Skip to main content
Log in

A general revealed preference test for quasilinear preferences: theory and experiments

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Experimental Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We provide a generalized revealed preference test for quasilinear preferences. The test applies to nonlinear budget sets and non-convex preferences as those found in taxation and nonlinear pricing contexts. We study the prevalence of quasilinear preferences in a laboratory real-effort task experiment with nonlinear wages. The experiment demonstrates the empirical relevance of our test. We find support for either convex (non-separable) preferences or quasilinear preferences but weak support for the hypothesis of both quasilinear and convex preferences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These are the percentages of participants for whom we can reject random behavior at a \(5\%\) significance level. Details of these calculations are in Sect. 4.

  2. That is, if \(y\in B^t\), then \(y'\in B^t\) for every \(y'\le y\).

  3. A function \(\mu : X\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) is decreasing if \(x\ge x'\) implies \(\mu (x')\ge \mu (x)\) and \(x > x'\) implies \(\mu (x') > \mu (x)\).

  4. A graph is said to be complete if there is an edge between every pair of vertexes. The construction we use is similar to that in Piaw and Vohra (2003).

  5. In this sense the quasilinear analog of the Varian (1983) is the test developed by Brown and Calsamiglia (2007).

  6. The crucial idea behind the requirement that each component is one-dimensional is that the corresponding set is fully ordered. Hence, we treat these notions as synonyms throughout the discussion.

  7. Dembo (2019) shows that this estimate is biased while the unbiased estimator is not computationally tractable.

  8. Differences in both means and medians are significant at \(p<.01\).

  9. Differences in both means and medians are significant at \(p<.01\).

  10. For a more detailed discussion of the method used to generate random choices and conducting hypothesis testing, see Cherchye et al. (2020).

  11. Of the 400000 random subjects, 20000 are consistent with LNU. These are used to construct cutoffs for QLU and C-LNU. Finally, 1,000 of random subjects consistent with QLU or C-LNU are used to generate cutoffs for C-QLU.

  12. The pass rate is a standard Binomial variable, where “success” is rejecting the null hypothesis (subject passed) and “failure” is not rejecting the null (subject failed). The Clopper-Pearson procedure provides exact confidence intervals. Results are similar if we estimate confidence intervals using the CLT (see Table 4). The significance levels we consider are \(p\in \{.10,.05,.01\}\) corresponding to the 90%, 95%, and 99% cutoffs. The right panel presents the HMI thresholds used in the analysis.

  13. Note that subjects are choosing over discretized budgets and therefore marginal conditions are only approximations. This pattern is observed for levels 3, 4, 6, and 7 tasks, but not at level 5. Concavity further requires that the changes in wages increase in the number of tasks (the marginal disutility of effort is increasing). That is, the maximal \(\triangle\)(wage) faced while choosing x tasks should be below the minimal \(\triangle\)(wage) faced while choosing y tasks for \(y>x\). Subject 7, depicted in Fig. 7c, provides an example of this. The implication is satisfied for \(\triangle\)(wage) corresponding to choices of 8 and 10 tasks. However, none of the choices of 9 tasks can be rationalized exactly by C-QLU.

  14. In terms of graph theory, this is equivalent to searching for the shortest walk (on a weighted directed graph), rather than a shortest path (on a weighted directed graph). However, the shortest walk is not always well-defined. A sufficient condition for it to be well-defined is the absence of negative cycles, which is guaranteed by cyclical monotonicity if we define the complete directed graph with vertexes as observations and weights as \(w_{s\rightarrow t} = m^t(x^t)-m^t(x^s)\).

References

  • Afriat, S. N. (1967). The construction of utility functions from expenditure data. International Economic Review, 8, 67–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Afriat, S. N. (1973). On a system of inequalities in demand analysis: An extension of the classical method. International Economic Review, 14, 460–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allcott, H., & Taubinsky, D. (2015). Evaluating behaviorally motivated policy: Experimental evidence from the lightbulb market. American Economic Review, 105, 2501–2538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, R., & Rehbeck, J. (2018). Assessing misspecification and aggregation for structured preferences.

  • Andreoni, J., & Miller, J. (2002). Giving according to garp: An experimental test of the consistency of preferences for altruism. Econometrica, 70, 737–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J., & Sprenger, C. (2012). Estimating time preferences from convex budgets. American Economic Review, 102, 3333–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Augenblick, N., Niederle, M., & Sprenger, C. (2015). Working over time: Dynamic inconsistency in real effort tasks. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 130, 1067–1115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Augenblick, N., & Rabin, M. (2019). An experiment on time preference and misprediction in unpleasant tasks. Review of Economic Studies, 86, 941–975.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. S. (1974). A theory of social interactions. Journal of Political Economy, 82, 1063–1093.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom, T. C., & Cornes, R. C. (1983). Independence of allocative efficiency from distribution in the theory of public goods. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 51, 1753–1765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. J., & Calsamiglia, C. (2007). The nonparametric approach to applied welfare analysis. Economic Theory, 31, 183–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrera, M., Royer, H., Stehr, M., Sydnor, J., & Taubinsky, D. (2022). Who chooses commitment? Evidence and welfare implications. Review of Economic Studies, 89, 1205–1244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cesarini, D., Lindqvist, E., Notowidigdo, M. J., & Östling, R. (2017). The effect of wealth on individual and household labor supply: Evidence from Swedish lotteries. American Economic Review, 107, 3917–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, C. P., & Echenique, F. (2016). Revealed preference theory (Vol. 56). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, C. P., & Echenique, F. (2017). A characterization of combinatorial demand. Mathematics of Operations Research.

  • Chen, D. L., Schonger, M., & Wickens, C. (2016). otree—An open-source platform for laboratory, online, and field experiments. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Finance.

  • Cherchye, L., De Rock, B., & Vermeulen, F. (2012). Married with children: A collective labor supply model with detailed time use and intrahousehold expenditure information. American Economic Review, 102, 3377–3405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherchye, L., Demuynck, T., & De Rock, B. (2015). Is utility transferable? A revealed preference analysis. Theoretical Economics, 10, 51–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherchye, L., Demuynck, T., De Rock, B., & Lanier, J. (2020). Are consumers rational? shifting the burden of proof. FEB Research Report Department of Economics.

  • Cherchye, L., Demuynck, T., De Rock, B., & Vermeulen, F. (2017). Household consumption when the marriage is stable. American Economic Review, 107, 1507–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S., Fisman, R., Gale, D., & Kariv, S. (2007). Consistency and heterogeneity of individual behavior under uncertainty. American Economic Review, 97, 1921–1938.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deb, R., Kitamura, Y., Quah, J. K. H., & Stoye, J. (2018). Revealed price preference: theory and empirical analysis. arXiv preprint arXiv:1801.02702.

  • Dembo, A. (2019). Rationality and error in individual choice data: a revealed preferences approach. Technical Report. Working paper.

  • Domencich, T. A., & McFadden, D. (1975). Urban travel demand-a behavioral analysis. Technical Report.

  • Dziewulski, P. (2020). Just-noticeable difference as a behavioural foundation of the critical cost-efficiency index. Journal of Economic Theory, 188, 105071.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Echenique, F. (2014). Testing for separability is hard. arXiv preprint arXiv:1401.4499 .

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1990). Utility theory and decision theory. Palgrave Macmillan UK.

  • Fisman, R., Kariv, S., & Markovits, D. (2007). Individual preferences for giving. The American Economic Review, 97, 1858–1876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forges, F., & Minelli, E. (2009). Afriat’s theorem for general budget sets. Journal of Economic Theory, 144, 135–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giupponi, G. (2019). When income effects are large: Labor supply responses and the value of welfare transfers.

  • Golosov, M., Graber, M., Mogstad, M., & Novgorodsky, D. (2021). How Americans Respond to Idiosyncratic and Exogenous Changes in Household Wealth and Unearned Income. National Bureau of Economic Research: Technical Report.

  • Green, J., & Laffont, J. J. (1977). Characterization of satisfactory mechanisms for the revelation of preferences for public goods. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 45, 427–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houtman, M., & Maks, J. (1985). Determining all maximal data subsets consistent with revealed preference. Kwantitatieve methoden, 19, 89–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleven, H. J. (2016). Bunching. Annual Review of Economics, 8, 435–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krishna, V. (2009). Auction theory. Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matzkin, R. L. (1991). Axioms of revealed preference for nonlinear choice sets. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 59, 1779–1786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. B. (1981). Optimal auction design. Mathematics of Operations Research, 6, 58–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nocke, V., & Schutz, N. (2017). Quasi-linear integrability. Journal of Economic Theory, 169, 603–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaw, T. C., & Vohra, R. V. (2003). Afriat’s theorem and negative cycles. preprint.

  • Polisson, M. (2018). A lattice test for additive separability.

  • Porter, M., & Adams, A. (2015). For love or reward? characterising preferences for giving to parents in an experimental setting. The Economic Journal, 126, 2424–2445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richter, M. K. (1966). Revealed preference theory. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 34, 635–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rochet, J. C. (1987). A necessary and sufficient condition for rationalizability in a quasi-linear context. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 16, 191–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rockafellar, R. T. (1970). Convex analysis. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strack, P., & Taubinsky, D. (2021). Dynamic preference “reversals” and time inconsistency. National Bureau of Economic Research: Technical Report.

  • Toussaert, S. (2018). Eliciting temptation and self-control through menu choices: A lab experiment. Econometrica, 86, 859–889.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varian, H. R. (1983). Nonparametric tests of models of investor behavior. Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 18, 269–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Castillo.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary file 1 (pdf 142 KB)

Appendices

Appendix 1: Proof of Theorem 1

Proof

(\(\Rightarrow\)) Consider a function \(v(x,m) = u(x) +m\) that rationalizes the consumption experiment. For clarity, we maintain the notation \(m^t(x^s)\), \(m^t(x^t)\) and \(m^t(x)\) for the rest of the proof. Then, for every sequence of observations \(k_1,k_2,\ldots , k_n \in \{1,\ldots ,T\}\), the following is true:

$$\begin{aligned} u(x^{k_{j+1}})+m^{k_{j+1}}(x^{k_{j+1}})\ge u(x^{k_{j}}) + m^{k_{j+1}}(x^{k_{j}}), \end{aligned}$$

where \(k_{n+1}=k_1\). We can simplify this and obtain the following inequalities:

$$\begin{aligned} {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} &{} m^{k_1}(x^{k_1}) - m^{k_1}(x^{k_2}) \ge u(x^{k_2}) - u(x^{k_1}), \\ &{} m^{k_2}(x^{k_2}) - m^{k_2}(x^{k_3}) \ge u(x^{k_3}) - u(x^{k_2}), \\ &{}\ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \ \ldots \\ &{} m^{k_n}(x^{k_n}) - m^{k_n}(x^{k_1}) \ge u(x^{k_1})-u(x^{k_n}). \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

Summing up these inequalities, we obtain the following:

$$\begin{aligned} m^{k_1}(x^{k_1}) - m^{k_1}(x^{k_2})+ m^{k_2}(x^{k_2}) - m^{k_2}(x^{k_3}) +\ldots + m^{k_n}(x^{k_n}) - m^{k_n}(x^{k_1})\ge 0. \end{aligned}$$

This is exactly the cyclical monotonicity condition.

(\(\Leftarrow\)) This part of the proof is split in two parts. First, we construct the subutility numbers corresponding to the observed choices and show that the observed chosen point \((x^t,m^t)\) is at least as good as any other point \((x^s,m^t(x^s))\). Next, we extend the subutility function to the entire \(\mathbb {R}^n_+\) and show that corresponding QLU rationalizes the data.

Let

$$\begin{aligned} u^t = \min \{m^{k_1}(x^{k_1})-m^{k_1}(x^{t})+\ldots +m^{k_{n}}(x^{k_n})-m^{k_n}(x^{k_{n-1}})\} \end{aligned}$$

over all sequences in the data, including those with repeating elements.Footnote 14 Note that all the sequences are starting with \(k_1\), however, the real “anchoring” element of the sequence is \(k_2=t\) for the observation \(t\in T\). We will show that the minimum is well-defined. It will be enough to show that there will be no cycles in the minimal sequence, since the rest will follow from the fact that the minimum is taken over finite sums of finite numbers. So assume, to the contrary, that the minimum sequence contains a cycle; then we have

$$\begin{aligned} \ldots + \left( m^{k_n}(x^{k_n})-m^{k_n}(x^{k_{n-1}}) + \ldots + m^{k_1}(x^{k_1}) - m^{k_1}(x^{k_n})\right) + \ldots . \end{aligned}$$

However, cyclical monotonicity implies that this term is greater or equal than zero, and hence, excluding it would make the sequence even smaller. That contradicts the original assumption that the sequence was the smallest.

Further, we show that such a construction of \(u^t\) will guarantee that the following system of inequalities is satisfied. For any \(t,s\in \{1,\ldots , T\}\) we want to show that

$$\begin{aligned} u^t - u^s \ge m^t(x^s)-m^t(x^t). \end{aligned}$$

By the construction of u(x), we can guarantee that

$$\begin{aligned} u^s \le m^t(x^t)-m^t(x^s)+u^t, \end{aligned}$$

since

$$\begin{aligned} u^t = m^{k_1}(x^{k_1})-m^{k_1}(x^t)+\ldots +m^{k_{n}}(x^{k_n})-m^{k_n}(x^{k_{n-1}}) \end{aligned}$$

for some (minimal) sequence, and we construct \(u(x^s)\) using that minimal sequence. Recall that we allowed taking every sequence, including those with repeating elements, so we can add any element to the existing sequence and the utility level \(u(x^s)\) will not exceed the value of the new extended sequence. Therefore,

$$\begin{aligned} u^t-u^s\ge u^t - \left( m^t(x^t)-m^t(x^s)+u(x^t)\right) =m^t(x^s)-m^t(x^t). \end{aligned}$$

This concludes the first part of the proof. Next, we use the numbers constructed above to recover the entire utility function.

For every \(x\in X\), let

$$\begin{aligned} u(x) = \min \limits _{t\in \{1,\ldots , T\}} \{u^t+m^t(x^t)-m^t(x)\}. \end{aligned}$$

Note that since \(m^t\) is continuous and monotone, so is u(x).

First, we will show that for every \(t\in \{1,\ldots , T\}\), \(u(x^t)=u^t\). As we have shown above for every \(s\in \{1,\ldots , T\}\) for which \(m^s(x^t)\) is defined,

$$\begin{aligned} u^t\le u^s + m^s(x^s)-m^s(x^t). \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, \(u(x^t)=u^t\). Next, we show that the constructed utility rationalizes the data, that is \(v(x,m)\le v(x^t,m^t(x^t))\) for every \((x,m)\in B^t\), where \(v(x,m) = u(x)+m\). By the construction of u(x), we know that \(u(x) = \min \limits _{t\in \{1,\ldots , T\}} \{u^t+m^t(x^t)-m^t(x)\} \le u^t+m^t(x^t)-m^t(x)\). Therefore, \(u(x)+m \le u(x)+m^t(x) \le u(x^t)+m^t(x^t)\). \(\square\)

Given the proof of the Theorem 1 one can immediately infer the following remark.

Remark 2

A consumption experiment \(E=((x^t,m^t),B^t)_{t=1}^T\) can be rationalized by a QLU function if and only if there is a monotone function \(u: C\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} u(x^t)-u(x^s) \ge m^t(x^s)-m^t(x^t) \text { for every } t,s\in \{1,\ldots ,T\}. \end{aligned}$$

where \(C = \bigcup \limits _{t\in \{1,\ldots ,T\} } \{x^t\}\) is the set of chosen points.

Remark 2 crucially important for the following reason. Cyclical monotonicity is an elegant condition, it may be less computationally tractable especially once mixed with measures of distance to rationality. However, the linear programming approach provides the definitely computationally tractable way of testing QLU rationalizability.

Appendix 2: Additional empirical results

This appendix presents additional empirical analysis. We first present additional results using the HMI index. We then present analysis using the Critical Cost Efficiency Index (CCEI) introduced by Afriat (1973). The results are robust to alternative measures of distance to rationality.

1.1 Additional results for HMI

We present two additional tables. Table 3 presents unconditional pass rates. Table 4 presents an alternative construction of confidence intervals using normal approximations instead of the exact procedure.

Table 3 Left panel: Pass rates for each theory considered. Unlike Table 2 in the main text, this table reports unconditional pass rates. The first number is the percentage pass rate; the fraction in parentheses is the numbers of subjects used to compute the pass rates; the numbers brackets are the 95% confidence intervals. Right panel: HMI cutoffs for different p-levels

Table 3 replicates the results of Table 2 but uses unconditional pass rates instead. These numbers serve for purely illustrative purposes, as it is not totally correct to analyze nested theories using unconditional pass rates. Recall that the nested structure can be summarized as follows.

$$\begin{aligned} \text {C-QLU(C)} \subseteq \text {C-LNU} \subseteq \text { LNU } \text { and } \text {C-QLU(Q)} \subseteq \text {QLU} \subseteq \text { LNU } \end{aligned}$$

That is, C-QLU is nested within both C-LNU and QLU, while both C-LNU and QLU are nested within LNU. Finally, C-LNU and QLU are independent theories.

Table 4 replicates the results of Table 2 using the CLT approximations for the confidence intervals of pass rates. Note that unlike the confidence intervals generated by Clopper-Pearson procedure (exact confidence intervals), the CLT confidence intervals are symmetric. Thus, they might run out of the domain: returning values above one or below zero. Even though there are no bound violations in our data we prefer to report the exact confidence intervals. Using the CLT confidence intervals does not alter the results presented in Table 2.

Table 4 Left panel: Pass rates for each theory considered. Unlike Table 2 in the main text, this table reports confidence intervals for pass rates using CLT approximations. The first number is the percentage pass rate; the fraction in parentheses is the numbers of subjects used to compute the pass rates; the numbers brackets are the 95% confidence intervals. Right panel: HMI cutoffs for different p-levels

1.2 Analysis using CCEI

Another measure of distance to rationality is the Critical Cost Efficiency Index (CCEI) introduced by Afriat (1973). The definition of the CCEI in the augmented consumption space we consider is, however, ambiguous. An interpretation of the CCEI is the share of wealth to be left on the table needed to make an agent rational. This can be done in linear budget sets straightforwardly. Assume all prices (p) are set up such that for each budget set income is normalized to be equal to 1. Then \(p^t y \le 1\) defines the “revealed preference relation.” The CCEI redefines this constraint by introducing \(e\in [0,1]\) such that \(p^t y \le e\) defines a new revealed preference relation. In this case \(1-e\) provides the relative measure of the wealth one needs to sacrifice in order to rationalize observed choices. Further, the CCEI finds the maximal e (minimizing potential wealth losses) such that observed choices are rationalizable.

However, in the augmented consumption space, “wealth” (wage in our context) is already one of the dimensions of the consumption space. Thus one option is to consider only changes in wages. This corresponds to the case described on the Fig. 9b. An alternative explanation of the CCEI is based on the idea of “thick indifference curves” or “just noticeable differences” as axiomatized by Dziewulski (2020). This interpretation allows us to disregard the fact that the consumption space includes money already. This interpretation allows shifting the budget downwards as presented in Fig. 9a. The nonlinearity of the budget set, however, produces another complication. Since we are using piece-wise linear budgets, it matters if the value of x at which price regime changes Varies with the level of the CCEI. The just noticeable difference interpretation of the CCEI (see Fig. 9a) implies that the “break-point” varies with e. The wealth interpretation of the CCEI (see Fig. 9b) does not allow the break-point to vary with e. Next we present the results for the pass rates for both interpretations of CCEI.

Fig. 9
figure 9

Introducing CCEI in augmented space

1.2.1 CCEI based on wealth

Table 5 presents the results as in Table 2 using the CCEI based on changes in wealth only (version from Fig. 9b) as the measure of distance to rationality. The pass rates for LNU and QLU are comparable to those using HMI. However, comparing C-LNU to QLU we observe that the pass rates for C-LNU are lower. This is evidence that the assumption of concavity is more restrictive than quasilinearity. Overall we see that the pass rates for C-QLU(Q) are lower than those for QLU. We observe that concavity is a restrictive assumption. However, pass rates for C-QLU(C) and C-LNU are comparable. Thus, adding the quasilinearity assumption to C-LNU does not seem to be restrictive.These results are consistent with the results presented in Table 2.

Table 5 Left panel: pass rates with absolute numbers in parentheses and confidence intervals for the pass rates in brackets. Tests for QLU and C-LNU are conditional on passing LNU; tests for CQLU are conditional on either QLU or C-LNU. Right panel: CCEI cutoffs for the given “significance” level

1.2.2 CCEI based on just noticeable differences

Table 6 presents results using the just noticeable differences interpretation of the CCEI (version from Fig. 9a). We see that the main results still hold. First, we see that pass rates for QLU condition on LNU are high. Moreover, using this version of the CCEI we obtain higher pass rates for QLU than C-LNU. We also see that pass rates for C-LNU are weakly lower than those of C-QLU(C) for all significance levels. This means that under the assumption of concavity adding quasilinearity is costless. Finally, we see that pass rates for C-QLU(Q) are lower than those of QLU. This agrees, accounting for noise, with the results obtained with alternative measures of rationality. We conclude that our main finding of quasilinearity is not more restrictive than concavity (see Table 2) does not depend on the measure of distance to rationality utilized.

Table 6 Left panel: pass rates with absolute numbers in parentheses and corresponding confidence intervals in brackets. Tests for QLU and C-LNU are conditional on passing LNU; tests for CQLU are conditional on either QLU or C-LNU. Right panel: CCEI cutoffs for the given “significance” level

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Castillo, M., Freer, M. A general revealed preference test for quasilinear preferences: theory and experiments. Exp Econ 26, 673–696 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10683-023-09790-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10683-023-09790-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation