Skip to main content
Log in

Outline of a Theory of Scientific Aesthetics

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I offer a theory of art that is based on science. I maintain that, as any other human activity, art can be studied with the tools of science. This does not mean that art is scientific, but aesthetics, the theory of art, can be formulated in accord with our scientific knowledge. I present elucidations of the concepts of aesthetic experience, art, work of art, artistic movement, and I discuss the ontological status of artworks from the point of view of scientific philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. From: The Soul of Man under Socialism, Fortnightly Review, London, February 1891, p. 292.

  2. I focus on theoretical aspects of scientific aesthetics. Experimental aesthetics deals with psychological research of artistic appreciation and it is not discussed here. The results of experimental research, however, are essential to test the theoretical concepts I introduce. See, for instance, Berlyne (1971) and Funch (1999).

  3. Examples include Alexandrian sculpture, French realist, naturalist, and decadentist literature, anti-war novels written in the 1920s by some outstanding French, German, and Austrian writers, whose main aim was to provoke revulsion, not pleasure, and much of contemporary plastic arts, among many other examples.

  4. The main character of the story is a playwright named Jaromir Hladík, who is living in Prague when the city is occupied by the Nazis during World War II. Hladík is arrested and charged with being Jewish as well as opposing the Anschluss, and sentenced to die by firing squad. During his execution God allows him a whole year of subjective time while everything else, including his body, remains motionless. Working from memory, Hladík mentally writes, expands, and edits a play, the artwork of his life, shaping every detail to his full satisfaction. Finally, after a year of labor, he completes the piece; only a single epithet is left to be written, which he chooses: time begins again and the fire from the rifles of the squad kills him. No one else will ever know that he finished his work and created the play.

References

  • Berlyne, D. E. (1971). Aesthetics and psychobiology. New York: Appletoll-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brattico, E., & Pearce, M. (2013). The neuroaesthetics of music. Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts, 7, 48–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1989). Ethics: The good and the right. In Treatise of basic philosophy (Vol. 8). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chandrasekhar, S. (1984). The general theory of relativity: Why “it is probably the most beautiful of all existing theories”. Journal of Astrophysics and Astronomy, 5, 3–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chao, W. Z. (1997). The beauty of general relativity. Foundations of Science, 2, 61–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, R. G. (1958). The principles of art. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1989). An ontology of art. New York: St Martin’s Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, S. (2013). Definitions of art. In B. Gaut & D. M. Lopes (Eds.), The Routledge companion to aesthetics (3rd ed., pp. 213–222). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Dio, C., & Gallese, V. (2009). Neuroaesthetics: A review. Current Opinion in Neurobilology, 9, 682–687.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. A. M. (1980). Why we believe in the Einstein theory. In B. Gruber & R. S. Millman (Eds.), Symmetries in science (pp. 1–11). New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorsch, F. (2000). The nature of aesthetic experiences, M. Phil. Thesis, University College London, London.

  • Ebert, R. (2004). Review of taxi driver. http://www.rogerebert.com/reviews/great-movie-taxi-driver-1976. Accessed 10 May 2017.

  • Einstein, A. (1915). In The collected papers of Albert Einstein, Volume 6: The Berlin years: Writings, 1914–1917 (p. 98) (trans: Engel, A.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Einstein, A. (1950). Out of my later years. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engler, G. (2002). Einstein and the most beautiful theories in physcis. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 16(1), 27–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engler, G. (2005). Einstein, his theories, and his aesthetic considerations. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 19(1), 21–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funch, B. S. (1999). The psychology of art appreciation. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landau, L. D., & Liftshitz, E. M. (1971). The classical theory of fields. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, F. (2016). Art theory for (neuro)scientists: Bridging the gap. Poetics Today, 37(4), 497–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meskin, A. (2008). From defining art to defining the individual arts: The role of theory in the philosophies of art. In K. Stock & K. Thomson-Jones (Eds.), New waves in aesthetics (pp. 125–149). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pais, A. (1982). Subtle is the Lord: The science and life of Albert Einstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renn, J., Janssen, M., & Schemmel, M. (Eds.). (2007). The genesis of general relativity (Vol. 4). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1966). The psychology of imagination (trans: B. Frechtman). New York: Washington Square Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slonimsky, N. (2000). Lexicon of musical invective: Critical assaults on composers since Beethoven’s time. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (1999). Fiction and metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (2004). The ontology of art. In P. Kivy (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to aesthetics (pp. 78–92). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D., & Christie, I. (Eds.). (1996). Scorsese on scorsese. London: Faber and Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1980). Art and its objects (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Federico Langer for constructive conversations and Daniela Pérez for reading the manuscript. My work is in part supported by Grant PIP 0338 (CONICET).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gustavo E. Romero.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Romero, G.E. Outline of a Theory of Scientific Aesthetics. Found Sci 23, 795–807 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9551-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9551-5

Keywords

Navigation