Some may think it obvious that performing any action that lowers the objective probability of fulfilling a moral obligation is morally wrong. For by performing an action that lowers the chances of fulfilling a moral obligation, you make it less likely that you will perform an action you are morally required to perform. So, the following may seem obvious:
-
(A)
If an agent, X, is under a moral obligation at a time t to perform some action at a later time t’, and faces a choice between (at least) two actions, Φ and Ψ, then if performing Φ as opposed to Ψ will lower X’s chance of fulfilling their moral obligation at t’, then it is morally wrong for X to Φ.Footnote 4
To explain: suppose that today (t) you have a moral obligation to deposit a cheque tomorrow (t’) for your friend to pay for his flight to see an ailing relative. Suppose, further, that you face a choice today between two actions, Φ and Ψ, where performing them makes the probability that you will deposit the cheque promptly 0.99 and 1.0 respectively.Footnote 5
According to (A), it would be morally wrong to perform Φ. For it would lower the chances of performing this action for your friend relative to at least one other action available to you, Ψ. But this seems false.
That is, the fact that a given action lowers the objective probability of performing some other morally obligatory act by some very small extent, relative to another action available to you, does not seem morally wrong. To illustrate this further, consider:
Car: Your best friend, Adam, calls you in need of urgent help. You are the only person who can help him and can do so at little cost to yourself. You have two ways to get to Adam: taking your car or the final bus on the requisite route which is presently outside your house. Taking your car will require driving amongst other cars, whilst the bus will drive through empty bus lanes. You opt for your car.
It seems, first, that you have a moral obligation to help Adam in the immediate future. Second, that getting in your car to drive to Adam will, to some extent, lower the objective probability of helping him relative to taking the final bus – since you incur the risk of accident, however small, whilst you do not if you take the final bus as it will be the only vehicle on the dedicated bus lane.
It does not seem, however, that by taking your car you would be doing anything morally wrong. Adam, for example, would have no strong moral complaint against you for doing so, and you would be taking a mode of transport that does not render your chances of fulfilling your obligation to him extremely slim (even if doing so lowers your chances of helping him relative to taking the bus).
If so, these cases show that it is false that any action that lowers the objective probability of fulfilling a moral obligation to some very small extent, relative to another action available to that agent, is morally wrong. So, (A) is false.
But now consider:
Car*: Same as Car, except your car is extremely unreliable. The overwhelming majority of times you have driven your car, it has broken down during your journey in need of repair. Despite this, you opt for your car.
Unlike Car, it does seem morally wrong for you to take your car in Car*. Relative to taking the bus, taking your car here will drastically decrease your chances of fulfilling your moral obligation to Adam (since it is very likely to break down). This is not the case in Car, where taking your car would only slightly lower your chances of fulfilling your moral obligation to Adam relative to taking the bus.
To answer (The Question) we need an explanation of the intuitive difference in the moral status of the actions you perform in Car and Car*. I suggest the salient difference is this: the extent to which the action you perform lowers your chances of fulfilling your moral obligation, relative to at least one other action available to you, drastically differs. In the former, the extent to which your chances of fulfilling your moral obligation are lowered appears insignificant. This is not so in Car*.
Since all else is equal between these cases, yet it seems that performing the chance-affecting action in Car* is morally wrong and not so in Car, this is good reason to think that the fact that taking your car in Car* is an action that will drastically decrease the objective probability of fulfilling your moral obligation (as opposed to one that, relative to other actions, only slightly lowers it) explains the intuitive wrongness of taking your car in that case and not the other.
This suggests:
-
(B)
If an agent, X, is under a moral obligation at a time t to perform some action at a later time t’, and faces a choice between (at least) two actions, Φ and Ψ, then if performing Φ as opposed to Ψ will drastically lower X’s chance of fulfilling their moral obligation at t’, then it is morally wrong for X to Φ.
(B) captures our intuitions. It entails that, in Car*, you are doing something morally wrong by taking your car which – relative to taking the bus – will drastically lower the chances of fulfilling your moral obligation. Additionally, it does not entail that in Car or the case used to illustrate (A) that you are doing anything morally wrong. These chance-affecting actions are not ones that will drastically decrease the chances of fulfilling your moral obligation relative to other actions available to you.Footnote 6
(B), however, is false. For consider:
Charity: You donate £10 a month to a charity that aims to alleviate extreme poverty in a distant country. Unbeknownst to you, every month this money has been intercepted by a ruthless gang leader in that country who uses it to fund his pillaging of nearby towns. When next month comes and donations for this charity are being accepted, you decide to donate to the same charity again.
It is plausible that you have a moral obligation to contribute to some extent to alleviating extreme poverty. This obligation, in Charity, may obligate you to donate money at a time at which donations are being accepted and where you can contribute at little cost to yourself.
By donating your money in the coming month to the same charity, you would be performing an action that will drastically decrease the objective probability of fulfilling your moral obligation to contribute to the alleviation of extreme poverty, relative to, say, donating to another similar charity (since it is highly likely to be intercepted).
According to (B), your action would be morally wrong. But it does not seem to be morally wrong, despite it, relative to some other action available to you (like donating to a different charity), drastically decreasing the chances of fulfilling your moral obligation to help end extreme poverty. (B), then, is false.
For all you know in Charity, your act of donation is one that is likely to lead to meeting your moral obligation to aid in the alleviation of extreme poverty. Charity illustrates that one can perform an action they do not think will lower the chances of fulfilling some moral obligation but in fact does. Such actions, as Charity reveals, do not seem to be morally wrong.
The problem with (B) is that it ignores the epistemic limitations that agents may face regarding the likely effect of an action on the chances of that agent fulfilling their moral obligation in question. But, as we’ve seen, there are some actions which lower such chances that do seem morally wrong. This suggests a third answer to (The Question):
-
(C)
If an agent, X, is under a moral obligation at a time t to perform some action at a later time t’, and faces a choice between (at least) two actions, Φ and Ψ, then if performing Φ as opposed to Ψ is an action X has good reason to believe will drastically lower X’s chance of fulfilling their moral obligation at t’, then it is morally wrong for X to Φ.Footnote 7
This view has a number of attractive features.
First, it captures our intuitions in the case illustrating (A) and in Car, since it does not entail that you would be doing anything morally wrong by choosing an action that lowers your chances of fulfilling your moral obligation – relative to another action available – by a small extent.
Second, it entails that you would be doing something wrong by taking your car in Car*, since doing so is an action that you have good reason to believe – on the basis of the car’s past performance – to be an action that will drastically decrease your chances of fulfilling your obligation to Adam.
Finally, it does not entail that you are doing anything wrong in Charity: the ‘good reason to believe’ clause ensures that performing actions that you lack evidence regarding the chance-affecting features of does not render your action morally wrong. Rather, it concerns only those actions that agents have good reason to believe will have certain effects on the chances of fulfilling a moral obligation at a future time.
Despite this, there is good reason to believe that (C) is false. For consider:
War: You are called to fight in a just war in which the army of another country is invading your own nation. You are one of a small number of people eligible to fight in the war. To fight, you must leave your family, comprised of your spouse and your child. You accept the call and go to war.
In War, it is plausible that you are under a moral obligation to fight in the war (since it is a just war, and you are one of a small number of people eligible to fight in it). You, also, are under a range of moral obligations to (amongst others) your family to do various things for them in the future.
If you accept the call, however, you will be performing an action that, relative to declining the call, is one that you have good reason to believe will drastically decrease the chance of fulfilling at least some familial moral obligations in the future (since you are likely to either merely be physically absent from your family, to become debilitatingly wounded, or die).
(C), then, entails you have done something morally wrong by going to war. But War looks like a counterexample to (C). Despite doing something that you have good reason to believe will drastically decrease your chances of fulfilling at least one moral obligation, War seems to show that such an action is not morally wrong. So, (C) is false.
Consider, further, a variant of Car. Suppose that, whilst in your car, you notice an injured person on the side of the road. Further suppose that this person will die without medical attention, you are the only person who can help them to receive such attention, and by taking this detour to the hospital you drive in the opposite direction to Adam.
You face a choice of either taking the detour to save this person’s life or driving on to Adam. Again, despite being under a moral obligation to help Adam, and having good reason to believe taking this detour (as opposed to driving on) will lower your chances of meeting your obligation to him, it does not seem morally wrong to take the detour to save this other person’s life.
Now note, first, that there are clear cases where performing an action you have good reason to believe will lower your chance of fulfilling a moral obligation seems morally wrong – such as Car* and analogous cases. Second, in both of the above counterexamples to (C), there seems to be a competing moral consideration that outweighs any moral wrongness of performing an action you have good reason to believe will lower the chances of fulfilling your moral obligation.
I submit that what cases like War and the last variant on Car above show is that actions we have good reason to believe will drastically lower our chances of fulfilling a moral obligation are pro tanto moral wrongs. That is, they are moral wrongs that can be outweighed by competing moral considerations.
This allows us to capture that some chance-affecting actions in cases we have considered are morally wrong, and that this moral wrongness seems to be outweighed in at least those cases where performing the relevant chance-affecting action allows us to bring about another action we have stronger moral reasons to perform (such as defensive fighting against unjust threateners or saving a morally innocent life).Footnote 8
One may object that what War and our Car variant show is that the chance-affecting action is not morally wrong at all. That is, that if performing an action that you have good reason to believe will drastically lower your chance of fulfilling a moral obligation allows you to bring about some weightier moral good, then performing that action is not even pro tanto morally wrong.
This is false. Suppose that in the variant of Car above you called Adam on the way to the hospital to apologise for taking the detour. Notice that your apologising does not seem inappropriate, since you are doing something that makes it very unlikely that you will succeed in fulfilling your moral obligation to him. But if you were not doing anything wrong by taking the detour, then it would be inappropriate to apologise. So, this objection fails.
We arrive, then, at:
-
(D)
If an agent, X, is under a moral obligation at a time t to perform some action at a later time t’, and faces a choice between (at least) two actions, Φ and Ψ, then if performing Φ as opposed to Ψ is an action X has good reason to believe will drastically lower X’s chance of fulfilling their moral obligation at t’, then it is pro tanto morally wrong for X to Φ.
Of the answers considered, (D) is the most plausible answer to (The Question).
First, it does not entail that all actions that lower the chance of fulfilling a moral obligation by even some small extent relative to at least one other action available are morally wrong (the cheque case and Car).
Second, it captures our intuition that when agents perform actions that they have good reason to believe are very likely to drastically lower their chances of obligation-fulfilment, they are doing something morally wrong (Car*).
Third, it acknowledges that, in cases where agents do not have good reasons to believe their actions are ones that will drastically lower their chances of fulfilling their moral obligations, the agent does not act wrongly by performing such actions (Charity).
Fourth, it achieves the aforementioned whilst allowing that there are cases (like War and our last Car variant) where the moral wrongness of performing a chance-affecting action can be outweighed by competing moral considerations (whilst still being a moral wrong).
(D) concerns the performing of a single chance-affecting action. But, as mentioned in §1, some actions that we perform are tokens of types of action that we have good reason to believe the systematic performance of which will drastically decrease our chances of fulfilling a moral obligation at some later time.
The analogue principle to (D) in the case of engagement in such activities is also plausible:
(D*) If an agent, X, is under a moral obligation at a time t to perform some action at a later time t’, and faces a choice between (at least) two types of action, Φ and Ψ, then if systematically engaging in tokens of Φ as opposed to Ψ is something X has good reason to believe the systematic performance of which will drastically lower X’s chance of fulfilling a moral obligation at t’, then it is pro tanto morally wrong for X to systematically Φ.
To see why, take:
Pill: You have a moral obligation at time t0 to help someone at time t10. At t0, you are given the choice to take a course of pills from t0 to t10. Each pill provides some pleasure for a brief period after consumption whilst doing some minor, imperceptible harm to you. You are reliably informed that whilst consumption of a single pill will not significantly harm someone, those who take these pills systematically over a period of time will become extremely physically unwell. You take the pills.
Here it seems like you would be doing something morally wrong by systematically taking the pills between t0 to t10. A single pill alone will not lower the chances of fulfilling your moral obligation at t10, but systematically consuming them will. Doing this, when you have good reason to believe it will drastically lower your chances of fulfilling your moral obligation (relative to, say, not taking the pills), seems morally wrong – even if, in principle, this moral wrongness could be outweighed.Footnote 9
Two important qualifications to (D) and (D*). First, consider:
Murder: You spend most evenings at home with your partner. You realise that if you killed your partner and got away with it you would have much more free time in the evenings to volunteer at your local food bank. Despite this, you decide not to kill your partner.
Obviously, you have done the morally right thing in Murder. But notice that by choosing not to kill your partner, you have done something that you know – relative to killing them – drastically lowers the chances of your fulfilling your moral obligations to aid the extremely poor.
One may think that since, e.g., (D) claims that performing actions that you have good reason to believe will drastically lower your chances of fulfilling a moral obligation is pro tanto morally wrong, then this entails you have done something pro tanto morally wrong by not killing your partner and, in turn, that you in fact have a pro tanto moral obligation to kill your partner in Murder.
This is implausible. You do not do anything even pro tanto morally wrong by not killing your partner in Murder. Prima facie, no view about the moral status of chance-affecting actions should entail that you do something pro tanto morally wrong in not performing an action that is itself morally impermissible. Equivalently, it should not entail that you are under a pro tanto moral obligation to perform some action the performance of which is independently morally wrong – such as killing your partner in Murder.
So, if (D) entails you have done something pro tanto morally wrong by not killing your partner, then (D) is false. The same is true, of course, of (D*) in analogous systematic act cases.
(D) and (D*) can, however, be easily qualified to avoid this consequence, whilst retaining all of their aforementioned attractive features, in this way: that the actions you are choosing from are themselves otherwise morally permissible actions. That is, they must be actions that, outside of this chance-affecting context, would be permissible to perform.Footnote 10
(D), then, only concerns the moral status of chance-lowering actions that would be morally permissible to perform outside of the chance-affecting context in question. This ensures that (D) does not entail that you have done something pro tanto morally wrong by not killing your partner in Murder. For killing your partner here is already not a morally permissible action, and, as such, is not a candidate for a chance-affecting action that may be pro tanto morally wrong to perform on this view.Footnote 11
Second, take:
Job: You have been offered a high-paying job. The job, however, will put you at very high risk of physical harm. You have a choice between accepting this job or remaining unemployed. You choose to remain unemployed.
Declining the job is an action that you have good reason to believe will drastically lower your chances of fulfilling an obligation to assist those in extreme poverty, relative to taking the job, since you will forgo money to utilise in providing such aid. But you do not seem to have done anything wrong in remaining unemployed. If (D) entails that you have, then it looks false.
The reason, however, that you have not done something pro tanto morally wrong by making this chance-lowering choice seems to be that accepting the job would involve your incurring a heavy burden: putting your personal well-being at significant risk (so as to be able to donate to charity). You seem to be able to permissibly choose to avoid incurring this risk. This suggests that chance-affecting actions that you have good reason to believe will drastically lower your chances of fulfilling a moral obligation are not pro tanto morally wrong to perform when they are heavily burdensome on you.
So, the final qualification to (D) and (D*) is this: they concern only those actions that are not heavily burdensome on an agent to perform.Footnote 12 With this qualification, (D) avoids the implausible entailment that you do something wrong in Job by choosing to remain unemployed. In doing so, it respects the fact that agents have at least some personal prerogative to live as they choose and are not morally obligated to perform actions that require them to unreasonably incur a heavy burden.Footnote 13
So qualified, we have good reason to believe (D) and (D*) as they capture our intuitions in all of the cases discussed and avoid all of the problems identified with (A)-(C). I now defend these principles against three objections.
The first: since, on my view, any action that affects the objective probability of performing a moral obligation at a future time is a chance-affecting action, in principle any action can be chance-affecting. If so, then both (D) and (D*) might be overdemanding: they potentially concern any action that an agent can perform, since it could be a chance-affecting action.
This objection misunderstands (D) and (D*). (D) is a claim only about the pro tanto moral wrongness of a specific class of chance-affecting actions: otherwise permissible and not heavily burdensome actions that we have good reason to believe will drastically decrease the objective probability of fulfilling a given moral obligation at some future time.
By contrast, (A) is very demanding. It says that any action that lowers your chances of fulfilling a moral obligation is wrong. This entails that any chance-affecting action that lowers the chance of fulfilling a moral obligation even by a very small extent relative to another action is wrong. (D) and (D*) do not, concerning only certain actions agents have good reason to believe will (relative to at least one other action available) drastically lower the chance of their fulfilling a moral obligation.
A second objection: suppose we agree that in, e.g., Car* you would be doing something morally wrong by taking your car. This intuition, however, might be explained by your failing to meet some other moral obligation that you would be under that makes no reference to the fact that the action you perform somehow lowers your chance of fulfilling a moral obligation. For example, in Car* and Pill you might be under a general moral obligation captured by:
(Transmission): If X ought to Φ, all things considered, and Ψ is a necessary means to Φ-ing, then X should also Ψ, all things considered (Cordelli 2018: 383).Footnote 14
According to (Transmission), if I ought to help my friend (all things considered), and if my going to their house is a necessary means for me to help my friend, then I also ought to go to my friend’s house (all things considered).
Perhaps, then, in Car* the moral wrongness of taking my car is explained not by reference to (D) and the chance-lowering feature of that action, but, rather, that taking the bus is a necessary means to being able to help Adam. And since I ought to help him, and I failed to do something that is necessary to do that, then I have done something wrong by taking the car.
Even if (Transmission) is true, however, it cannot explain the moral wrongness of taking my car in Car*. For whilst taking my car will lower the chances of fulfilling my moral obligation to Adam, it is not a necessary means to help him. Rather, it will only lower my chances of being able to do so. This chance-lowering does not render taking the bus a necessary means to help Adam, but only the one that is more likely – relative to the car – to ensure that I can fulfil my obligation. So, this objection fails.
One might respond by suggesting that a revised form of (Transmission) can explain the wrongness of the chance-lowering actions that (D) and (D*) concern:
(Transmission*): If X ought to Φ, all things considered, and Ψ is a reasonable step to ensure that X will Φ, then X should also Ψ, all things considered.
In Car* and Pill, e.g., you might be under a general moral obligation to take all reasonable steps to ensure that you fulfil a moral obligation. By taking your car, or systematically consuming the pill, you would violate that obligation since they are actions that the agent has good reason to believe will drastically lower their chances of fulfilling their moral obligation. The failure to meet (Transmission*), then, might be the best explanation of our intuitions in these cases – and not (D) or (D*).
It is unclear whether (Transmission*) is true. But even if it is, there will be some explanation for why it is. Absent one, positing the existence of this general obligation alone as the best explanation for the intuition that certain chance-affecting actions are pro tanto morally wrong leaves unexplained why we may have this additional moral obligation.
But (D) and (D*) provide the desired explanation. For if it is pro tanto morally wrong to perform an action (or engage in a type of action) that we have good reason to believe will drastically decrease the chance of fulfilling a moral obligation in the future, then – on standard accounts of the relationship between moral wrongs and obligations – (D) and (D*) entail that we have a pro tanto moral obligation not to perform such actions.
The existence of this moral obligation would explain why there is a general obligation to take reasonable steps to ensure that we fulfil our moral obligations: because it is wrong to do those things that, absent weightier competing moral considerations, will drastically decrease our chances of fulfilling a moral obligation in the future. So, this revised form of the second objection fails.
Finally, one might protest that modal changes in a case can change what moral obligations an agent is under, and that this can explain why we find actions like those in Car* morally wrong. For example, perhaps once you enter your car and start driving you generate an additional moral obligation to change your behaviour and rectify having rendered the chance of your making it to Adam drastically lower than some other action you could perform (e.g. taking the bus).
But, again, the presence of a moral obligation to rectify your behaviour in Car* calls for explanation. And (D) provides this: the reason that you are (suppose) under a (pro tanto) moral obligation to get out of your car and catch the bus is because driving your car to Adam’s is, relative to taking the bus, an action you have good reason to believe will make it very unlikely you will fulfil your obligation to Adam. This concern, then, provides no reason to reject (D) (or (D*) in analogous cases) in light of modal changes in cases such as Car* (or Pill).