :=\alpha |A\rangle +\delta |D\rangle +\dots,\;|\alpha |^2+|\delta |^2 +\dots \; =1, \end{aligned}$$
    (2)
    $$\begin{aligned}&\quad \text{ then }, |Q\rangle \;\longrightarrow \; \alpha |D\rangle +\delta |B\rangle +\dots . \end{aligned}$$
    (3)

    We see that the amplitudes remain the initial ones, while the \(\mathcal OS\) evolve by permutations, in the chosen example according to (1) of footnote 1.

  6. This does not imply that quantum mechanical superposition states are to be avoided. On the contrary, part of the motivation for CAI is to better understand, why they are so extremely effective in describing experiments probing nature.

  7. On a historical note, we add here that the discussion of ontological vs. epistemological approaches to the building of theories of physics has an intense precursor in times when Newtonian physics was superseded by field theories of forces in the sequel of Maxwell’s electrodynamics [15, 16]. The fine distinction between qualitatively different types of theories or theory building seems to have been lost during the rapid developments leading to Quantum Mechanics in the sequel. Attention to this has been drawn by Khrennikov, indicating possible consequences for the persisting interpretational problems of quantum theory [17].

  8. The following considerations work with other boundary conditions as well. However, periodic boundary conditions turn out to yield the most transparent picture of the dynamics.

  9. Shifting by an odd integer, instead, converts leftmovers and rightmovers into each other.

  10. Overall, beginning with \({\hat{U}}\) itself on the first line, the relations produce also an interesting functional equation for \({\hat{U}}\).

  11. It follows from Eq. (38) that the coefficients \(\pi /2\) can be replaced on the right-hand side of Eq. (39) without harm by \((2k+1/2)\pi \), with integer k. Similarly, a substitution by \((2k+3/2)\pi \) can be absorbed.

  12. Which is one motivation for the search of physics beyond the Standard Model, namely to yield stronger constraints on the large set of its parameters.

  13. ...who might suffer with us from the all-too-often blurred terminology when it comes to the foundations of quantum theory.

References

  1. ’t Hooft, G.: The Cellular Automaton Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Fundamental Theories of Physics. Springer, London (2016)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. ’t Hooft, G: Deterministic Quantum Mechanics: the Mathematical Equations. Front. Phys., to appear; Preprint. arXiv:2005.06374 [quant-ph] (2020)

  3. Elze, H.-T.: Qubit exchange interactions from permutations of classical bits. Int. J. Quant. Info. (IJQI) 17(8), 1941003 (2019)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  4. Elze, H.-T.: A Baker–Campbell–Hausdorff formula for the logarithm of permutations. Int. J. Geom. Meth. Mod. Phys. (IJGMMP) 17(4), 2050052 (2020)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Rovelli, C.: An argument against the realistic interpretation of the wave function. Found. Phys. 46(10), 1229 (2016)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Vervoort, L.: Bell’s theorem: two neglected solutions. Found. Phys. 43, 769 (2013)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Vervoort, L.: Probability theory as a physical theory points to superdeterminism. Entropy 21(9), 848 (2019)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  8. Wetterich, C.: Information transport in classical statistical systems. Preprint. arXiv:1611.04820v4 [cond-mat.stat-mech] (2016)

  9. Wetterich, C.: Fermions as generalized Ising models. Preprint. arXiv:1612.06695v2 [cond-mat.stat-mech] (2016)

  10. Elze, H.-T.: On configuration space, Born’s rule and ontological states. In: Kirsch, J., et al. (eds.) Discoveries at the Frontiers of Science. FIAS Interdisciplinary Science Series, vol. 253. Springer, London (2020)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Atmanspacher, H., Primas, H.: Epistemic and ontic quantum realities. In: Khrennikov, A. (ed.) Foundations of Probability and Physics—3. Conf. Proc. Series, vol. 750, p. 49. AIP, Melville (2005)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Khrennikov, A., Basieva, I., Pothos, E.M., Yamato, I.: Quantum probability in decision making from quantum information representation of neuronal states. Sci. Rep. 8, 16225 (2018)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  13. Khrennikov, A., Yurova, E.: Automaton model of protein: dynamics of conformational and functional states. Progr. Biophys. Mol. Biol. 130A, 2 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Elze, H.-T.: Linear dynamics of quantum-classical hybrids. Phys. Rev. A 85, 052109 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  15. Hertz, H.: The principles of mechanics: presented in a new form. Macmillan, London (1899)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Boltzmann, L.: Über die Frage nach der objektiven Existenz der Vorgänge in der unbelebten Natur. In: J.A. Barth (Leipzig) (ed.) Populäre Schriften, vol. 170 (1905)

  17. Khrennikov, A.: Hertz’ viewpoint on quantum theory. Activitas Nervosa Superior 61, 24 (2019)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Elze, H.-T., Schipper, O.: Time without time: a stochastic clock model. Phys. Rev. D 66, 044020 (2002)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  19. Elze, H.-T.: Emergent discrete time and quantization: relativistic particle with extradimensions. Phys. Lett. A 310, 110 (2003)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. Elze, H.-T.: Action principle for cellular automata and the linearity of quantum mechanics. Phys. Rev. A 89, 012111 (2014)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  21. Elze, H.-T.: Quantumness of discrete Hamiltonian cellular automata. EPJ Web Conf. 78, 02005 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Van-Brunt, A., Visser, M.: Explicit Baker–Campbell–Hausdorff formulae for some specific Lie algebras. Mathematics 6, 135 (2018)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Matone, M.: Closed form of the Baker–Campbell–Hausdorff formula for the generators of semisimple complex Lie algebras. Eur. Phys. J. C 76(11), 610 (2016)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

It is a great pleasure to thank Andrei Khrennikov for instigating the writing of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hans-Thomas Elze.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Elze, HT. Are Quantum Spins but Small Perturbations of Ontological Ising Spins?. Found Phys 50, 1875–1893 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00370-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00370-4

Keywords

Navigation