Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

On Altruistic War and National Responsibility: Justifying Humanitarian Intervention to Soldiers and Taxpayers

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The principle of absolute sovereignty may have been consigned to history, but a strong presumption against foreign intervention seems to have been left in its stead. On the dominant view, only massacre and ethnic cleansing justify armed intervention, these harms must be already occurring or imminent, and the prudential constraints on war must be satisfied. Each of these conditions has recently come under pressure. Those looking to defend the dominant view have typically done so by invoking international peace and stability, or the value of communal self-determination. But the internal aspect of legitimacy has been overlooked in all of this. If a government insists on defending the human rights of foreigners, it must also be sure not to violate the rights of its own citizens in the process. I argue that the current presumption against humanitarian intervention cannot be substantially relaxed for internal reasons, or given the obligations that states owe to their own constituents.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The humanitarian justification for the 2003 invasion of Iraq was rejected by Human Rights Watch on the grounds that it failed to live up to this criterion (Roth 2004). Saddam Hussein’s most heinous crimes—those which coalition leaders invoked to justify their actions, such as the gassing of the Kurds—occurred in the 1980’s. The purpose of humanitarian intervention, however, must be to rescue the victims of massacre, not to avenge them.

  2. These are referred to in the ICISS report as “precautionary principles”, but I will use the term “prudential conditions” in keeping with the terminology that I have used elsewhere.

  3. For more on the consensus around this threshold, see Dobos (2007).

  4. The fact that a state has signed an international agreement committing itself to engage in humanitarian intervention under certain circumstances has no bearing on this. If it is morally impermissible for a state to engage in humanitarian intervention, it cannot validly commit itself to doing so. As Spinoza says “… no sovereign can keep promises to the detriment of his state without committing a sin; for if he sees any promise he has made to be turning out to the disadvantage of his state, he can only keep it by breaking his pledge to his subjects, although the latter is a pledge which binds him most strictly…” (Spinoza 1958: 141).

  5. Miller does seem to want to allow for some exceptions: “[patriotic] priority does not totally exclude support for foreign aid in the presence of relevant domestic burdens”. But he fails to elaborate. (1998: 210).

  6. As Mickey Kaus puts it, “is it fair to ask someone who volunteered to die for America to die for Father Aristide?” (Kaus 1994: 61). Kaus does not endorse this view of the soldier-state contract. Here he is simply describing the position taken by fellow columnist Michael Kinsley.

  7. The term “riskless war” is taken from Kahn 2002. “Post-heroic” war is taken from Luttwak 1995.

  8. Jovana Davidovic (2008) introduces the concept of minimal decency to the humanitarian intervention debate.

  9. To be sure, “riskless” methods of warfare can sometimes be prohibited on independent grounds. Many have argued that the NATO bombing of Yugoslavia fell short of the principles of jus in bello, which require that civilian casualties be minimised even if this means endangering the lives of troops. But it is important to note that this is a contingent rather than an essential feature of riskless war; one which is slowly but surely being addressed by advances in military technology.

  10. So far, more than 2000 active-duty U.S. soldiers, sailors, Marines and airmen have signed an online Appeal for Redress calling for the withdrawal of troops from Iraq (http://www.appealforredress.org/). Interviews with several of the signatories suggest that Cook’s account of the soldier-state contract resonates with at least some members of the armed forces. “Lisa” of the U.S Air Force, having “joined up two weeks after [turning] 17 because [she] wanted to save American lives”, now feels that “our troops have no reason for being there”. “Sergent Gary” signed up while still in junior high school on the pretence that Saddam “was a threat to America”. The evidence to the contrary led Gary to sign the Appeal. See Cooper 2006.

  11. To be sure, some of these do not technically count as humanitarian interventions on the prevailing definition, according to which an intervention necessarily takes place without the consent of the target state. (Australian forces have been invited by the governments of Timor-Leste and the Solomons).

  12. I would like to thank Igor Primoratz and Andrew Alexandra for their helpful comments and suggestions on an earlier version of this paper.

References

  • Beitz C (2001) Human rights as a common concern. Am Polit Sci Rev 95(2):269–283. doi:10.1017/S0003055401002015

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan A (1999) The internal legitimacy of humanitarian intervention. J Polit Philos 7(1):71–87. doi:10.1111/1467-9760.00066

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke E (1774) Speech to the Electors of Bristol, at http://www.ourcivilisation.com/smartboard/shop/burkee/extracts/chap4.htm

  • Coady CAJ (2008) Morality and political violence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York.

  • Cook ML (2000) Immaculate war: constraints on humanitarian intervention. Ethics Int Aff 14:55–65. doi:10.1111/j.1747-7093.2000.tb00053.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook ML (2004) The moral warrior: ethics and service in the U.S. Military. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper M (2006) About face: soldiers call for Iraq Withdrawal, The Nation, December 16, at: http://www.thenation.com/doc/20070101/cooperweb

  • Davidovic J (2008) Are humanitarian military interventions obligatory? J Appl Philos 25(2):134–144. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5930.2008.00393.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Spinoza B (1958) The political works. Wernham A.G. (ed. and trans.), Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Dobos N (2007) The re-emerging medieval interventionism. Antithesis 17:51–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunne T, Schmidt BT (2001) Realism. In: John Baylis, Steve Smith (eds) The Globalization of World Politics, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans M (2002) Selectivity, Imperfect Obligations, and the Charter of Humanitarian Morality. In: Moseley A, Norman R (eds) Human Rights and Military Intervention. Ashgate, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg J (1968) Collective responsibility. J Philos 65:674–688. doi:10.2307/2024543

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes T (1985) Leviathan, Macpherson CB (ed) Harmondsworth, Penguin

  • International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (2001) The responsibility to protect: the report of the International commission on intervention and state sovereignty, at http://www.iciss.ca/report2-en.asp

  • Jackson R (1994) The political theory of International society. In: Booth K, Smith S (eds) International Relations Theory Today. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn PW (2002) The paradox of riskless warfare. Philos Public Policy Q 22(3):2–8

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaus M (1994) TRB from Washington: Somalia Syndrome, The New Republic

  • Kennan GF (1985) Morality and Foreign Policy. Foreign Aff 64:205–218 1986

    Google Scholar 

  • Krauthammer C (1985) When to intervene: what’s worth fighting for? The New Republic 192:10–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Luban D (2002) Intervention and civilization: some unhappy lessons of the Kosovo War. In: de Greiff P, Cronin C (eds) Global Justice and Transnational Politics: Essays on the Moral and Political Challenges of Globalization. MIT, Cambridge Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Luttwak E (1995) Towards post-heroic warfare. Foreign Aff 74:109–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellema G (1997) Collective responsibility. Amsterdam; Atlanta, Rodopi

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller RW (1998) Cosmopolitan respect and patriotic concern. Philos Public Aff 27(3):202–224. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.1998.tb00068.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy SD (1996) Humanitarian intervention: the United Nations in an evolving world order. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Nye JS (1990) The changing nature of world power. Polit Sci Q 105:177–192. doi:10.2307/2151022

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orend B (2000) War, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/war/

  • Orend B (2006) The morality of war. Broadview, Peterborough

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennock JR (1979) Democratic political theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Pevnick R (2008) Political coercion and the scope of distributive justice. Polit Stud 56:399–413. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2007.00694.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge TW (2001) The influence of the global order on the prospects for genuine democracy in the developing countries. Ratio Juris 14(3):326–343. doi:10.1111/1467-9337.00185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge TW (2002) World poverty and human rights: cosmopolitan responsibility and reforms. Polity, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) The law of peoples; with the idea of public reason revisited. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth K (2004) War in Iraq: not a humanitarian intervention, Human Rights Watch World Report, 2004, at www.hrw.org/wr2k4/3.htm

  • Shue H (1996) Basic rights: subsistence, affluence, and US foreign policy, Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Shue H (1999) Conditional sovereignty. Res Publica 8(1):1–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Teson F (1995) The Rawlsian theory of International law. Ethics Int Aff 9:79–99. doi:10.1111/j.1747-7093.1995.tb00172.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teson F (2005) Ending tyranny in Iraq. Ethics Int Aff 19(2):1–20. doi:10.1111/j.1747-7093.2005.tb00496.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M (2007) Beyond humanitarian intervention: human rights in global society. In: David Miller (ed) Thinking politically: essays in political theory. Yale University Press, New Haven and London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ned Dobos.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dobos, N. On Altruistic War and National Responsibility: Justifying Humanitarian Intervention to Soldiers and Taxpayers. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 13, 19–31 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-009-9167-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-009-9167-5

Keywords

Navigation