Skip to main content
Log in

Can Theories of Mental Representation Adequately Explain Mental Imagery?

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Traditionally it is taken for granted that mental imagery (MI) is a mental representation (MR) of some kind or format. This yields that theory of MR can give an adequate and exhaustive explanation of MI. Such co-relation between the two is usually seen as unproblematic. But is it really so? This article aims at challenging the theoretical claim that the dominant ‘two-world’ account of MR can adequately explain MI. Contrary to the standard theory of MR, there are reasons to believe that: (a) MI has different cognitive architecture, (b) the relations between elements of MI are dynamic, (c) relations between elements of MI are context-dependent. Consequently, it follows that dominant account of MR neglects important characteristics of MI and, thus, fails to give a comprehensive explanation of the latter. Alternatively, I will argue that a sign-theoretic approach, proposed by C. S. Peirce, can suggest a promising explanation of MI and fully account for the divergent empirical data on the matter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I call the representing relation between the physical and mental worlds dyadic, because this relation holds between two distinct domains. A dyadic relation is thus the type of relationship that holds between two entities.

  2. I use the term ‘cognitive architecture’ following Z. Pylyshyn (2002) to signify the underlying structure of MI, that is “properties and mechanisms [that] are intrinsic to, or constitutive of having and using mental images…” (Pylyshyn 2002: 159, original emphasis).

  3. Another alternative and non-representational approach to MI is the enactivist or sensorimotor theory (O’Regan and Nöe 2001; Thompson 2008; Thomas 2009, 2014). According to enactivism, imagery is a mental capacity of an active cognitive search of information in the absence of actual perceptual stimulus (Thomas 2009: 454–455). Although some empirical research (e.g. Bartolomeo 2007; Dulin et al. 2008; Moro et al. 2008) seems to support the enactivist theory, it still encounters serious problems (e.g. vagueness of the explanation of MI functioning) and thus remains unpopular among cognitivists.

References

  • Ambrosio, C. (2009). From similarity to homomorphism: toward a pragmatic account of representation in art and science, 1880–1914. In Proceedings of second biennial conference of SPSP: Society for philosophy of science in practice (pp. 1–17).

  • Ambrosio, C. (2014). Iconic representations and representative practices. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science,28(3), 255–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. R. (1978). Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychological Review,85, 249–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkin, A. (2013). Peirce’s theory of signs. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Resource document. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/peirce-semiotics/. Accessed 23 June 2018.

  • Bailer-Jones, D. (2003). When scientific models represent. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science,17(1), 59–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartolomeo, P. (2002). The relationship between visual perception and visual mental imagery: A reappraisal of the neuropsychological evidence. Cortex,38(3), 357–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartolomeo, P. (2007). Visual neglect. Current Opinion in Neurology,20, 381–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartolomeo, P. (2008). The neural correlates of visual mental imagery: An ongoing debate. Cortex,44(2), 107–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science,22(3), 295–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1983). Mental pictures and cognitive science. The Philosophical Review,92(4), 499–541.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buck, D. J. M., Hutchinson, J. C., Winter, C. R., & Thompson, B. A. (2016). The effects of mental imagery with video-modeling on self-efficacy and maximal front squat ability. Sports. https://doi.org/10.3390/sports4020023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (2006). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clapin, H. (2002). Philosophy of mental representation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deledalle, G. (2001). Charles S. Peirce’s philosophy of signs: Essays in comparative semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1992). What computers still can’t do: A Critique of artificial reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dulin, D., Hatwell, Y., Pylyshyn, Z. W., & Chokron, S. (2008). Effects of peripheral and central visual impairment on mental imagery capacity. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews,32, 1396–1408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1978). Mental representation. Erkenntnis,13, 9–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1990). A Theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. (2001). Psychology of mental representation. In N. J. Smelser & P. B. Baltes (Eds.), Encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences (pp. 9691–9695). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganis, G. (2013). Visual mental imagery. In S. Lacey & R. Lawson (Eds.), Multisensory imagery (pp. 9–28). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. (2011). Words and images: An essay on the origins of ideas. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent physical reality. Philosophy of Science,71(5), 742–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2004). On folk psychology and mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in mind: New approaches to mental representation (pp. 147–163). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy,21, 725–740.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubbard, T. (2007). What is mental representation? And how does it relate to consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies,14(1–2), 37–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Issajeva, J. (2015a). Sign theory at work: The mental imagery debate revisited. Sign Systems Studies,43(4), 584–596.

    Google Scholar 

  • Issajeva, J. (2015b). Mental imagery as a sign system. In A. Benedek & K. Nyiri (Eds.), Visual learning Beyond words: Pictures, parables, paradoxes (pp. 99–109). Frankfurt: Peter Lang Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, P. E. (2012). Mental imagery in music performance: Underlying mechanisms and potential benefits. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, The Neurosciences and Music IV Learning and Memory,1252, 206–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2005). Models as epistemic artefacts: Toward a non-representationalist account of scientific representation. Dissertation, University of Helsinki.

  • Knuuttila, T. (2011). Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science,42, 262–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and brain: The resolution of the imagery debate. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2013). Two notions of mental representation. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of mind (pp. 161–179). London, NY: Routledge Taylor and Francis Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, S., & Lawson, R. (2013). Multisensory imagery. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. (1981). Mind and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markman, A. B. (2012). Knowledge representation. In K. J. Holyoak & R. G. Morrison (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of thinking and reasoning (pp. 36–44). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (2006). Vision. In J. L. Bermudez (Ed.), Philosophy of psychology: Contemporary readings (pp. 385–406). London, NY: Routledge Taylor and Francis Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendelovici, A. (2012). Reliable misrepresentation and tracking theories of mental representation. Philosophical Studies,165(2), 421–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merrell, F. (2001). Charles Sanders Peirce’s concept of the sign. In P. Cobley (Ed.), The Routledge companion to semiotics and linguistics (pp. 28–39). London, NY: Routledge Taylor and Francis Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moro, V., Berlucchi, G., Lerch, J., Tomaiuolo, F., & Aglioti, S. M. (2008). Selective deficit of mental visual imagery with intact primary visual cortex and visual perception. Cortex,44, 109–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in mind: New approaches to mental representation (pp. 1–20). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, K. J., & Nöe, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,24(05), 939–973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, J., & Kosslyn, S. M. (2015). The heterogeneity of mental representation: Ending the imagery debate. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of United States of America,112(33), 10089–10092.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1994). The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Electronic edition, J. Deeley (Ed.), reproducing Vols. I–VI (1931–1935), C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; Vols. VII–VIII (1958), A.W. Burks (Ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). Excerpts from Letter to Lady Welby. In N. Houser, J. R. Eller, A. C. Lewis, A. D. Tienne, C. L. Clark, & D. B. Davis (Eds.), The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings (Volume 2, 1893–1913). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2017). Mental representation. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Resource document. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/mental-representation/. Accessed 23 June 2018.

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2000). Situating vision in the world. Trends in Cognitive Sciences,4(5), 197–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2002). Mental imagery: In search of a theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,25(2), 157–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2004). Imagery. In R. L. Gregory (Ed.), Oxford companion to the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2012). Representing without representations. Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies,3(1), 133–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1990). Is the brain a digital computer? Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association,64(3), 21–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (2017). Consciousness and intentionality. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Resource document. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/consciousness-intentionality. Accessed 23 June 2018.

  • Slezak, P. (1990). Re-interpreting images. Analysis,50(4), 231–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slezak, P. (1991). Can images be rotated and inspected? A test of the pictorial medium theory. In The proceedings of the thirteenth annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 55–60).

  • Slotnick, S. D., Thompson, W. L., & Kosslyn, S. M. (2005). Visual mental imagery induces retinotopically organized activation of early visual areas. Cerebral Cortex,15(10), 1570–1583.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suarez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science,71(5), 767–779.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, N. J. T. (2009). Visual imagery and consciousness. In W. Banks (Ed.), Encyclopedia of consciousness (pp. 445–457). Oxford: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, N. J. T. (2014). Mental imagery. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Resource document. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/mental-imagery/. Accessed 23 June 2018.

  • Thompson, E. (2008). Representationalism and the phenomenology of mental imagery. Synthese,160, 397–415.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy,92, 345–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T., & Port, R. (1995). It’s about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In R. Port & T. van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition (pp. 1–43). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Eckardt, B. (1993). What is cognitive science?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jelena Issajeva.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Issajeva, J. Can Theories of Mental Representation Adequately Explain Mental Imagery?. Found Sci 25, 341–355 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-019-09613-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-019-09613-8

Keywords

Navigation