In the previous section I argued that Gettier cases involve veritic luck. In this section and the next, I will defend the following claim:
JUSTIFICATION A belief is justified only if it is not veritically lucky.
The account is original in that anti-luck conditions are usually formulated as conditions on knowledge, rather than on justification (Littlejohn 2014; Pritchard 2005; Williamson 2009). Under the assumption that knowledge requires justification, our account will explain why there is such an anti-luck condition on knowledge. But depending on how these authors flesh out their notion of justification, our account may or may not be compatible with theirs. In any case, in this section I will argue specifically for an anti-luck condition on justification.
I will do so by first presenting a modal interpretation of Goldman’s famous reliabilist theory of justification, an interpretation on which no justified belief is veritically lucky. While I believe many of Goldman’s writings are compatible with such a reading of reliabilism, this is rarely noted, and the modal interpretation of reliabilism is not widely endorsed in the literature. I will therefore provide further support for this interpretation in the next section, by considering and diffusing main objections to it.
First, some preliminaries. The relevant kind of justification at issue in JUSTIFICATION is doxastic justification, a property of beliefs, rather than propositional justification, which is a property of propositions.Footnote 10 Further, the claim specifies a necessary condition for doxastic justification, not a sufficient one. It may very well be that there are other necessary conditions on doxastic justification, besides the one proposed in this paper. It should finally be noted that whether a belief is veritically lucky depends on factors other than the believing agent’s mental states or reflectively accessible information, so that the concept of justification we are working with here in this paper is externalist.Footnote 11
JUSTIFICATION is supported by one of the most prominent accounts of doxastic justification in the literature: Goldman’s process reliabilism (1979, 1994).Footnote 12 While Goldman does not explicitly endorse the claim that justification excludes veritic luck in his writings, in this section I will argue that there is a plausible interpretation of his account that does.
Consider first Goldman’s reliabilist account of justification:
RELIABILISM S’s belief in p is justified IFF it is caused (or causally sustained) by a reliable cognitive process, or a history of reliable processes. (Goldman 1994)
The general idea behind reliabilism is that a belief is justified if and only if it is caused by a process that reliably produces true beliefs. Thus, beliefs formed on the basis of perception under normal circumstances will come out as justified (as they should) because under normal circumstances perception reliably causes true beliefs. Conversely, beliefs formed on the basis of tea-leaf reading will not come out as justified (as they should), because this process will not produce a high ratio of true over false belief.
There are different ways to understand the relevant truth/falsity ratio. First, we can understand it to concern actual operations of the process, or also counterfactual ones. This gives us the difference between frequency and modal interpretations of reliabilism. On a frequency account, what matters is whether the process in actual operation produces enough truth over falsity, whereas on the modal interpretation, what matters is whether the process would produce truth over falsity, even if it actually does not operate at all, or actually fails to produce enough truth over falsity.
We may further distinguish global from local reliability. A process is globally reliable if and only if it produces enough truth over falsity in all its possible or actual applications, whereas it is locally reliable if and only if it produces (or would produce) enough truth over falsity in situations similar enough to the actual case. Thus, ‘going by eyesight’ may be a globally reliable process or method, but it will not be a locally reliable method if one is currently in barn-façade county and forming beliefs about the presence of barns. Generally, (we presume,) trusting one’s eyes will produce a high ratio of true beliefs over false ones, but in the context of barn-façade county, looks are deceiving, and so in similar circumstances one would form many false beliefs in the same way.
Which of these notions is relevant for justification? According to Timothy Williamson, reliability should be understood in modal rather than frequency terms:
Reliability and unreliability, stability and instability, safety and danger, robustness and fragility are modal states. They concern what could easily have happened. They depend on what happens under small variations in the initial conditions. (Williamson 2000)
In the epistemic context, there are good reasons for doing so, in particular that we would not want to say that belief-forming methods that are only used once are either completely reliable or completely unreliable. Relatedly, if I follow a version of the gambler’s fallacy consistently, and believe that the next number of a roulette wheel will be the number that has not come up for the longest amount of runs, this method will not produce justified beliefs, even if in the actual circumstances in which I apply it, it actually does produce mostly true beliefs, What matters for justification seems to be whether the method could have easily produced false belief, not whether it has actually done so.
We can find a similar modal interpretation of reliability in the work of Goldman, specifically a local modal account, when he speaks about the reliability required for knowledge:
… a cognitive mechanism or process is reliable if it not only produces true beliefs in actual situations, but would produce true beliefs, or at least inhibit false beliefs, in relevant counterfactual situations. (Goldman 1976)
The reliability theories [of knowledge] presented above focus on modal reliability, on getting truth and avoiding error in possible worlds with specified relations to the actual one. They also focus on local reliability, that is, truth-acquisition in scenarios linked to the specific scenario in question as opposed to truth-getting by a process or method over a wide range of cases. (Goldman and Beddor 2016)
At first sight, it is not clear whether the kind of reliability required for knowledge is the same as that required for justification according to Goldman. For example, in Epistemology and cognition, when he speaks explicitly about the reliability required for justification, Goldman again opts for modal condition, but one that is slightly more difficult to place on the global–local axis, since it makes the required reliability dependent on what happens in so-called ‘normal’ worlds—worlds that conform to our current beliefs about the world (1986, p. 107). Such ‘normic’ reliability conditions on justification receive support from recent defenses by Jarett Leplin and Martin Smith (Leplin 2009; Smith 2016).
Normic reliability resembles local reliability since both depend on what happens in a restricted class of worlds rather than all possible worlds. But it differs from local accounts of reliability in that it anchors the relevant set of worlds not to the actual world but to a class of ‘normal worlds’, where normal worlds are worlds compatible with our current beliefs about the world. Thus, if we are envatted brains, we may continue to believe as we do, and our methods would still be justified according to the normic reliability criterion (for these methods are reliable in worlds compatible with our current beliefs about the world). This is how normic reliabilists accommodate the intuition that the beliefs of BIV’s are justified.
In this paper, I opt for a local conception of the kind of reliability required for justification rather than a normic conception. Normic accounts unduly prioritize the epistemic relevance of (our beliefs about) our current world. It is a guiding thought behind the present paper that methods that produce justified beliefs do so because they ensure a proper fit between our beliefs and the world. If the notion of reliability has any relevance in epistemology it is to designate that our methods are guides to truth. That some method is reliable in contexts in which it will never be used seems of little epistemic relevance. Normic reliability accounts predict that BIV’s are justified in using our empirical belief-forming methods even if the relevant subject is envatted from the moment they are born to the moment they die, and these empirical methods never produce a single true belief. Ideally, we want a general analysis that has sensible conditions on knowledge and justification not just for us, but for creatures cognizing in vastly different epistemic contexts as well. It is hard to imagine why such creatures would accord any epistemic relevance to methods that are reliable at our world only. What their epistemologists would care about is reliability in their context, and so I think it is local reliability that ultimately matters for a general theory of justification.
In any case, Goldman abandoned his normic account in favor of a distinction between strong and weak justification (Goldman 1988). A belief is said to be strongly justified just in case it is produced by an (epistemically) adequate method, whereas it is said to be weakly justified just in case the believer is (epistemically) blameless in so believing. Since no method for which one is epistemically to blame is epistemically adequate, strong justification implies weak justification, but not the other way around, for adequate methods may require more than just blameless believing.
What more is required? Here Goldman is very explicit. For any belief-forming process, we should assess its “rightness [strong justification] in [world] W not simply by its performance in W, but by its performance in a set of worlds very close to W” (Goldman 1988, p. 63). This clearly indicates that the reliability that Goldman thinks is required for strong justification is local modal reliability.
The same kind of reliability is not required for weak justification, however, as becomes clear from Goldman’s treatment of the Cartesian demon case (a variant of the envatted brain case discussed above): “The present version of reliabilism accommodates the intuition that demon-world believers have justified beliefs by granting that they have weakly justified beliefs” (Goldman 1988, pp. 62, 63). Obviously, demon-world victims do not have beliefs that are produced by processes that perform well in their actual world as well as in a set of worlds close to the demon-world. This does not stop their beliefs from being weakly justified according to Goldman, so weak justification does not require local modal reliability.
Weak justification thus does not eliminate veritic luck. But with our definitions of veritic luck and local modal reliability in hand, it is easy to see that strong justification, as well as any account that requires local modal reliability, does entail the absence of veritic luck.
First, a method that is locally modally reliable is a process or method that produces a high ratio of truth over falsity situations similar to the actual case. Second, a belief is veritically lucky if and only if the method or process that produced it produced a true belief but produces false belief in close possible worlds.
Now, it is natural to interpret the notion of ‘similar circumstances’ occurring in our definition of local modal reliability in terms of close possible worlds. After all, close possible worlds are defined as worlds that differ little from the actual world. Such an interpretation of reliabilist justification fits well with Goldman’s claims regarding the modal profile of strong justification provided above, as well as with his treatment of BIV’s. Envatted subjects lack reliably formed beliefs because in worlds close to their actual world, their methods produce false beliefs too often. We will thus continue under the assumption that the notions of ‘close possible worlds’ and ‘similar situations’, as they occur in the definitions of veritic luck and local modal reliability, share their extension.
Admittedly, it is unclear how ‘wide’ the class of worlds where the agent forms a false belief in the same way as she formed her true belief in the actual world must be for a belief to count as veritically lucky.Footnote 13 But similarly, it is unclear what counts as a similar situation, on a local modal reliabilist conception of justification.
To circumvent this worry, I will assume that reliability and veritic luck are both graded notions. By this I mean that our beliefs can be more or less reliable than other beliefs, without it being clear that there is a sharp cut-off point between reliable and unreliable beliefs. The same holds for veritic luck: it is intuitively plausible that there is a continuum of veritic luck, where beliefs can be more, or less veritically lucky without there being a precise cut-off point where a veritically lucky belief becomes a non-veritically lucky one.
If this is true, then it follows that the higher the local modal reliability of a method is, the lower the degree of veritic luck will be that attaches to the beliefs produced by this method. In this sense, a local modal reliability condition behaves as an anti-veritic luck condition on justification. The more (locally modally) reliable your method, the less subject your beliefs are to veritic luck. In the extreme case, complete local modal reliability entails complete absence of veritic luck (in this case, there are no nearby possible worlds where one’s method produces a false belief).
A final point worth emphasizing in this section is that while RELIABILISM takes reliability to be both necessary and sufficient for justification, I will commit myself only to its necessity (that is why JUSTIFICATION does not feature a biconditional). There are several reasons for this, some will be outlined in the next section, and some in Sect. 6. But perhaps the most important point presently is that I want to show as clearly as possible what is required to evade Gettier cases, and an anti-veritic luck condition on justification suffices for this purpose. Perhaps other conditions on justification are necessary, perhaps not. We will leave this question for another time.
Let us briefly recap. I have presented in this section a local modal interpretation of RELIABILISM supported by the writings of Alvin Goldman, and argues that it excludes veritic luck. This means that there is at least one prominent and plausible account of justification in the literature that satisfies JUSTIFICATION. I do not claim the interpretation presented in this section is the only possible interpretation of RELIABILISM, nor that it is Goldman’s own interpretation, nor that RELIABILISM is the only plausible account that satisfies JUSITIFICATION. My aim in this paper is only to establish that there is a plausible interpretation of justification that allows for an anti-luck defense of the tripartite analysis of knowledge, not that this defense is possible for all accounts of justification. In the next section I will provide further support for JUSTIFICATION by defending it against objections.