Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Mental Illness, Natural Death, and Non-Voluntary Passive Euthanasia

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When it is considered to be in their best interests, withholding and withdrawing life-supporting treatment from non-competent physically ill or injured patients – non-voluntary passive euthanasia, as it has been called – is generally accepted. A central reason in support of the procedures relates to the perceived manner of death they involve: in non-voluntary passive euthanasia death is seen to come about naturally. When a non-competent psychiatric patient attempts to kill herself, the mental health care providers treating her are obligated to try to stop her. Yet it has been suggested that death by suicide can be a part of the natural course of a severe mental illness. Accordingly, if the perceived naturalness of the deaths occurring in connection with non-voluntary passive euthanasia speaks for their moral permissibility, it could be taken that a similar reason can support the moral acceptability of the suicidal deaths of non-competent psychiatric patients. In this article, I consider whether the suicidal death of a non-competent psychiatric patient would necessarily be less natural than those of physically ill or injured patients who die as a result of non-voluntary passive euthanasia. I argue that it would not.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. While prognoses of patients suffering from severe mental illnesses are currently often less pessimistic than they were earlier, it would unfortunately still be exaggerated to maintain that all severe mental illnesses are curable, cf., e.g., Clemmensen et al. (2012)); Jobe and Harrow (2010); and Slade (2009).

  2. Callahan, Ryan, & Kerridge maintain that coercive suicide-preventing treatment is acceptable in the cases of non-competent patients. While Szasz argues against suicide-prevention, he also thinks that physician-assisted suicide is not acceptable medical practice. The Royal Dutch Association of Medicine, in its turn, allows that physical illnesses and injuries can provide grounds for physician-assisted dying and maintains that suicide based on psychiatric reasons should not be treated differently from assisted suicide in medicine generally. In Belgium, also, suffering unrelated to physical illness or injury is acknowledged in law as a valid basis for physician-assisted dying (cf. Royal Dutch Association of Medicine 2011 and, e.g., Naudts et al. 2006).

  3. Some understandings of naturalness, including the one employed here, allow that naturalness comes in degrees. I take it that, in this context, a death is natural enough when it is as natural as the deaths occurring in connection with non-voluntary passive euthanasia.

  4. It is possible for one to reject active euthanasia and endorse passive euthanasia and think that only the death occurring in connection with the former is natural without believing that its naturalness speaks for its moral acceptability. But then it is unclear what is meant by bringing up the issue of naturalness here and, as proposed, precisely why only passive euthanasia should be deemed morally acceptable. I am not saying that there could not be convincing answers to these questions but that it remains unclear what they would be.

  5. It has been proposed that ‘unresponsive wakefulness syndrome’ would be a more adequate name than ‘vegetative state’ for the condition in question (Laureys et al. 2010). Yet as the older terminology still appears to be more prevalent and, accordingly, less likely to cause confusion, I here use it, but without any intention of endorsing any pejorative connotations that might attach to it. For characterizations of the central features of the chronic disorders of consciousness see, e.g., Fine (2005).

  6. As the above usage of terminology suggests, in cases like that of Mary the question would commonly be taken to be about suicide. Accordingly, the expression ‘psychiatric non-voluntary passive euthanasia’ could be considered misleading, if not question begging. The considerations presented below provide reasons for putting this concern aside.

  7. The forms of euthanasia in which a patient is killed against her will, variations of involuntary euthanasia, are commonly morally condemned and legally prohibited.

  8. As suggested, referring to the division between killing and letting die or to that between intending and foreseeing death are not the only possible ways of arguing that active and passive euthanasia are morally different from each other (and the latter division has also been used in defending active euthanasia). It could instead be maintained that in passive euthanasia a harm is only permitted but in active euthanasia it is caused, that passive euthanasia does not take away anything a patient would have had without outside help whereas active euthanasia does, etc. Yet the divisions between killing and letting die and intending and foreseeing death would appear to be the most popular ones in this connection. And the other distinctions would seem to face similar problems as those two divisions: precisely why would a permitted harm be morally better than a caused one? Etc.

  9. The just characterized one is the main sense in which personal autonomy is understood in current medical ethics (see, e.g., Beauchamp and Childress 2008, Ch. 4). Yet it is not universally endorsed in the context (cf., e.g., Taylor 2009) and, as is also well-known, beyond the sphere of medical ethics a still wider variety of conceptions of autonomy can be found (see, e.g., Dworkin 1988; Garnett 2014; Kekes 2011). For further elucidation of the notion of personal autonomy employed above and defense of it against central rival conceptions of autonomy see, e.g., Beauchamp & Childress (2008, Ch. 4) and Beauchamp and Wobber (2014).

  10. To be sure, this is not to say that severely mentally ill people can never be morally responsible for their actions. For discussion relating to the difficulties pertaining to determining their responsibility see, e.g., Bortolotti et al. (2014) and Radden (2004).

  11. According to some understandings of the notion, naturalness is centrally about absence of human involvement.

  12. I here understand ‘treatment’ in a wide sense in which it encompasses, among other things, all of the means by which the mental health care providers taking care of Mary try to prevent her from killing herself.

  13. The other patients are, of course, suffering in the sense that they have a severe medical condition. But in that respect they and Mary are similar to each other.

  14. For arguments to the effect that the suffering caused by psychiatric conditions provides moral grounds for physician-assisted dying see, e.g., Cholbi (2013) and Hewitt (2013).

  15. Some recent studies suggest that patients with chronic disorders of consciousness may have feelings free of cognitive awareness, so that they may be in distress (see, e.g., J. Panksepp et al. 2007). Given that voluntary euthanasia is commonly taken to presuppose that a patient makes an autonomous request to die, the category of non-voluntary passive euthanasia would seem to encompass also patients who are known to suffer, but who are not autonomous. Accordingly, it would seem to be possible that some patients deemed eligible for non-voluntary passive euthanasia are in distress.

  16. This idea has been suggested before (Burgess and Hawton 1998, 121; “Hardcastle and Stewart 2002” 432–433), but arguments for it remain rare, if not non-existing.

References

  • American Medical Association Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs (2014-2015) Opinion 2.20 – Withholding or Withdrawing Life-Sustaining Medical Treatment. Code of Medical Ethics, 2014–2015. American Medical Association, Chicago IL http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-ethics/code-medical-ethics/opinion220.page? Accessed 29 Jan 2015

  • Appel JM (2007) A Suicide right for the mentally ill: a Swiss case opens new debate. Hast Cent Rep 3:21–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battin MP (2005) Ending life: ethics and the way we die. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp TL, Childress JF (2008) The principles of biomedical ethics, 6th edn. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp TL, Wobber V (2014) Autonomy in chimpanzees. Theor Med Bioeth 35:117–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti L, Broome MR, Mameli M (2014) Delusions and responsibility for action: insights from the Breivik case. Neuroethics 7:377–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan AE, Brock DW (1989) Deciding for others: the ethics of surrogate decision making. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgess S, Hawton K (1998) Suicide, euthanasia, and the psychiatrist. Philos Psychiatr Psychol 5:113–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Callaghan R, Ryan C, Kerridge I (2013) Risk of suicide is insufficient warrant for coercive treatment for mental illness. Int J Law Psychiat 36:374–385

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cholbi M (2013) The terminal, the futile, and the psychiatrically disordered. Int J Law Psychiat 36:498–505

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clemmensen L, Vernal DL, Steinhausen H-C (2012) A systematic review of the long-term outcome of early onset schizophrenia. BMC Psychiatry 12:150–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham C, Peters K (2014) Aetiology of schizophrenia and implications for nursing practice: a literature review. Issues Ment Health Nurs 35:732–738

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickens BM, Boyle JM, Ganzini L (2008) Euthanasia and assisted suicide. In: Singer PA, Viens AM (eds) The Cambridge textbook of bioethics. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 72–77

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas C (2009) End-of-life decisions and moral psychology: killing, letting die, intention and foresight. J Bioeth Inq 6:337–347

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin G (1988) The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fairbairn GJ (1995) Contemplating suicide: the language and ethics of self-harm. Routledge, Florence, KY

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fine RL (2005) From Quinlan to Schiavo: medical, ethical, and legal issues in severe brain injury. Proc (Bayl Univ Med Cent) 18:303–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanigan J (2014) Non-culpable ignorance and HIV criminalization. J Med Ethics 40:798–801

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garnett M (2014) The autonomous life: a pure social view. Australas J Philos 92:143–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett G (1994) Killing, letting die, and moral perception. Bioethics 8:312–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giordano S (2010) Anorexia and refusal of life-saving treatment: the moral place of competence, suffering, and the family. Philos Psychiatr Psychol 17:143–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glock H-J (2009) Can animals act for reasons? Inquiry 52:232–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez-Liencres C et al. (2014) Oxidative stress in schizophrenia: a case-control study on the effects on social cognition and neurocognition. BMC Psychiatry 14:268–277

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grisso T, Appelbaum PS (1998) Assessing competence to consent to treatment: a guide for physicians and other health professionals. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle VG, Stewart RW (2002) Supporting irrational suicide. Bioethics 16:425–438

  • Hewitt J (2010) Rational suicide: philosophical perspectives on schizophrenia. Med Health Care Philos 13:25–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hewitt J (2013) Why are people with mental illness excluded from the rational suicide debate? Int J Law Psychiat 36:358–365

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill DJ (2011) What is it to commit suicide? Ratio 24:192–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jobe TH, Harrow M (2010) Schizophrenia course, long-term outcome, recovery, and prognosis. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 19:220–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kekes J (2011) Doubts about autonomy. Philosophy 86:333–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendell RE (2001) The distinction between mental and physical illness. Brit J Psychiat 178:490–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laureys S et al. (2010) Unresponsive wakefulness syndrome: a new name for the vegetative state or apallic syndrome. BMC Med 8:68–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee A (2011) Me and my body: the relevance of the difference for the distinction between withdrawing life support and euthanasia. J Law Med Ethics 39:671–677

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee A (2015) Acting to let someone die. Bioethics 29:74–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLachlan HV (2008) The ethics of killing and letting die: active and passive euthanasia. J Med Ethics 34:636–638

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller FG, Truog RD, Brock DW (2010) Moral fictions and medical ethics. Bioethics 11:453–460

    Google Scholar 

  • Naudts K et al. (2006) Euthanasia: the role of the psychiatrist. Br J Psychiat 188:405–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panksepp J et al. (2007) Does any aspect of mind survive brain damage that typically leads to a persistent vegetative state? ethical considerations. Philos Ethics Humanit Med 2:1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker M (2013) Defending the indefensible? psychiatry, assisted suicide and human freedom. Int J Law Psychiat 36:485–497

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quill TE, Greenlaw J (2008) Physician assisted death. In: Crowley M (ed) From birth to death and bench to clinic: the Hastings Center bioethics briefing book for journalists, policymakers, and campaigns. The Hastings Center, Garrison, NY, pp. 137–142

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels J (1986) The end of life: euthanasia and morality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Radden J (2004) Identity: personal identity, characterization identity, and mental disorder. In: Radden J (ed) The philosophy of psychiatry: a companion. Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 133–146

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raus K, Sterckx S, Mortier F (2012) Continuous deep sedation at the end of life and the ‘natural death’ hypothesis. Bioethics 6:329–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Royal Dutch Association of Medicine (2011) The role of the physician in the voluntary termination of life. http://knmg.artsennet.nl/Publicaties/KNMGpublicatie-levenseinde/100696/Position-paper-The- role-of-the-physician-in-the-voluntary-termination-of-life-2011.htm. Accessed 13 Jan 2015

  • Sandman L (2005) Should people die a natural death? Health Care Anal 13:275–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siipi H (2008) Dimensions of naturalness. Ethics Environ 13:71–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slade M (2009) Personal recovery and mental illness: a guide for mental health professionals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith H (2011) Non-tracing cases of culpable ignorance. Law Philos 5:115–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz T (2011) Suicide prohibition: the shame of medicine. Syracuse University Press, Syracuse

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor JS (2009) Practical autonomy and bioethics. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas AG (2012) Continuing the definition of death debate: the report of the President’s Council on bioethics on controversies in the determination of death. Bioethics 26:101–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torisky EV (2015) Minimally intentional suicide and “the falling man”. J Value Inq 49:69–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Washington State Legislature (2015) Directive to Withhold or Withdraw Life-Sustaining Treatment. http://apps.leg.wa.gov/rcw/default.aspx?cite=70.122.030. Accessed 25 February 2015

  • Zeiler K (2009) Deadly pluralism? why death-concept, death-definition, death-criterion and death-test pluralism should be allowed, even though it creates some problems. Bioethics 23:450–459

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank an anonymous reviewer of this journal for comments and the Kone Foundation for generous financial support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jukka Varelius.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Varelius, J. Mental Illness, Natural Death, and Non-Voluntary Passive Euthanasia. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 19, 635–648 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9664-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9664-7

Keywords

Navigation