1 Introduction

Connexive logic, as a research programme in philosophical logic, is motivated by powerful intuitions about the clear defectiveness of statements like

If A is the case, then not-A is the case.

I strongly believe that these intuitions must be accounted for in some way or other, even though they have been largely ignored, at least until recently. Those who have not ignored them have usually been trying to develop a semantic account of conditionals and negations that leads to a connexive logic, a move that requires considerable logical revision. In this paper, I will investigate whether this could maybe not be necessary, because the intuitions might be explained by pragmatic phenomena instead; in particular, I will be looking at the pragmatics of conditionals to answer this question.

The question breaks up into two more specific ones that will lead us through the essay:

figure a

The outline of the paper is as follows: In a first part, I will introduce the principles of connexive logic and supply a first analysis of the intuitions that lie behind their plausibility. I will show that the intuitions are equally strong for indicative and counterfactual conditionals. The second part will discuss the pragmatic features of conditionals that might help explain those intuitions and present my answer to Q-Pragmatic: I will argue that such an explanation works for indicative conditionals, but not for counterfactuals. Lastly, a third part surveys the upshots for logic choice of such an explanation and thus supplies my answer to Q-Revision, this time a resounding “It depends”.

Two remarks about what to expect: First, from a logical point of view the paper is quite programmatic in nature, in that it discusses rather general features of semantic and logical theories rather than particular systems. My aim is to get the goal into clearer focus, how to get there is beyond the scope of this piece. As a result, the material is not heavy on formal technicalities; in fact, I hope that even philosophers of language and linguists who are not particularly interested in logic at all might be able to get something of value, especially out of the part on pragmatics.

Second, although I am sympathetic to the aims of the lately invigorated and growing connexive community, I try to conduct this investigation without any foregone conclusions in mind (however, I will allow myself some opinionated comments at the very end of the essay). I will present a range of options, and though I find some of these more plausible than others, I believe they can all be incorporated into a generally feasible theory of conditionals which will, in particular, all have some success in accommodating the connexive intuitions. Some of them will require adopting a connexive logic, others will not. What is common to all of them is that they can make a claim to do justice to the intuitions motivating connexivity, and that they entail changes to commonly held assumptions about logic, semantics and/or pragmatics.

Part I: Connexive Logic and Connexive Intuitions

2 Connexive Logic: Principles and Variations

Connexive logicsFootnote 1 are non-classical logics that are characterized by the following principles:

  • Aristotle: \({{\lnot }}(A\rightarrow \lnot A)\) and \({{\lnot }}(\lnot A\rightarrow A)\) are valid.

  • Boethius: \((A\rightarrow B)\rightarrow \lnot (A\rightarrow \lnot B)\) and \((A\rightarrow \lnot B)\rightarrow \lnot (A\rightarrow B)\) are valid.Footnote 2

These principles surely seem plausible when the connectives are read with their usual meaning, and it is the aim of this paper to get clear about where that feeling of plausibility comes from. Before we get there, though, let me say a little bit more about the peculiar status of connexive logics in the landscape of present day philosophical logic. Let me also take the opportunity to sketch my personal view on how to think about connexivity, as it will be helpful to know the perspective from which this paper is written.

The connexive principles,Footnote 3 although that surprises many students even after a thorough introductory course in logic, are not valid in classical logic. That is what makes connexive logic a topic in non-classical logic, but the pattern is interestingly different from that of other non-classical logics. In all other well-known cases, the non-classical logic rejects something that is valid in classical logic, such as the Law of Excluded Middle, Explosion or some other classical principle.Footnote 4

Connexive logics, in contrast, ask for more validities than classical logic gives us. It so happens that this is impossible without giving up other things in turn: Classical logic is Post-complete, which means that adding new axioms without removing others will trivialize the resulting logical system. Accordingly, much of the philosophical work in the field of connexive logics takes the form of a cost-benefit analysis, weighing the attractiveness of Aristotle and Boethius against the undeniable discomfort of giving up other principles one might like to keep. I will not go into the specifics of this balancing act here; instead, my aim in this part is to describe and assess the weight and the nature of what is on one of the sides of the scale: the intuitive attractiveness of the connexive principles.

As I have noted, the principles strike most people as common-sensical when they look at them and translate them into natural language statements.Footnote 5 Now, it is important to note that this is true whether we read the arrow as an indicative conditional or whether we read it as a subjunctive or counterfactualFootnote 6 one:

It is not the case that if I go to France next year I do not go to France next year.

It is not the case that if I were to go to France next year, I would not go to France next year.

Also, changing tense is not making much of a difference:

It is not the case that if I went to France last year I did not go to France last year.

It is not the case that if I had gone to France last year, I would not have gone to France last year.

All of these, I would suggest, seem equally true. Indeed, they seem trivially true. Instances of Boethius, though still more unwieldy and unlikely to come up in conversation, seem upon reflection equally true. I will only give one example explicitly, the adjustment to achieve the three variations that are analogous to the examples above are obvious:

If it is the case that I will have a good time if I go to France next year, then it is not the case that I will not have a good time if I go to France next year.

Strong as they might be, I think that the intuitions about such statements are derivative in their nature, that is, that they are based on more fundamental ones. I take it that the intuition that leads to thinking that \(\lnot (A\rightarrow \lnot A)\) is valid is actually grounded in an intuition about \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\). Here is a first rough suggestion as to what that intuition might be (it will get more precise in the next section): There is something seriously wrong with asserting natural language instances of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\). For Boethius, I believe that the intuitive core of finding \((A\rightarrow B)\rightarrow \lnot (A\rightarrow \lnot B)\) and its twin \((A\rightarrow \lnot B)\rightarrow \lnot (A\rightarrow B)\) plausible is the following intuition: There is something seriously wrong with someone’s saying both \(A\rightarrow B\) and \(A\rightarrow \lnot B\). If you say one, you should not say the other.Footnote 7

This line of thought has led me to point out (Kapsner 2012) that connexivists should ask, in addition to Aristotle and Boethius, for the following unsatisfiability-conditions:

  • UnSat1: In no model, \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) is satisfiable.Footnote 8

  • UnSat2: In no model \(A\rightarrow B\) and \(A\rightarrow \lnot B\) are satisfiable simultaneously (for any A and B).

Logics that satisfy these two clauses in addition to Aristotle and Boethius are called strongly connexive logics, while those that only satisfy Aristotle and Boethius are called weakly connexive logics.

It may be surprising to learn that logics that are only weakly connexive even exist, but they do: Many attractive connexive logics are ruled out if one insists on UnSat1 and UnSat2. In fact, at least in view of the current theoretical landscape, it might even appear that strong connexivity will turn out to be too high a bar to clear, at least for any logic that is suitable for natural language analysis.

In view of this difficulty, I have more recently made a suggestion how we might lower the bar slightly without giving up my demand for the unsatisfiability-conditions. This suggestion is based on the observation that there is one area in which the compelling nature of our intuitions might start to fade. This concerns impossible or contradictory antecedents:

It is not the case that if A and not-A are both the case, then it is not the case that A and not-A are the case.

Assuming someone is able to parse things like that correctly, maybe they won’t feel as strongly pushed towards accepting this as true as in the other cases discussed above. This puts in doubt whether the formalized version of the above, \(\lnot ((A\wedge \lnot A) \rightarrow \lnot (A\wedge \lnot A))\), should come out logically valid.

In my paper Humble Connexivity,Footnote 9 I have argued that the connexive principles should be restricted so as not to apply to such cases. A logic achieves humble connexivity if Aristotle, Boethius, UnSat1 and UnSat2 hold in all cases that do not involve impossible antecedents. The details are somewhat more intricate than one might expect. Instead of going into this much further here, let us agree to simply disregard such statements for the purposes of this paper.Footnote 10

I will only note the following: In proposing the humble restrictions, my intention was not to say that achieving a more ambitious form of connexivity that does not make such restrictions would be philosophically bad per se. It’s just that we know that a logic will explode if we push it to do too much work; the impossible antecedents are, in my view, a valve that we can easily open up to let off some steam. But the pressure is still considerable. Even if we don’t ask for Aristotle, Boethius and the UnSat-clauses to hold in cases involving contradictions, but only when the constituent statements are garden variety contingent statements, we are still asking for a considerable revision of classical logic. In classical logic, Aristotle will fail in each case in which A is simply false, no matter whether A is contradictory or consistent. Indeed, most other non-classical logics are in a similar situation.Footnote 11 Even though humble connexivity has lowered the bar, it is still quite high.

Pondering this problem has led me to the questions I investigate in this paper, in particular the ones I have called Q-Pragmatic and Q-Revision above. My aim in this piece is to uncover the ultimate source of the connexive intuitions: I am interested in whether they stem from the semantics of conditionals and negation, or whether they are intuitions about pragmatics (Q-Pragmatic). If the latter is the case, maybe we don’t need to revise logic at all, or only in a less radical way than we thought (Q-Revision). I will unpack these possibilities in the later sections of this piece; for now, we will have to start by getting clearer about what the connexive intuitions are, exactly.Footnote 12

3 Connexive Intuitions, in More Detail

Again, I claim that the core of the connexive intuitions is the thought that there is something very wrong with asserting things like \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc. If we want to make that rather fuzzy characterization more precise, there are several ways to do this. I present three that I take to be promising (leaving out variations in tense, such as “If A was the case, then not-A was the case”). They are increasing in strength, at least under commonly held ideas about assertion conditions, truth values and negation.Footnote 13

figure b

Here, all we are taking the intuitions to come down to is that instances of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc. cannot be asserted correctly in any conversational circumstance. The word “together” in the explication of the intuitions behind Boethius is imprecise: It could mean “at the same time in the same conversation” or “at the same time in the same conversation by the same speaker”; I mean the latter, but the former is of course another way to spell out our intuitions that one might want to consider. In any case, whether the unassertability has to do with the semantic value of these statements or not is left open. The next version is more specific on this:

figure c

Here, the unassertability of the statements has to do with semantic values; however, it is still left open by these clauses what exactly it has to do with them: It could be the case that the statements always take a value that is associated with unassertability (i.e. falsity on most accounts, or possibly some other undesignated value in many-valued settings). However, it could also be the case that they simply fail to take a semantic value at all. The last version is explicit on this question:

figure d

In this last version, it is clear that we are dealing with semantic values as the main source of connexive intuitions: \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) and its variations take the truth value “false”, as does at least one of \(A\rightarrow B\) and \(A\rightarrow \lnot B\).

It might be worthwhile to try to find out empirically whether one of these formulations captures people’s intuitions more clearly than the others, but I have some doubts that untrained subjects will be perfectly clear about which of them is the most plausible. I will get back to this point towards the end of the paper, but let me here nonetheless speculate a bit: I believe that most people will agree at least to the plausibility of Unassertability, and that a large majority would go on to Untruth. Whether they would go on to Falsity will depend, I suspect, on the presentation of the options. If only Falsity is on offer to either accept or reject, I suspect they will embrace Falsity, but if they can choose between all three options, they might stop at Untruth. It is between Untruth and Falsity that my own intuitions waver, though one might argue that my intuitions on this question are compromised by now.

In any case, I will keep all three options on the table as I move into the next part of this paper, in which I will launch my investigation into the main questions of this piece: Whether these intuitionsFootnote 14 could be explained by an appeal to pragmatic principles (Q-Pragmatic), and, if so, whether we might not need to ask for logic to validate the connexive principles (Q-Revision). A positive answer to both questions would leave the non-connexive logician in a very comfortable place: She would not have to dispute the connexive intuitions, but the issue could be handed to the linguists and philosophers of language who analyze matters of pragmatics.

To see whether such hopes are well founded or in vain (or if it is something in between, in that the appeal to pragmatics leads to a milder logical revision than expected), let us start to look into which kinds of pragmatic constraints are at play here, and whether any of them explain our connexive intuitions.

Part II: The Pragmatics of Connexivity

4 Saving Logic from Intuitions: Grice

The project of explaining connexive intuitions by appeals to pragmatics takes on a roughly similar form as Gricean explanationsFootnote 15 of seeming counterexamples against the material conditional analysis of indicative conditionals.

Grice held that to say \(A\rightarrow B\) in a situation where one knows of the truth of either \(\lnot A\) or B (or both) will be pragmatically incorrect, even if what one is saying is true. It is incorrect because it violates several conversational maxims.

According to the material analysis Grice defends, what one is saying is equivalent to \(\lnot A \vee B\), and using the disjunction or something that is equivalent to a disjunction implies that the speaker knows nothing more specific than that at least one of the disjuncts is true. It is, thus, misleading to utter the statement instead of simply asserting the disjunct which one knows to be true. The latter would also be more concise and more informative.

Maybe one could try to defend the truth of at least some instances of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) (namely those instances in which A is false), while explaining the connexive intuitions that go against such statements by using these considerations. We would be lead to conclude that the true core of our intuitions is Unassertability, and that Untruth would already be going too far, not to speak of Falsity.

Here is what such a possible line of defense would look like that aims to show why Aristotle seems so compelling and why \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) seems so wrong: \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) just means \(\lnot A \vee \lnot A\), and it would be more concise and more elegant to just say \(\lnot A\).

However, unlike in the more general case, note that it is not really more informative to say \(\lnot A\) instead of \(\lnot A \vee \lnot A\). It is also not really misleading to say the latter. The speaker who says something with this logical form is not pretending to know less than she does; she is only using clumsy language to say what she knows. For a conditional which is asserted on grounds of knowing the precise truth value of the antecedent, the consequent, or indeed both, and which is judged defective on Gricean grounds, this would seem to be one of the least offensive cases possible.Footnote 16

But that diagnosis of inoffensiveness does not ring true to me. Take a case that should feel parallel, but (at least to me), does not: \(A\wedge A\).Footnote 17 That, translated to natural language, is just a very strange and complicated way to say A. The strangeness can be made explicit by appeal to Gricean maxims, and that lets us see why the statement would normally not be correctly assertable. But at no point in thinking about this example would anyone have thought it couldn’t be true. I feel no inclination to respond “Now that can’t be true, can it?” to \(A\wedge A\), while I do in the case of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\). In my terminology above, my intuition is to go further than Unassertability here, but the Gricean strategy cannot take us further along.Footnote 18

Though conversational maxims won’t get us beyond Unassertability, there are pragmatic stories that lead to Untruth, and maybe even to Falsity. However, instead of general conversational maxims, we need to start to look at the specific pragmatic principles that attach to indicative and counterfactual conditionals for that purpose.

5 The Pragmatics of Conditionals

There is no clear consensus on the pragmatics of indicative and subjunctive conditionals. In the upcoming sub-sections, I will go through some important views on this, but here I will immediately start out with what strikes me as the correct account.Footnote 19

I take the central pieces of the pragmatics of conditionals to be two presuppositions, one attaching to indicatives, one to counterfactuals.Footnote 20 Presuppositions of a statement are, roughly, things that need to be true in order for the whole statement to even have a chance of being true.

Here is the form these presuppositions take:

figure e

To see how plausible these principles are, think of someone saying on Monday

If today is Tuesday, then it’s Mary’s birthday.

IP claims that this could be a non-defective assertion only if the speaker actually doesn’t know that today is Monday.Footnote 21 If he signals in some way that he does know, then he has clearly made some mistake or is trying to communicate something vastly non-literal. For example,

If today is Tuesday, then it’s Mary’s birthday. Today is Monday.

just sounds plainly wrong, assuming the speaker utters these sentences without any pause in which she might acquire new information about which day it is. Here, the presupposition IP is not met, and that is the source of the trouble with that statement. The most charitable reading of this might be to suppose that the speaker is not a native speaker of English and meant to use the subjunctive mood to utter a counterfactual, in which case the pair of assertions would be fine:

If today were Tuesday, then it would be Mary’s birthday. Today is Monday.

Not only is there no problem with the speaker knowing the antecedent to be false, this is actually called for by CP, the presupposition I have suggested to hold for counterfactuals. This presupposition does little more than to ask for a counterfactual to be counter to fact, something that sounds close to analytically true. That there is, nonetheless, some contention around this principle will be discussed in the next subsection.

Do these presuppositions help account for the connexive intuitions beyond what we have seen so far? On the face of it, the Gricean strategy laid out above would explain the unassertability of the example sentence in the indicative mood in a way that might not seem too different from IP: According to Grice, what the speaker has said is equivalent to

Either today is not Tuesday, or it’s Mary’s birthday.

Uttered on the grounds that today is Monday, this is needlessly complex and misleading.

IP differs from the Gricean strategy in two important ways: First, it makes no presumption about the correctness of the material conditional analysis of indicative conditionals. Moreover, the Gricean analysis rests on an idea about the assertability of disjunctions that is not needed for the more direct IP. Second, in regarding IP a presuppositon, one is making a committment to honoring intuitions that the first sentence in

If today is Tuesday, then it’s Mary’s birthday. Today is Monday.

is not just saying something misleading, but indeed something that is not true. A presupposition that can not be satisfied, as I said above, precludes the truth of the statement.Footnote 22 Whether that means that the statement is false is a separate question that I will return to below. At this point, just note that the explanation of the connexive intuitions that utilizes IP is more general than the Gricean strategy (in not being committed to the material analysis of conditionals), and that it helps account for the stronger versions of these intuitions, be they Untruth or Falsity.

The two presuppositions I propose are somewhat asymmetric, in that IP makes reference to the epistemic state of the speaker, while CP does not. That is not to say that the epistemic state of the speaker is irrelevant to CP: not only must she use a statement that is false as the antecedent of a counterfactual, she must also believe that the antecedent is false in order to make a correct assertion. But the latter is implied by her realizing that the antecedent needs to be false to justify her use of a counterfactual (realizing that is part of using this device correctly). On the other hand, to use a counterfactual correctly, it is not enough to just believe the antecedent to be false, it must actually be false. To say

If you hadn’t lied to me back then, we would still be friends.

is objectionable if the addressee didn’t lie, even if the speaker believes him to have lied.

I have not seen the above pair of IP and CP proposed together in the literature so far, but I don’t want to claim that they are very original.Footnote 23 The ideas, or slight variations of them, were expressed by others before, just not in this exact combination. The suggestions I found that were closest to mine are by Brian Leahy, by Lauri Karttunen and Stanley Peters, and by Robert Stalnaker. Let me comment on our differences before I explain how an account of the connexive intuitions might (or might not) be able to make use of these presuppositions.

5.1 Leahy

Leahy (Leahy 2011) endorses IP, and thus we are in complete agreement on indicatives. However, he does not endorse CP; rather, he believes that counterfactuals have no presuppositions at all.Footnote 24 I think that most of our difference lies in the oft-lamented terminological situation at this point: As counterfactuals are, at least in English, expressed by switching to the subjunctive mood, “counterfactual conditionals” and “subjunctive conditionals” are often used synonymously. This leads to some subjunctive conditionals that are used as counterexamples to principles such as the presupposition I suggested above. The poster-child that is cited by virtually everyone who claims that counterfactuals might have true antecedents is the following example by Alan Anderson:

If he had taken arsenic, he would have shown exactly the symptoms that he in fact showed. So he likely took arsenic (Anderson 1951).

It is slightly ironic that Anderson himself did not use “counterfactual conditionals” and “subjunctive conditionals” as synonymous. Furthermore, he meant his example to show that not all subjunctive conditionals need to have false antecedents, while he did not dispute that counterfactuals do.

Quite similarly, where researchers like Leahy see counterexamples to the presupposition I suggest, I see conditionals in the subjunctive mood in the English language that happen not to express counterfactuals. I am, again, not claiming originality for this view, as it goes back to at least Anderson. It is also quite in harmony with what Stalnaker says about subjunctives and counterfactuals in Stalnaker (1975a), a paper I will discuss in more detail below. What bearing the difference in opinion between Leahy and me has on the topic of connexivity will be answered in Sect. 6.2.

5.2 Karttunen and Peters

Karttunen and Peters (Karttunen and Peters 1979), on the other hand, come close to agreeing with both IP and CP.

Karttunen and Peters fall into the same camp as Leahy when it gets to identifying subjunctive and counterfactual conditionals and thereby allowing counterfactuals that have true antecedents. This leads them, however, to a weaker version of CP, as opposed to the claim that subjunctives/counterfactuals have no pragmatic restrictions at all on them, as Leahy argues.

They write (Karttunen and Peters 1979, p. 8):

“If A then B” conventionally implicates:

        a. Indicative mood

        “It is epistemically possible that A

        b. Subjunctive mood

        “It is epistemically possible that not-A

Again, I will discuss the import of that difference compared to CP in 6.2. For now, there are two more things to draw your attention to:

First, they don’t make it clear for whom the antecedent’s truth or falsity must be epistemically possible. IP makes it clear that it is the speaker whose epistemic state is at issue, while we will see a different view in the next section. As I don’t know which camp to sort Karttunen and Peters into, I will say nothing more about it in this section.

The second interesting difference between their proposed restrictions and IP and CP is that the latter are framed as presuppositions, while Karttunen and Peters take them to be conventional implicatures.

Now, the line between presuppositions and conventional implicatures is hardly a clear one. Precise usage varies among authors, who often don’t give a direct comparison between their reading of the two notions. Where the distinction is drawn explicitly, it looks to be a rather thin line. In one of the clearest discussions I know, Christopher Potts (Potts 2015) claims that the main difference between the two is that presuppositions are “backgrounded” (p. 174), while conventional implicatures are not. That means that presuppositions need to be present in the common groundFootnote 25 between the participants of a conversation before the utterance, while conventional implicatures must be new to the common ground.

However, there are mechanisms that neutralize this difference:

  • For presuppositions that are new, there is the familiar notion of accommodation, going back to Lewis (1979). If an utterance requires a certain presupposition that is not yet part of the common ground, then the hearers normally quietly add it to the common ground.

  • For conventional implicatures that are not new to the conversation, Potts employs the idea of “evoked content” (Potts 2015, p. 190). The idea is that by using a sentence that conventionally implicates some fact that is already part of the common ground, that fact can thereby be brought back to attention, or its importance can be underlined.

Given those possibilities, it is unclear how the distinction between presuppositions and conventional implicatures can be neatly drawn in practice. Indeed, Potts goes on to suggest that the future of pragmatics might lie in the merging of categories such as these two, rather than more fine-grained frameworks (Potts 2015, p. 192).

However, there is an important difference between presuppositions and conventional implicatures, after all: As I mentioned above, a failed presupposition is usually taken to preclude the truth of the statement, while a false conventional implicature has no influence on the truth or falsity of the statement.Footnote 26

This difference will be important when I get to discuss the logical upshots of my investigation of pragmatics in Sects. 8 and 9, and I will further develop the topic there.

5.3 Stalnaker

In this last subsection, I want to look at a proposal that is due to Robert Stalnaker, who first developed it in his Stalnaker (1975a). It has been quite influential and, again, shares much with IP and CP; the differences between these principles and those he suggests, however, carry more weight than was the case in the other proposals discussed so far, and it will be worthwhile to pay close attention to them.

Stalnaker’s full theory of the semantics and pragmatics of conditionals is rich and has inspired much subsequent research; it is also quite subtle, and it has changed over the years. Looking back, he moreover once described his own writing as “vague and equivocal” (Stalnaker 2002, p. 701), and regarding at least some of the specifics, it is not implausible to agree with him on this. I will not attempt a full reconstruction of his theory here; I will only do so much as to bring out our differences and commonalities concerning the presuppositions in sufficient detail.

For Stalnaker, the pragmatics of indicative and counterfactual conditionals play a most important role. He thinks that semantically, there is actually no difference between the two kinds of conditionals.Footnote 27 It is only in their presuppositions that they differ.

To express these presuppositions, he makes use of a notion that I have already mentioned above without explaining it further, namely that of a common ground of a conversation. The common ground is what the participants of the conversation collectively take for granted.Footnote 28 That they in fact do take something for granted collectively might have different reasons. The standard case (meaning the most common and most straightforward case) is that they believe it, believe that the others believe it as well, believe that the others believe that everyone in the conversation believes it, etc.; that is, the standard is for common grounds to be constituted by common belief. Something is commonly believed either because it has been asserted and accepted in the earlier course of the conversation, because it is obvious common background knowledge, or because it is a salient feature of the context in which the discussion takes place.

Note that a common ground that is constituted by what is commonly believed might well hold open the possibility of the truth of a statement that the speaker actually thinks is false.Footnote 29 That is, not-A might not be in the common ground, even though the speaker believes A to be false. The converse, of course, holds: whatever actually is in the common ground needs to be believed by the speaker, at least in the standard case in which common belief and the common ground coincide.

However, this does not hold in other, non-standard cases that Stalnaker repeatedly draws our attention to: In these cases, Stalnaker allows that what is in the common ground actually need not be believed by the conversants. There are special contexts in which it is enough to be ready to assume (or to accept, or to take for granted) that everything in the common ground is true, if only for the sake of the conversation at hand.

In Stalnaker (2002),Footnote 30 he writes:

One may simplify or idealize in an inquiry, one may presume innocence to ensure fairness, one may make assumptions for the purpose of contingency planning, one may grant something for the purpose of an argument.

These kinds of contexts are indeed important and interesting. I believe that what I say below about the standard cases carries over to the non-standard cases, namely that IPFootnote 31 and CP are preferable to Stalnaker’s proposal. However, I found a satisfying discussion of the matter to be a quite complicated affair, with many cases to consider and intuitions in some of them turning rather murky. I have therefore decided to leave this discussion for another time and concentrate on the standard case.

Let me, then, present Stalnaker’s proposal for the presuppositions of conditionals, which are expressed in the theoretical framework that I have just sketched out.

Here is what Stalnaker takes the presuppositions of indicatives and counterfactuals to be:

figure f

The first of these is clearly stated in the text of Stalnaker (1975a),Footnote 32 the second not quite so clearly. At times he simply writes that counterfactuals presuppose the falsity of the antecedent,Footnote 33 just as I did in proposing CP. However, his general theory of presupposition (cf. Stalnaker 1975b) ensures that the two ways of expressing the condition come to the same thing, and expressing the presupposition as I did ensures that that general part of his theory is also captured.

Even without the specifics of Stalnaker’s theory of presuppositions in the background, it will turn out that the difference between the two ways of expressing the condition, and thus the difference (if there is any) between his proposal for counterfactuals and CP is not important, at least for the questions I am focused on in this piece.

The case of the indicative conditional, on the other hand, is quite another issue: We saw above that it makes quite a difference whether you say that a proposition must be a possibility left open by the common ground, or whether you say that it must be an epistemic possibility for the speaker. Moreover, this is a difference that will turn out to be important.

To decide which account is more promising, take again the example I introduced above:

If today is Tuesday, then it’s Mary’s birthday. Today is Monday.

Even though this seems clearly unassertable, Stalnaker cannot explain why this must be the case. It could well be that the common ground leaves the question open which day it is, because it is not common belief that today is Tuesday (maybe the two statements were preceded by someone else asking “What day is today?”). In that case, Stalnaker’s presupposition is met, while IP is not met.

Similarily, to say, in a conversation where nothing is commonly known about the beverage-related habits of the speaker,

If I have some beer in the fridge, you can have one. I don’t, though, I never have beer in the fridge.

is not just a lame move, it also seems linguistically defective to me. But, again, Stalnaker’s presupposition does not predict a defect; IP does.Footnote 34

Note that in well-behaved contexts, there can be no cases where the pattern of the last two examples is reversed, i.e., where Stalnaker would predict a presupposition failure and IP would not. If the common ground between you and me is constituted by our common belief, then it cannot preclude something that I think is possible. It can not be common belief between you and me that A is not the case while I believe that A might be true.

So, IP implies Stalnaker’s presupposition: If the speaker holds that the antecedent is a live possibility, then there can be nothing in the common ground that precludes it, as we are assuming that she believes everything in the common ground.

In making the last observation, I used the qualification “in well-behaved contexts” because this implication breaks down when the common ground is defective. This is Stalnaker’s term to describe situations in which there are divergent beliefs between the members of a conversation about what the common ground actually is. In such cases, it may well be that I hold something to be epistemically possible, while you think that our common ground rules it out.

In defective contexts, it might seem that Stalnaker’s presupposition is adding an important element that IP doesn’t cover.

For example, it seems at the very best borderline acceptable for an underage girl to tell her unsuspecting parents

If I’m pregnant, I’ll call the baby Kim, no matter whether it’s a girl or a boy.

if a possible pregnancy was not part of the common ground before.

Still, the ensuing discussion will probably not center on questions of linguistic appropriateness. More to the point, at least linguistically the example seems much less problematic than the example involving Mary’s birthday; and as far as it does have linguistic problems, I would argue that they have little to do with the conditional per se. You might have realized that the example is riffing on an example of von Fintel’s that Stalnaker mentions in Stalnaker (2011). In the example a daughter informs her father that she is getting married by saying

O Dad, I forgot to tell you that my fiancé and I are moving to Seattle next week.

The problem in these two examples is the same one: The daughter forces the parents to fix their end of the defective common ground via accommodation, where the importance of this information would call for a much more direct act of communication. If the topic were a less exciting one, or if it was not your daughter but one of your colleagues at work telling you these things, there would be little wrong with either of the examples.

In general, I submit that cases involving defective common grounds can be handled by IP at least as well as by Stalnaker’s presupposition, and I can’t think of any other examples in which IP might run into problems while Stalnaker’s presupposition would not (these would have to take the form of a pragmatically acceptable statement that is ruled out by IP but not by Stalnaker’s presupposition, given that the latter is implied by the former). Therefore, I conclude that in the standard case, where common ground and common belief come to the same thing, IP is preferable to Stalnaker’s presuppostion.

6 Connexive Intuitions, Pragmatically Explained

Armed with a proposal for the pragmatics of conditionals, as well as an understanding of some of its alternatives, let us now come to the first core question of this essay (Q-Pragmatic): Can we explain the connexive intuitions by appealing to these pragmatic features? For those who are, by now, at least somewhat excited about this possibility, there is good news and bad news ahead. I will start with the good news, which concerns the indicative flavor of conditionals.

6.1 Indicative Conditionals: Success (at Least with the Right Presupposition)

Starting with Aristotle, here is how IP might explain the intuition that “If A is the case, then not-A is the case” is never assertable.

According to IP, if a speaker asserts \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\), then she is presupposing that A is epistemically possible for her.

But the speaker undercuts that presupposition immediately with the consequent of the conditional. While that seems pre-theoretically obvious to me,Footnote 35 an explanation of how that undercutting exactly works will depend on the details of the semantic story we choose to give for indicative conditionals.Footnote 36 If this story fails to give such an explanation, then this would, in my opinion, speak strongly against it.

Here are four examples of how semantic theories of conditionals help explain why the presuppositionFootnote 37 fails:

  • Material Conditional In the simplest case, where some version of the material analysis is defended, the speaker who asserts \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) says nothing more nor less than \( \lnot A\). That is, she is denying the possibility of that which, according to the presupposition, should be epistemically possible for her.

  • Constructive/Intuitionistic Conditional For those favoring a constructive or intuitionistic interpretation of indicative conditionals, asserting \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) means something like this: If you give the speaker a construction that proves that A, he can turn that into a construction that proves \(\lnot A\), which is a definitional abbreviation of \(A \rightarrow \bot \) . Combining the two, the speaker can give you a construction that proves \(\bot \). Such a construction is impossible, so that means that he is certain that you will not be able to provide a construction of A (he has made what I have elsewhere called an “empty promise conversion”, see footnote 1). But that means that the truth (or provability) of A is not an epistemic possibility for him, which goes against the presupposition.

    If you think that intuitionistic logic provides the right formalization of the informal constructive interpretation, a quicker argument is that \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) is, as in classical logic, equivalent to \(\lnot A\).

  • Strict Conditional Here we are thinking in terms of possible worlds: \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) means that in all the accessible worlds from the actual one, if A is the case, then \(\lnot A\) is the case at that world. There are only two cases in which this is possible: If there are no accessible worlds from the actual one (including itself), or if A is true in none of the accessible worlds. Regarding the first possibility, I have not seen any proposal to analyze indicatives in terms of a strict conditional in which the actual world might be a “dead-end” world. Regarding the second, usually the modality underlying the strict analyses is some kind of wide-ranging possibility, either logical or metaphysical. That is, the only cases in which A will be true at no accessible world will be those in which A is impossible. By virtue of the logical form of her statement, the speaker makes a committment to the impossibility of A, and thus violates the presupposition.Footnote 38

  • Variably Strict Conditional For a reason very similar to the last one, a view of conditionals along the lines of Stalnaker’s Stalnaker (1975a) would tell us that anyone who makes a statement with the logical form \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) is ruling out the possibility of the antecedent. Again, his proposal was to use the same semantic account (plus some pragmatics) he gave for counterfactuals. The account is sometimes called a “variably strict” theory of conditionals, making the close connection to the strict account explicit. The “variable” part makes no difference: The only case in which \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) could be true is the one in which A is impossible.

In more general terms, if your conditional entails the material conditional (as is the case for most of the common variations of the last two items, but not the case for, e.g., intuitionistic logic), then the consideration about the material conditional above is all you need to think through.Footnote 39

Now, let us look at how the intuitions behind Boethius might be explained by IP. Why can’t it be correct to say both “If A is the case, then B is the case” and “If A is the case, then not-B is the case”? Because, according to IP, A should be epistemically possible for the speaker, and this possibility is not on the table any more if both conditionals are true. Again, the specifics of why it is off the table depends on the semantic account of the conditionals. For example, in the material case, one is saying “Either not-A or B” and “Either not-A or not-B”. In one of these, the second disjunct can’t be true. Thus, the first disjunct, not-A, must be true for the disjunction to be true. And if not-A is true, the possibility of A’s truth is not open any more. Explanations given in terms of the other semantic accounts of conditionals would proceed in a way that is similarly parallel to the explanations of the unassertability of \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) above.

To sum up: It appears that IP can supply a convincing pragmatic explanation of the connexive intuitions. Let us now look at Stalnaker’s proposal for the presuppositions of indicatives and see if a similar explanation could be had here. Again, Stalnaker’s presupposition only requires that, in a statement like \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\), the antecedent should be an open possibility in the common ground of the conversation.

There might be accounts of the semantics of indicatives that brew up some trouble in this case, but I am not aware of any. To give just one example, consider the material analysis of someone saying \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) while Stalnaker’s presupposition is met. On the material view of conditionals, this is equivalent to saying simply \(\lnot A\) in a conversation in which, up to that point, there was nothing in the common ground that precluded A. There is obviously no problem with that.

In general, I believe that there is no way that Stalnaker’s indicative presupposition can lead to a pragmatic explanation of the connexive intuitions. I have made my case for IP and against Stalnaker’s proposal. Those who are not convinced and still favor the latter over the former will have to give up hope for a pragmatic explanation of the connexive intuitions about indicative conditionals. Those who accept IP, in contrast, can avail themselves of such an explanation. What they can do with such an explanation will be explored after we take a look at counterfactuals.

6.2 Counterfactual Conditionals: No Pragmatic Explanation in Sight

As for counterfactuals, the hopes of explaining the connexive intuitions by appeal to pragmatics are rather dim on any of the proposals I have discussed. We have seen that there are three options on the table: Either they have no specific pragmatic principles associated with them at all, or they presuppose the falsity of the antecedent, or they presupposeFootnote 40 that the falsity of the antecedent is at least epistemically possible (either for the speaker or for all participants of the conversation). In the first case, it is obvious that there is nothing to be had here, so we are left with the second and the third (that is, CP and Karttunen and Peters’s proposal, respectively).

As I pointed out above (see Sect. 5), if CP is correct, then the speaker must also believe that the antecedent is false in order to speak correctly. A fortiori, she must believe that the antecedent is possibly false. Thus, Karttunen and Peters’s presupposition is entailed by CP. I think that even the stronger CP can’t yield an explanation of the connexive intuitions, so that this remains the only case to be examined.

Let us, then, begin with an attempt to explain the intuitions behind Aristotle with the help of CP: If I say

If A had been the case, then not-A would have been the case

and CP is correct, then what I say presupposes that A is false at the actual world. The consequent does not seem to contradict this. In fact, on a very naive way of thinking about this, it might even seem that this is exactly what it states. But of course, it is commonly accepted that the consequent of a counterfactual should not be evaluated at the actual world (or the actual situation, or in the obtaining state of affairs, or in reality, or whatever fits your semantic setup most comfortably). The presupposition, on the other hand, is about the actual world. There is neither corroboration nor tension between what is presupposed and what is said here.

To understand why the statement above is unassertable, one needs to understand something about the semantics of the statement. According to some of our best theories, what one needs to understand is that A must be true in the world (or worlds, or situation(s), or state(s) of affairs ... ) in which the statement is to be evaluated, and to understand that in such a world, not-A can therefore not be true, and thus, that the whole statement must be false. But all of that is a matter of semantics, not pragmatics.

As for the intuitions behind Boethius, to understand why saying both

If A had been the case, then B would have been the case

and

If A had been the case, then not-B would have been the case

at the same time is wrong, CP is no help. Instead, one needs to understand (again, if one of the family of our most successful theories in the field is correct) that both statements need to be evaluated at a world (state of affairs...) in which A is the case, and that in such a world, B and not-B can’t both be true, and that thus the two statements cannot be asserted together. And again, this is a matter of semantics, not pragmatics.

In sum, what is doing the explanatary work for indicatives is that the antecedent has to be epistemically possible for the speaker. This is not a presupposition that attaches to counterfactuals, and the ones that do (if any) cannot step up to do the job.

Thus, it seems to me that CP, and therefore also the weaker alternatives we have explored, cannot add to an explanation of the connexive intuitions. If we want to do right by them, then we will have to deal with that in our semantic theory. As I mentioned above, we are in luck here, as at least some of the favorite theories for counterfactuals conform to the connexive theses, provided we take them in their humble form (see Sect. 2).Footnote 41

To sum up what has been claimed in this part:

  • There is a presupposition for indicatives (which I called IP) that says that the antecedent needs to be epistemically possible for the speaker: If I say “If today is Monday, Susy will come home tomorrow”, then this is only correct if I don’t know for sure that today is not Monday.

  • This presupposition rules out the correct assertibility of statements like “If today is Monday, today is not Monday”.

  • However, this presupposition does not hold for counterfactuals: If I say “If I hadn’t met my wife, my children would not have been born”, then that surely does not presuppose that my not meeting my wife is epistemically possible for me.

  • Therefore, an explication running parallel to the indicative case does not work, nor will explanations building on other presuppositions for counterfactuals.

In terms of our guiding pair of questions, this leaves us with an answer of the first and a restriction of the second:

figure g

Part III: Logical Upshots

So far, we have learned that the pragmatics of conditionals judge that assertions like \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) are incorrect for indicatives, but not for counterfactuals. What does that mean for logic choice? After all, we are interested in what we can learn about connexive logic from all this.

The answer to that question depends on two very general issues. First: What general shape is our theory of conditionals supposed to take? And second: How are we going to treat presupposition failures (or false conventional implicatures) logically?

I will spend the next two sections to talk about these questions one by one.

7 V- and Y-shaped Accounts of Conditionals

So, let us start with the first question: What shape is, ultimately, our theory of conditionals going to take?

The talk of shapes is of course not quite literal, but it almost is. Jonathan Bennett has introduced a very vivid way of talking about two general shapes such theories can take. He calls them “Y- shaped” and “V-shaped” theories (see Fig. 1).

A Y-shaped theory (what others sometimes call a “unified” theory) tries to give an account of the semantics of indicatives and counterfactuals that is as closely related as possible. The account shares all of the stem of the Y-shape, and only bifurcates at the last possible moment. One classic example of this is Stalnaker’s own theory,Footnote 42 who holds that the pragmatic constraints on indicatives are the only difference between indicatives and counterfactuals. That is, the whole account involving variable strictness, the idea of most similar worlds, etc. is located on the stem of the Y, and the only additional idea on one of the branches (the indicative branch) is that the pragmatic constraint is in place.

The main attraction of a Y-shaped theory is that it explains why indicatives and counterfactuals are sharing so much in terms of surface grammar (see Stalnaker 1987, p. 111ff, for this and other arguments, and Bennett 2003 for discussion).

In contrast, those who prefer a V-shaped theory do not give much weight to this consideration. For them, the similarity of surface grammar is an oddity that masks a vast difference in semantics (see Gibbard (1980) for the classic expression of this line of argument). Accordingly, the two branches of semantical analysis go off in different directions very early on. Examples of such V-shaped theories would be those that give Lewis-Stalnaker-style analyses of counterfactuals, but explain indicatives in terms of the material conditional or in terms of conditional probabilities.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Different kinds of theories of conditionals (Bennett 2003)

Now, where will the features that preclude the assertability of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc. be located in these pictures? Let us refer to pragmatic features of this kind by “P!” and to semantic features by “S!”, and see where we should place them.

We have seen that the pragmatic constraints on counterfactuals do not add to a pragmatic preclusion. There will thus not be a P! on the right branch; but, given that we are, as a premise of this essay, committed to explaining the connexive intuitions one way or the other, we should therefore expect a S! somewhere on this branch.

On the other hand, we have seen that it is plausible to expect a P! on the left (indicative) branch. Nothing I have presented here should lead us to conclude that a S! couldn’t be on that branch, as well; in this case we would be dealing with a sort of double causation for indicatives: Statements like \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) are unassertable for semantic and pragmatic reasons alike (presumably, the pragmatic reasons should be seen as preempted by the semantic ones).

So, two scenarios are possible, depending on whether there is a S! on the indicative branch or not. Here is how those two possibilities look like for V-shaped theories:

  • P! : Pragmatic feature that prohibits assertability of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc.

  • S! : Semantic feature that prohibits truth of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Where the semantic action might be on a V

The right shape is somewhat unlikely given that convincing connexive logics are arguably scarce, but of course it is a possible pattern. As it displays a form of causal overdetermination, where pragmatics is preempted by semantics, such a shape would suggest a ready answer to Q-Revision: No, pragmatics will not come to the rescue of those who do not want to revise logic. The semantic features that make up S! will make their influence on logic choice felt.

On the other hand, the left shape leaves the possibility of a positive answer to Q-Revision open, and we will therefore keep exploring it further. This shape would be exemplified by an account that accepts, say, a Stalnaker-style explanation of counterfactualsFootnote 43 but reverts to a material analysis for indicatives.

For Y-shaped explanations, (see Fig. 3), the considerations above mean that the P! needs to occur after the branching point. For otherwise, we would see a pragmatic explanation of the unassertability of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc. for counterfactuals, which, according to my arguments in Sect. 6.2, is not to be expected.

The location of the S!, however, seems to me to be likely to be on the stem of the Y, simply because it seems plausible to me that a difference in semantics that is great enough to warrant the unassertability of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc. will be so fundamental that it becomes implausible to still call the account Y-shaped, even if there has been quite a bit of material in common to the account of indicatives and counterfactuals. The picturesque way of talking about V- and Y-shaped accounts is useful, but one should keep in mind that it is only a means of illustration and should not be taken too literally. Whether something is a Y or a V is a matter of degree. Even the clearest V-shaped account will, if you zoom in, display a little stem. For example, there will not be a sensible theory that gives the meaning of indicatives by solely interpreting linguistic items while factoring facial expressions into the meaning of counterfactuals. So, a theory that starts with linguistic expressions in both cases, but goes off into wildly different directions afterwards, will still have a little common stem; the information that linguistic expressions are what is to be interpreted lives on that stem, if nothing else (and in most cases, there will be much more).

So, whether we are dealing with a Y-shaped picture or a V-shaped one is a matter of discretion, but I think it probable that it will be more natural to call a theory that has an S! on only one branch a V-shaped theory.

Fig. 3
figure 3

Where the semantic action might lie on a Y

That leaves the class of Y-shaped accounts in a similar state as the right shape in Fig. 2. Yes, the pragmatics of indicatives would rule out statements that offend our connexive intuitions, but those have been taken out of the race at an earlier stage by semantic considerations already. The answer to Q-Revision would, once again, be negative. To give an example for such a theoretical scenario, Stalnaker’s theory simply displays a single S! on the stem of the Y and, in fact, no P! at all, as we have seen above that his pragmatic theory does not rule out statements like \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\). If, however, Stalnaker would be convinced to accept IP in standard contexts, he would be lead to the shape we are talking about.

In either case, how to treat statements like \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) logically is a question that pragmatics has little to add to in such an environment. More generally, it seems to me that a defender of a Y-shaped account who wants to do justice to the connexive intuitions will simply have to provide a semantic theory that validates the connexive theses. A Y-shaped theory requires a connexive logic.

We have, thus, established for which class of theories a study of the pragmatics might have the most interesting logical upshots regarding connexivity. More to the point, we have determined which shape a theory must have to make a positive answer to Q-Revision possible. To repeat, it is the shape of a theory that gives a quite distinct semantic account of indicatives and counterfactuals, and for which the unassertability of \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc. is explained pragmatically for indicatives in standard contexts, and semantically for counterfactuals.

Fig. 4
figure 4

Theories in which pragmatics can have an influence on logic choice

8 Semantic Responses to Presupposition Failures

Now, exactly what the logical upshots of a consideration of the pragmatics of indicatives might be is the topic of this section. There are three possible outcomes, corresponding to three responses to the question what happens to the truth value of an indicative conditional whose presupposition is not met.

I found that few if any of the authors who write about the pragmatics of conditionals give explicit answers to this question. However, the following three options are discussed in the more general literature on failures of presuppositions and conventional implicatures.

(A):

The pragmatic failure is a conventional implicature and has no effect on the truth value of the statement.

(B):

If one sees the pragmatic failure as a presupposition failure, then the first option holds that neither something true nor something false was said.Footnote 44

(C):

The other prominent way of treating a statement with a failed presupposition is to view it as simply false.

The debate between proponents of options (B) and (C) has been going on since Peter Strawson’s classic paper On Referring (Strawson 1950), in which he made the case for option (B). A good starting point for delving into this debate is von Fintel’s (2004). If any consensus at all has been achieved, then it is probably that naive intuitions will not be ultimately decisive here. They are too uncertain and context sensitive to bear that much weight. As Beaver (2001, p. 10) writes:

Judgements on whether sentences are meaningless or false are typically hazy - indeed, it is hard even to know how to pose to a naive informant the question of whether a given sentence is meaningless or false - and the debate arguably never reached a satisfactory conclusion.

The question will more likely be decided by theoretical concerns: How easy will it be to integrate either option into a larger theory of language and logic that gives a correct and, as far as possible, elegant account?

To judge this question in our case, let us see how these options would play out for statements like \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\), etc. Applying these general strategies to concrete examples like

If today is Monday, then today isn’t Monday.

leads to judgments such as these:

(A\('\)):

According to the first option, I might be saying something true with such a statement. I might also be saying something false; this will be decided by the semantics of the conditional and the factual question which day of the week it is. (E.g., for classical logicians the statement will be judged false when uttered on Monday, and true otherwise.) In either case, the conditional will be pragmatically unassertable. Thus, this option would underwrite the intuition I have called Unassertability (see Sect. 3).

(B\('\)):

According to the second view, the statement above does not have a truth value. This accords well with pre-theoretic intuitions that find the statement bizzarre and even maybe non-sensical. Such intuitions would be expressed by Untruth.

(C\('\)):

Lastly, proponents of the third option would judge the assertion of such statements as simply false. This accords with intuition Falsity.

As I have said above, I locate my own intuitions between Untruth and Falsity; but again, intuitions will probably not be what decides between those two, and maybe they aren’t even reliable enough to confidently rule out mere Unassertability.

So, let us turn to more theoretical concerns. First, for both option (B) and (C), we will need more machinery to evaluate the truth values of conditionals than we might have expected, because those truth values now depend on whether the presupposition is met, and that depends on what speakers believe to be possible. In particular, we need the semantic machinery necessary to evaluate indexicals. What we will need to evaluate “If A, then B” is exactly what we need to determine the truth value of

I believe A might be true, and, if A, then B.

Indeed, option (C) agrees with the truth value of that statement, while option (B) gives a different result if the presupposition is not met (namely, it judges “If A, then B” truthvalueless in such a case).

There is a critique of similar cases of seemingly extreme context dependence of conditionals by Edgington (1986), who has specifically Stalnaker’s view (Stalnaker 1975a) in mind here.Footnote 45 He responds in Stalnaker (2011) to this worry;Footnote 46 I will not go into their argument further, I only want to flag that this is a point that anyone who wants to implement (B) or (C) will have to address, and if that can’t be done adequately, this would speak in favor of option (A).

But let us get to another theoretical concern, the one that is at the center of this whole investigation: What effect do the different options above have on logic choice?

9 The Pragmatic Effects on the Choice of Logic

In terms of logic choice, options (A) and (C) represent black and white responses as far as connexivity is concerned:

Proponents of option (A) will say that logic is unconstrained by pragmatic failures. Thus, even though the connexive intuitions should not be dismissed, a non-connexive logic faces no problems in accommodating them.

On the other hand, friends of option (C) will have to say that instances of \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) are always false. Therefore, instances of \(\lnot (A \rightarrow \lnot A)\) etc. will always be true, and consequently a fully connexive logic will be called for.

It is option (B) that might allow for a more nuanced answer. Again, according to (B), \(A \rightarrow \lnot A\) is neither true nor false. What that means for \(\lnot (A \rightarrow \lnot A)\) depends on the semantics of negation, in particular how it reacts to truth value gaps. If negation is a truth-functional connective, there are only two plausible options, sometimes called external and internal negation, respectively:

figure h

Applied to our example, the first view says that

It is not the case that if today is Tuesday, it is not Tuesday.

is negating something that is not true, and thus that it itself is true.

The second view denies that, maybe because it views the statement to be so strange that it does not make any more sense than the statement that is negated, and therefore, that it is likewise not even false. This would be more in line with Strawson’s original argument, but of course he was not thinking about conditionals in that context.

In any case, logically the first choice (external negation) leads to the same outcome as option (C): All four of Aristotle, Boethius and the two UnSat-conditions will be required (possibly, if you agree with me, with the humble restrictions discussed in Sect. 2).

The second, internal, interpretation of negation will, in contrast, not require the validity of Aristotle and Boethius: A truth value gap will usually not be designated;Footnote 47 therefore, \(\lnot (A\rightarrow \lnot A)\) will not be expected to be a logical truth, since it will always take this undesignated value.

Does that mean that someone who champions the internal interpretation is in the same boat as proponents of option (A) above, in that their view imposes no strictures on logic when it comes to connexive ideas?

Not quite: As \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) will always take an undesignated value, we are reminded of the unsatisfiability clauses mentioned in section 2. To repeat:

  • UnSat1: In no model, \((A\rightarrow \lnot A)\) is satisfiable.

  • UnSat2: In no model \(A\rightarrow B\) and \(A\rightarrow \lnot B\) are satisfiable simultaneously (for any A and B).

In Estrada-González and Ramírez-Cámara (2016), discussed logics that obey UnSat1 and UnSat2 but do not necessarily validate Aristotle and Boethius, and they chose to call these logics Kapsner-strong connexive logics. However, beyond introducing the notion, neither their paper nor any other I am aware of in the connexive literature makes any suggestion as to what the possible use of such logics might be. So far, the line of thought above is the only I can think of that would motivate such logics, and it does so quite clearly in the case of UnSat1: If we treat both \(A\rightarrow \lnot A\) etc. and \(\lnot (A\rightarrow \lnot A)\) etc. as truthvalueless, we will not want to ask for the validity of Aristotle, but we will want to insist on UnSat1.

On the other hand, the story that tries to motivate UnSat2 along parallel lines is not quite as simple. The pragmatic dissonance that we observed arose if a single speaker asserted both \(A \rightarrow B\) and \(A \rightarrow \lnot B\). If the statements are made by different speakers, that dissonance might disappear: if you assert \(A \rightarrow B\) and I assert \(A \rightarrow \lnot B\), then that does not show that either of us isn’t taking A to be an epistemic possibility. So, the presupposition might actually be met and a truth value gap might not be called for. And consequently, UnSat2 might not be a necessary part of the account.

However, we have already at the end of Sect. 8 seen that the truth-value-gap analysis forces us to see conditionals as more indexical semantic phenomena than we might have expected. In view of that, we should maybe modify UnSat2 in the following way:

  • Unsat2*: In no model, the propositions expressed by \(A\rightarrow B\) and \(A\rightarrow \lnot B\), as uttered by the same speaker, are satisfiable simultaneously (for any A and B).

I don’t mean to be specific on how a model theory that incorporates speaker roles in this way might look like; as one of the reviewers rightly remarks, one example of the kind of theory this might lead to is Jaśkowski’s (1999). There, the requirement would, roughly, translate to the conjunction of \(A\rightarrow B\) and \(A\rightarrow \lnot B\) being embedded under the same modal operator.

I am not sure whether Estrada-González and Ramírez-Cámara would still want to call a logic that satisfies only UnSat1 and Unsat2* Kapsner-strongly connexive, or indeed, whether there might not be better phrased alternatives to this amendment. Also, the fact that my discussion seems to provide some possible motivation for a property that bears my name makes me slightly suspicious of my own subconscious motives. Therefore, I will simply speak of Unsatisfiability-logics in the short rest of this pieceFootnote 48 and mean by that logics that capture the spirit of UnSat1 and UnSat2 with the understanding that they might have to be adapted to the specifics of the semantic theory at hand, maybe along the lines of Unsat2*, or maybe in some other way.

It seems clear that the constraints on an Unsatisfiability-logic might be easier to fulfill than those of full connexivity, as the former constraints are a proper part of the latter, at least if connexivity is understood along the lines of my characterization in Sect. 2 and factoring in the idea of the last paragraph concerning the modification of UnSat2. If we should find ourselves with a satisfying logic that obeys the unsatisfiability clauses, but does not achieve full connexivity, then that could be seen as the kind of theoretical clue that might help us decide whether Untruth or Falsity is the best way of making our connexive intuitions more precise.

I sum up the possibilities for indicative conditionals (on a V-shaped theory with no S! on the left branch) in the following table:

figure i

As an impetus for future logical explorations, maybe most interesting in this table is the middle ground that the second line represents. As I pointed out in the first part of this essay, it is admittedly very hard to find a strongly connexive logic that has a convincing and well motivated semantics, even under the restrictions of humble connexivity; however, reaching such a point with a logic that only has to satisfy Unsat1 and Unsat2* seems much more feasible.

That said, all of the lines in the table above present interesting possibilities with their unique benefits, but also with their own challenges that any theory that tries to make them more concrete will have to deal with. What is, at the very least, commendable about all of them is that they all take the connexive intuitions seriously and try to provide a theoretical explanation of them, a task that much of mainstream philosophical logic has not come to terms with so far.

10 Summary

Let me end by bringing it all together: I have argued that the connexive intuitions are too strong to be ignored, and have invested some time into making them more explicit before trying to explain them (Sects. 2, 3).

In this piece, my aim was to find out whether a pragmatic explanation of these intuitions might work. This, first, required me to delve into the pragmatics of conditionals and to synthesize an account from the discussions in the literature that strikes me as correct (Sect. 5).

The upshot of applying that account to the probelm at hand is this: I think that explaining the connexive intuitions pragmatically might be quite a viable route in the case of indicatives, but not for counterfactuals (Sect. 6).

The presupposition that does the relevant work is that the antecedent is an epistemic possibility for the speaker; that presupposition only attaches to indicatives, not to counterfactuals.Footnote 49

I argued that, at least if the underlying theory of conditionals is of the V-shaped variety (see Sect. 7), the pragmatic account might allow someone to stick to their non-connexive logic for indicatives and still acknowledge the correctness of the connexive intuitions. What that means for logic depends on how one chooses to treat pragmatic failures (Sects. 8, 9).

The upshot of all of this is presented in the following two answers to my leading questions:

figure j

The above presents the result of an inquiry I decided to engage in because I had a hazy hunch that there seemed to be a certain pragmatic dimension to my connexive intuitions.Footnote 50 I could at the time not articulate it any better, because up to that point, I had never inquired what the literature had to say about the pragmatics of conditionals. I am now confident that that hunch was correct, in the manner that my answer to Q-Pragmatic indicates. The positive result (for indicatives) and the negative one (for counterfactuals) strike me as equally important.

As I said up front, when it comes to Q-Revision I have tried to treat all of the options impartially and to point out what seems to me the most fruitful ways in which they might be further pursued and elaborated. However, it is not the case that this aspired impartiality reflects a truly agnostic stance. After thinking about this for a long while, my own general feeling, which I allow myself now to express, is that a purely pragmatic explanation of the connexive intuitions is potentially useful, but unsatisfying at a deeper level.

Here is an analogy; if you find that it is a fitting one, then this will indicate that we share that same intuitive discomfort with a positive answer to Q-Revision. Say you are interested (hopefully for purely theoretical reasons) in the problem of blackmail. Thinking hard about it, you find that it is exceedingly hard to say why blackmail is wrong and, indeed, why it should be considered a crime. Thinking even longer about it, you come up with a purely economic argument about misallocated resources that indicates that a society that makes blackmail a crime will be better able to maximize economic efficiency.

This is not a fanciful example. One can read Coase (1988) for a great exposition of the theoretical conundrum and the economic argument. Coase’s argument has since engendered a sizeable commentarial literature, but let us assume, for the sake of analogical argument, that it is roughly correct. We have, then, a way forward for theoretically justifying the legal statutes concerning blackmail, statutes that help prevent deeds that are intuitively obviously wrong. Maybe we’re even reasonable happy with legal theorists turning their attention to more pressing matters. But deep down, few will get the feeling that the question has been fully answered, and, moreover, that the answer came from quite the right angle. Coase himself ended his essay on blackmail by noting: “It would be a sad day if all the answers had to be provided by economists.”Footnote 51 In the future, we may yet get to a deeper and better understanding of the wrongness of blackmail. Maybe this will suggest better legal instruments to deal with it, and maybe this will even lead to different verdicts in a few cases.

This is, broadly, how I feel about the pragmatic explanation of connexive intuitions. Not that asserting “If A, then not-A” is quite as bad as blackmailing someone, but I do sense close similarity in the explanatory pattern: In adopting the pragmatic explanation, we have at least not made the mistake of ignoring the problem. But there is a lingering sense that the ultimate solution will be one in which a deeper reason for these intuitions will be uncovered (in terms of the illustrations above, that the ultimate picture will be one in which a P! is preempted by a S! on the same branch). This will not make the pragmatic account irrelevant, just as the economical considerations of blackmail will be valuable even after a deeper moral account of blackmail’s nature is found. The pragmatic failures I have pointed to in this essay are part of what is wrong with assertions that go against connexive intuitions for indicatives. A full understanding of what it wrong with such assertions will involve the pragmatic part of the story. And maybe, if my gut feeling is misguided, this is the whole story.