Advertisement

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice

, Volume 19, Issue 3, pp 635–648 | Cite as

Mental Illness, Natural Death, and Non-Voluntary Passive Euthanasia

  • Jukka VareliusEmail author
Article

Abstract

When it is considered to be in their best interests, withholding and withdrawing life-supporting treatment from non-competent physically ill or injured patients – non-voluntary passive euthanasia, as it has been called – is generally accepted. A central reason in support of the procedures relates to the perceived manner of death they involve: in non-voluntary passive euthanasia death is seen to come about naturally. When a non-competent psychiatric patient attempts to kill herself, the mental health care providers treating her are obligated to try to stop her. Yet it has been suggested that death by suicide can be a part of the natural course of a severe mental illness. Accordingly, if the perceived naturalness of the deaths occurring in connection with non-voluntary passive euthanasia speaks for their moral permissibility, it could be taken that a similar reason can support the moral acceptability of the suicidal deaths of non-competent psychiatric patients. In this article, I consider whether the suicidal death of a non-competent psychiatric patient would necessarily be less natural than those of physically ill or injured patients who die as a result of non-voluntary passive euthanasia. I argue that it would not.

Keywords

Death Mental illness Passive euthanasia Physician-assisted suicide Psychiatry 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I thank an anonymous reviewer of this journal for comments and the Kone Foundation for generous financial support.

References

  1. American Medical Association Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs (2014-2015) Opinion 2.20 – Withholding or Withdrawing Life-Sustaining Medical Treatment. Code of Medical Ethics, 2014–2015. American Medical Association, Chicago IL http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-ethics/code-medical-ethics/opinion220.page? Accessed 29 Jan 2015
  2. Appel JM (2007) A Suicide right for the mentally ill: a Swiss case opens new debate. Hast Cent Rep 3:21–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Battin MP (2005) Ending life: ethics and the way we die. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF (2008) The principles of biomedical ethics, 6th edn. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  5. Beauchamp TL, Wobber V (2014) Autonomy in chimpanzees. Theor Med Bioeth 35:117–132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bortolotti L, Broome MR, Mameli M (2014) Delusions and responsibility for action: insights from the Breivik case. Neuroethics 7:377–382CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Buchanan AE, Brock DW (1989) Deciding for others: the ethics of surrogate decision making. Cambridge University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  8. Burgess S, Hawton K (1998) Suicide, euthanasia, and the psychiatrist. Philos Psychiatr Psychol 5:113–126Google Scholar
  9. Callaghan R, Ryan C, Kerridge I (2013) Risk of suicide is insufficient warrant for coercive treatment for mental illness. Int J Law Psychiat 36:374–385CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cholbi M (2013) The terminal, the futile, and the psychiatrically disordered. Int J Law Psychiat 36:498–505CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Clemmensen L, Vernal DL, Steinhausen H-C (2012) A systematic review of the long-term outcome of early onset schizophrenia. BMC Psychiatry 12:150–165CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cunningham C, Peters K (2014) Aetiology of schizophrenia and implications for nursing practice: a literature review. Issues Ment Health Nurs 35:732–738CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dickens BM, Boyle JM, Ganzini L (2008) Euthanasia and assisted suicide. In: Singer PA, Viens AM (eds) The Cambridge textbook of bioethics. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 72–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Douglas C (2009) End-of-life decisions and moral psychology: killing, letting die, intention and foresight. J Bioeth Inq 6:337–347CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Dworkin G (1988) The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Fairbairn GJ (1995) Contemplating suicide: the language and ethics of self-harm. Routledge, Florence, KYCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Fine RL (2005) From Quinlan to Schiavo: medical, ethical, and legal issues in severe brain injury. Proc (Bayl Univ Med Cent) 18:303–310Google Scholar
  18. Flanigan J (2014) Non-culpable ignorance and HIV criminalization. J Med Ethics 40:798–801CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Garnett M (2014) The autonomous life: a pure social view. Australas J Philos 92:143–158CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gillett G (1994) Killing, letting die, and moral perception. Bioethics 8:312–328CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Giordano S (2010) Anorexia and refusal of life-saving treatment: the moral place of competence, suffering, and the family. Philos Psychiatr Psychol 17:143–154CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Glock H-J (2009) Can animals act for reasons? Inquiry 52:232–255CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Gonzalez-Liencres C et al. (2014) Oxidative stress in schizophrenia: a case-control study on the effects on social cognition and neurocognition. BMC Psychiatry 14:268–277CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS (1998) Assessing competence to consent to treatment: a guide for physicians and other health professionals. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  25. Hardcastle VG, Stewart RW (2002) Supporting irrational suicide. Bioethics 16:425–438Google Scholar
  26. Hewitt J (2010) Rational suicide: philosophical perspectives on schizophrenia. Med Health Care Philos 13:25–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hewitt J (2013) Why are people with mental illness excluded from the rational suicide debate? Int J Law Psychiat 36:358–365CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Hill DJ (2011) What is it to commit suicide? Ratio 24:192–205CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Jobe TH, Harrow M (2010) Schizophrenia course, long-term outcome, recovery, and prognosis. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 19:220–225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Kekes J (2011) Doubts about autonomy. Philosophy 86:333–351CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Kendell RE (2001) The distinction between mental and physical illness. Brit J Psychiat 178:490–493CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Laureys S et al. (2010) Unresponsive wakefulness syndrome: a new name for the vegetative state or apallic syndrome. BMC Med 8:68–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. McGee A (2011) Me and my body: the relevance of the difference for the distinction between withdrawing life support and euthanasia. J Law Med Ethics 39:671–677CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. McGee A (2015) Acting to let someone die. Bioethics 29:74–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. McLachlan HV (2008) The ethics of killing and letting die: active and passive euthanasia. J Med Ethics 34:636–638CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Miller FG, Truog RD, Brock DW (2010) Moral fictions and medical ethics. Bioethics 11:453–460Google Scholar
  37. Naudts K et al. (2006) Euthanasia: the role of the psychiatrist. Br J Psychiat 188:405–409CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Panksepp J et al. (2007) Does any aspect of mind survive brain damage that typically leads to a persistent vegetative state? ethical considerations. Philos Ethics Humanit Med 2:1–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Parker M (2013) Defending the indefensible? psychiatry, assisted suicide and human freedom. Int J Law Psychiat 36:485–497CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Quill TE, Greenlaw J (2008) Physician assisted death. In: Crowley M (ed) From birth to death and bench to clinic: the Hastings Center bioethics briefing book for journalists, policymakers, and campaigns. The Hastings Center, Garrison, NY, pp. 137–142Google Scholar
  41. Rachels J (1986) The end of life: euthanasia and morality. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  42. Radden J (2004) Identity: personal identity, characterization identity, and mental disorder. In: Radden J (ed) The philosophy of psychiatry: a companion. Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 133–146CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Raus K, Sterckx S, Mortier F (2012) Continuous deep sedation at the end of life and the ‘natural death’ hypothesis. Bioethics 6:329–336CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Royal Dutch Association of Medicine (2011) The role of the physician in the voluntary termination of life. http://knmg.artsennet.nl/Publicaties/KNMGpublicatie-levenseinde/100696/Position-paper-The- role-of-the-physician-in-the-voluntary-termination-of-life-2011.htm. Accessed 13 Jan 2015
  45. Sandman L (2005) Should people die a natural death? Health Care Anal 13:275–287CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Siipi H (2008) Dimensions of naturalness. Ethics Environ 13:71–103CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Slade M (2009) Personal recovery and mental illness: a guide for mental health professionals. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Smith H (2011) Non-tracing cases of culpable ignorance. Law Philos 5:115–146Google Scholar
  49. Szasz T (2011) Suicide prohibition: the shame of medicine. Syracuse University Press, SyracuseGoogle Scholar
  50. Taylor JS (2009) Practical autonomy and bioethics. Routledge, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  51. Thomas AG (2012) Continuing the definition of death debate: the report of the President’s Council on bioethics on controversies in the determination of death. Bioethics 26:101–107CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Torisky EV (2015) Minimally intentional suicide and “the falling man”. J Value Inq 49:69–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Washington State Legislature (2015) Directive to Withhold or Withdraw Life-Sustaining Treatment. http://apps.leg.wa.gov/rcw/default.aspx?cite=70.122.030. Accessed 25 February 2015
  54. Zeiler K (2009) Deadly pluralism? why death-concept, death-definition, death-criterion and death-test pluralism should be allowed, even though it creates some problems. Bioethics 23:450–459CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Behavioural Sciences and PhilosophyFIN-20014 University of TurkuTurkuFinland

Personalised recommendations