Skip to main content
Log in

Interpreting Supersymmetry

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Supersymmetry in quantum physics is a mathematically simple phenomenon that raises deep foundational questions. To motivate these questions, I present a toy model, the supersymmetric harmonic oscillator, and its superspace representation, which adds extra anticommuting dimensions to spacetime. I then explain and comment on three foundational questions about this superspace formalism: whether superspace is a substance, whether it should count as spatiotemporal, and whether it is a necessary postulate if one wants to use the theory to unify bosons and fermions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. My presentation of this model is based off of Susskind (2012) and Bagchi (2001, 9–36).

  2. Not that \((Q^{\dag })^2=0\), which means that we cannot violate the exclusion principle by replacing multiple bosons with fermions. Only one particle may be swapped. This phenomenon holds generally: SUSY doesn’t allow us to create Bose-Einstein condensates out of fermions, for example!

  3. Roughly, a supergroup behaves like a group except that it includes some elements that multiply like Grassmann numbers.

  4. This is closely related to North’s own view of how to understand the debate about general relativity, except that she considers substantivalism about general relativity to be a conditional view of the form: If general relativity were a fundamental theory, then spacetime would be fundamental (North 2018).

  5. To avoid the misleading appearance of begging the question against either superspace spatiotemporality or its denial, I will do my best to refer to “the thing substantivalists are substantivalist about” not as spacetime, but as the fundamental background structure of a theory.

  6. The two formalisms may still differ about which observable operators signify fundamental quantities, as opposed to merely physically significant (but derivative) quantities. I wish I had room in the present paper to explore the implications of this possible disagreement, but it is worth noting that it may imply further differences in explanatory power between the Minkowksi substantivalist and superspace substantivalist ontologies, beyond the ones discussed here.

  7. Such a law will have to relate a theory’s dynamical symmetries to its absolute background geometrical structure, of course. In a theory like general relativity, for example, which admits of many solutions with different spacetime structures, we should not require that the symmetries of the force laws vary from solution to solution. But a similar law in general relativity could explain the local Lorentz covariance of the laws of general relativistic field theory, since Lorentz covariance is a local symmetry of all general relativistic spacetimes.

  8. Knox’s account actually focuses on local inertial frames, but since the scope of this paper only includes flat spacetimes, I’ll follow Menon in leaving that complication aside and considering only the special case of global inertial frames.

  9. Thanks to Tim Maudlin and James Wells for discussion that inspired some of the arguments presented here, to Alexander Schenkel for fielding some of my mathematical questions, and to Tushar Menon for many months of edifying discussion, correspondence and comments.

References

  • Bagchi, B. K. (2001). Supersymmetry in quantum and classical mechanics. New York: Chapman and Hall/CRC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, D. J. (2009). Against field interpretations of quantum field theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 585–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, D. J. (2020). Knox’s inertial spacetime functionalism (and a better alternative). Synthese. https://doi-org.proxy.lib.umich.edu/10.1007/s11229-020-02598-z.

  • Baker, D. J., Halvorson, H., & Swanson, N. (2015). The conventionality of parastatistics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66, 929–976.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, T. W., & Halvorson, H. (2016). Glymour and quine on theoretical equivalence. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 45, 467–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. R. (2005). Physical relativity: Space-time structure from a dynamical perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchbinder, I. L., & Kuzenko, S. M. (1998). Ideas and methods of supersymmetry and supergravity. London: IOP Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castellani, L., Catenacci, R., & Grassi, P. A. (2014). Supergravity actions with integral forms. Nuclear Physics B, 889, 419–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coffey, K. (2014). Theoretical equivalence as interpretative equivalence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 821–844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1989). World enough and spacetime. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hack, T.-P., Hanisch, F., & Schenkel, A. (2016). Supergeometry in locally covariant quantum field theory. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 342, 615–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. (1998). Absolute versus relational spacetime: For better or worse, the debate goes on. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 451–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N., & Wüthrich, C. (2013). Emergent spacetime and empirical (in)coherence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 276–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, M. (2009). Drawing the line between kinematics and dynamics in special relativity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 40, 26–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knox, E. (2013). Effective spacetime geometry. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 346–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knox, E. (2014). Newtonian spacetime structure in light of the equivalence principle. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 863–880.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, S. P. (2016). A supersymmetry primer, hep-ph/9709356.

  • Menon, T. (forthcoming). Taking up superspace. In N. Huggett, C. Wuthrich & B. Le Bihan (Eds.), Philosophy beyond spacetime. Oxford: Oxford UP.

  • Minkowski, H. (1909). Space and time. Annual Report of the German Mathematician Association, 18, 75–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, J. (2018). A new approach to the relational-substantival debate. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 11, 3–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, J., Brown, H. R., & Lehmkuhl, D. (2018). Two miracles of general relativity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 64, 14–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenstock, S., Barrett, T. W., & Weatherall, J. O. (2015). On Einstein algebras and relativistic spacetimes. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52, 309–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rynasiewicz, R. (1996). Absolute versus relational space-time: An outmoded debate? Journal of Philosophy, 93, 279–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2006). Review of Harvey R. Brown, Physical relativity: Space-time structure from a dynamical perspective. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.

  • Susskind, L. (2012). Supersymmetry and Grand Unification. Stanford University Lecture Series. Retrieved April 27, 2017, from https://www.youtube.com/playlist?list=PL_IkS0viawhpBbVkmwRLiysdV5eXegvd.

  • Wallace, D. (2008). Philosophy of quantum mechanics. In D. Rickles (Ed.), The Ashgate companion to contemporary philosophy of physics (pp. 16–98). Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weingard, R. (1988). A philosopher looks at string theory. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (pp. 95–106).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David John Baker.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baker, D.J. Interpreting Supersymmetry. Erkenn 87, 2375–2396 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00306-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00306-4

Navigation