In this section we will translate the four positions introduced in Sect. 3 as well as (PDO) and (CTRL) into CBN terminology. Hand in hand with the translation process we will develop two causal models which will allow us to evaluate whether (PDO) and (CTRL) can be combined with these views. We will use these models to explore which combinations of (PDO) and (CTRL) are metaphysically possible given the different combinations of non-reductive versus reductive physicalism and determinism versus indeterminism. Assuming different combinations of these positions will give us different constraints on the probability distributions compatible with our models and, thus, will delimit the space of metaphysical possibilities. Let us start with some basic assumptions for both models. For the evaluation we are aiming at we need to represent an agent’s decisions as well as what is going on at the fundamental physical level. Let us do this by means of a variable D (modeling an agent’s decisions) and the three variables \(P_0\), \(P_1\), and \(P_2\) (representing different physical states). We assume that \(P_0\) is a direct cause of \(P_1\), and that \(P_1\) is a direct cause of \(P_2\). Thus, our two models will feature the causal chain \(P_0\longrightarrow P_1\longrightarrow P_2\). In addition, let us assume that the agential states modeled by D supervene on the physical states represented by \(P_1\).
Next, let us see which constraints we have to accept if non-reductive physicalism were true. Recall that non-reductive physicalism is committed to (ONI), (SUP), and (CE). \(\mathbf {(ONI)}\) demands that D is on an ontologically different level than the physical states represented by \(P_0,P_1,P_2\). Because of this, D should not be identified with one of these variables:
- (\({\mathbf{ONI}}_{{BN}}\)):
D is not identical with one of the variables \(P_0,P_1,P_2\).
\(\mathbf {(SUP)}\) says that an agent’s decisions supervene on physical states. For our model this means that D supervenes on \(P_1\), which gives us the following topological and probabilistic constraints:
- (\({\mathbf{SUP}}_{{BN}}\)):
\(P_1\Longrightarrow D\) is part of the model and the following two equations hold:
$$\begin{aligned}&\forall d\forall d'\exists p_1:{\text { If }}d\not =d{'\text {, then }}P(p_1|d)\not =P(p_1|d') \end{aligned}$$
(2)
$$\begin{aligned}&\forall p_1\exists d: P(d|p_1)=1 \end{aligned}$$
(3)
The arrow \(P_1\Longrightarrow D\) represents the supervenience relation in our model. It is required to account for the dependence of D on \(P_1\) and is assumed to technically work exactly like an ordinary single-tailed causal arrow: It conforms to the Markov factorization [Eq. (1)].Footnote 12 Equation (2) says that if the decision variable D changes its value, the probability distribution over its supervenience base \(P_1\) has to change as well, and Eq. (3) guarantees that fixing the value of the supervenience base \(P_1\) fully determines the value of the supervening variable D. Note that (\({\mathbf{SUP}}_{{BN}}\)) does not provide a definition of supervenience; the condition should rather be seen as a consequence (formulated in terms of the CBN model) that comes with assuming supervenience (SUP).
\(\mathbf {(CE)}\) finally forces us to add an arrow from D to \(P_2\). This reflects the assumption that, according to non-reductive physicalism, decisions are at least sometimes causally relevant for an agent’s actions at the physical level:
- (\({\mathbf{CE}}_{{BN}}\)):
\(D\longrightarrow P_2\) is part of the model.
The graph of the model we get when subscribing to non-reductive physicalism will, according to the considerations above, be the one depicted in Fig. 1.Footnote 13 Reductive physicalism, on the other hand, can be modeled by a CBN with the structure depicted in Fig. 2. We arrive at this graph by removing the arrow \(P_1\Longrightarrow D\) and by identifying D with \(P_1\). This move can be justified by translating (RED) into (\({\mathbf{RED}}_{{BN}}\)). (\({\mathbf{RED}}_{{BN}}\)) reflects the main thesis of reductionism which implies that agential properties are identical to physical properties in our model:Footnote 14
- (\({\mathbf{RED}}_{{BN}}\)):
D is identical with \(P_1\).
We have now two models available: One captures non-reductive physicalism (Fig. 1), and one reductive physicalism (Fig. 2). We can further constrain both models’ probability distributions in such a way that they reflect the assumption of determinism or indeterminism. Let us start with determinism. To represent (DET) in our models, we have to establish a deterministic dependence of every physical variable on its direct physical cause:
- (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)):
For all \(p_i,p_j\) with \(i\in \{0,1\}\) and \(j=i+1\): \(P(p_j|p_i)\) is either 1 or 0.
Indeterminism can, in accordance with (IND), be formulated as the negation of (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)):
- (\({\mathbf{IND}}_{{BN}}\)):
For some \(p_i,p_j\) with \(i\in \{0,1\}\) and \(j=i+1\): \(P(p_j|p_i)\) is neither 1 nor 0.
One might wonder whether determinism and indeterminism are not represented in a too simplistic way. (DET) and (IND) both refer to how things are earlier and to the laws of nature. In our models, on the other hand, \(P_1\) and \(P_2\) have only one direct cause and (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)) simply assumes that each \(P_0\)-value determines some \(P_1\)-value with probability 1 and that each \(P_1\)-value determines some \(P_2\)-value with probability 1, where (\({\mathbf{IND}}_{{BN}}\)) is the negation of that claim. In addition, neither (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)) nor (\({\mathbf{IND}}_{{BN}}\)) mention laws of nature. The idea here is the same as in the case of (\({\mathbf{SUP}}_{{BN}}\)) above: (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)) and (\({\mathbf{IND}}_{{BN}}\)) should not be read as definitions of determinism and indeterminism, respectively, but rather as consequences one gets by assuming (DET) or (IND) formulated in terms of the two models. The laws of nature, for example, are not explicitly represented in the models. They appear, however, implicitly: They are crucial for how exactly the models’ probability distributions are constrained. And that we assume that \(P_1\)’s only cause is \(P_0\) and that \(P_2\)’s only cause is \(P_2\) is a harmless simplification. One could also split each one of the variables \(P_i\) (with \(0\le i\le 2\)) into two or more variables. This would make the reasoning and the models a little bit more complicated, but would have no impact on the results we will present below. Hence, we stick with the nice and simple models whose graphs are depicted in Figs. 1 and 2.
Before we can evaluate whether a strong notion of free will committed to (PDO) and (CTRL) is compatible with the four ontological positions introduced in Sect. 3, we finally have to translate (PDO) and (CTRL) into the language of our models as well. (PDO) requires that the agent has the possibility to decide otherwise. In terms of our two causal models this idea could be expressed by assuming that D’s value is not fully determined by the variables describing the past:
- (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)):
The conditional probabilities P(d|x) are not extreme, where X stands for the set of variables describing D’s past.
Note that (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)) nicely fits the strong version of the possibility to do otherwise we introduced in Sect. 2: If an agent’s decisions are not fully determined by the laws and the past, then the probabilities P(d|x) in (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)) should not be extreme. This corresponds, in terms of the model, to the assumption that the agent possesses the actualist possibility to do otherwise as is captured by (PDO) introduced in Sect. 2.
The second requirement for free will which we introduced in Sect. 2 is that an agent is supposed to have to some extent (causal) control over her environment. To decide whether D has probabilistic causal impact on the agent’s environment (here represented by \(P_2\)), we can employ the productivity test for single causal arrows introduced in Sect. 4. (CTRL) can then be translated as follows:
- (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)):
\(P_2\) probabilistically depends on D conditional on \(Par(P_2)\backslash \{D\}\).
More informally, (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)) requires that—for an agent to have free will—her decisions must be probabilistic causal difference makers. They have to make a probabilistic causal difference for her environment in at least some causal setting, where possible causal settings are modeled by \(P_2\)’s alternative causes \(Par(P_2)\backslash \{D\}\) taking different values r.
We have now all the tools available for evaluating whether a strong notion of free will subscribing to (PDO) and (CTRL) is compatible with our four world views introduced in Sect. 3. Let us start with the first model (Fig. 1) representing non-reductive physicalism, which seemed to be one of the more promising views for a strong incompatibilist notion of free will.
Non-reductive Physicalism Plus Determinism According to our first wild guess (Sect. 3) this combination seems, at first glance, to allow for (PDO) as well as for (CTRL). However, to get (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)), D’s value must be allowed to vary when conditionalizing on D’s past (including \(P_0\)). But once we conditionalize on any \(P_0\)-value, we get an extreme probability distribution over \(P_1\) due to (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)), which gives us, in turn, an extreme probability distribution over D due to (\({\mathbf{SUP}}_{{BN}}\)). Hence, the actualist possibility to do otherwise is excluded if non-reductive physicalism and determinism are true.
Here is an argument that shows that also (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)) is excluded if non-reductive physicalism and determinism are true:Footnote 15 According to (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)), for every \(P_1\)-value \(p_1\) there is a \(P_2\)-value \(p_2\) such that \(P(p_2|p_1)=1\) holds, while \(P(p_2'|p_1)=0\) holds for all other \(P_2\) -values \(p_2'\). Now there are two possible cases for every D-value d: Either (i) d and \(p_1\) are compatible (i.e., \(P(d,p_1)>0\)), or (ii) they are not (i.e., \(P(d,p_1)=0\)). If (i), then \(P(p_2|d,p_1)=1\) and \(P(p_2'|d,p_1)=0\) hold because conditionalizing on compatible values of additional variables does not change conditional probabilities of 1 or 0. Hence, no \(P_2\)-value will depend on d given \(p_1\). If (ii), then \(P(d,p_1)=0\). In this case, no \(P_2\)-value will depend on d conditional on \(p_1\) by definition. Since d was arbitrarily chosen and also \(p_1\) was arbitrarily chosen, it follows that \(P_2\) is probabilistically independent of D conditional on \(Par(P_2)\backslash \{D\}=\{P_1\}\). But this just means that the arrow \(D\longrightarrow P_2\) is not productive, i.e., that D cannot have any causal impact on \(P_2\) whatsoever, which contradicts (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)).
Non-reductive Physicalism Plus Indeterminism Does non-reductive physicalism combined with indeterminism fare better when it comes to the question of free will? Since neither the agential nor the fundamental physical level are assumed to be deterministic, an agent could be able to do otherwise in this view. According to (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)), everything required for this is that D is not fully determined by its past. This actually turns out to be true in our model. Even if one conditionalizes on \(P_0\), nothing excludes that the conditional probabilities \(P(d|p_0)\) are non-extreme. If the probability distribution of our model (Fig. 1) would, for example, be specified as follows, (\({\mathbf{ONI}}_{{BN}}\)), (\({\mathbf{SUP}}_{{BN}}\)), (\({\mathbf{CE}}_{{BN}}\)), (\({\mathbf{IND}}_{{BN}}\)), and (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)) would be satisfied and \(0<P(d|p_0)<1\) would hold for arbitrarily chosen D- and \(P_0\)-values d and \(p_0\), respectively:
$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lll} P(P_0=0)=0.5 &{} P(P_1=0|P_0=0)=0.75 &{} P(P_2=0|D=0,P_1=0)=0.75 \\ P(P_0=1)=0.5 &{} P(P_1=1|P_0=0)=0.25 &{} P(P_2=1|D=0,P_1=0)=0.25 \\ &{} P(P_1=0|P_0=1)=0.25 &{} P(P_2=0|D=0,P_1=1)=0.5 \\ &{} P(P_1=1|P_0=1)=0.75 &{} P(P_2=1|D=0,P_1=1)=0.5 \\ &{} P(D=0|P_1=0)=1 &{} P(P_2=0|D=1,P_1=0)=0.5 \\ &{} P(D=1|P_1=0)=0 &{} P(P_2=1|D=1,P_1=0)=0.5 \\ &{} P(D=0|P_1=1)=0 &{} P(P_2=0|D=1,P_1=1)=0.25 \\ &{} P(D=1|P_1=1)=1 &{} P(P_2=1|D=1,P_1=1)=0.75 \\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
Unfortunately, there are, again, problems with (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)) and D’s probabilistic causal impact on \(P_2\): Because of (\({\mathbf{SUP}}_{{BN}}\)) for every \(P_1\)-value \(p_1\) there is a D-value d such that \(P(d|p_1)=1\) and \(P(d'|p_1)=0\) for all other D-values \(d'\). This time there are two possible cases for every \(P_2\)-value \(p_2\): Either (i) \(p_2\) and \(p_1\) are compatible, or (ii) they are not. If (i), then \(P(d|p_2,p_1)=P(d|p_1)=1\) and \(P(d'|p_2,p_1)=P(d'|p_1)=0\). Thus, no D-value depends on \(p_2\) conditional on \(p_1\). If (ii), then no D-value depends on \(p_2\) conditional on \(p_1\) by definition. This result generalizes: Because \(p_2\) and \(p_1\) were arbitrarily chosen, D and \(P_2\) are independent given \(Par(P_2)\backslash \{D\}=\{P_1\}\). This means, again, that D cannot have any probabilistic causal impact on \(P_2\) and that one of the requirements for a strong notion of free will we are interested in in this paper is excluded.
Reductive Physicalism Plus Determinism According to this view, D has to be identified with \(P_1\) (see Fig. 2). Nothing we have assumed excludes that \(P_2\) probabilistically depends on D conditional on \(Par(P_2)\backslash \{D\}\), which is the empty set if reductionism is true. Hence, (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)) can be satisfied and an agent’s decisions might have probabilistic causal impact. The following distribution, for example, would allow for (\({\mathbf{RED}}_{{BN}}\)), (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)), and (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)) to be satisfied:
$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lll} P(P_0=0)=0.5 &{} P(P_1=0|P_0=0)=1 &{} P(P_2=0|P_1=0)=1 \\ P(P_0=1)=0.5 &{} P(P_1=1|P_0=0)=0 &{} P(P_2=1|P_1=0)=0 \\ &{} P(P_1=0|P_0=1)=0 &{} P(P_2=0|P_1=1)=0 \\ &{} P(P_1=1|P_0=1)=1 &{} P(P_2=1|P_1=1)=1 \\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
The problem for free will if reductionism plus determinism is true is (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)) which requires that D’s value is not fully determined by the past, i.e., by \(P_0\). But this is logically excluded by (\({\mathbf{DET}}_{{BN}}\)). This result does not suit strong incompatibilists or libertarians, but it suits strong compatibilists or soft determinists.
Reductive Physicalism Plus Indeterminism Here comes the last one of the possible combinations to be explored. This view is the only one of the four combinations of positions discussed in this paper that actually can account for libertarian free will committed to the possibility to do otherwise as well as the probabilistic causal efficacy of an agent’s wilful decisions. (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)) can be satisfied because (\({\mathbf{IND}}_{{BN}}\)) allows for non-extreme conditional probabilities \(P(p_1|p_2)\), and (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)) can be satisfied simply because nothing excludes a dependence of \(P_2\) on \(P_1\) in the second model (see Fig. 2). This can be demonstrated by the following probability distribution which allows for (\({\mathbf{RED}}_{{BN}}\)), (\({\mathbf{IND}}_{{BN}}\)), and (\({\mathbf{PDO}}_{{BN}}\)) as well as for (\({\mathbf{CTRL}}_{{BN}}\)) to be satisfied:
$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lll} P(P_0=0)=0.5 &{} P(P_1=0|P_0=0)=0.75 &{} P(P_2=0|P_1=0)=0.75 \\ P(P_0=1)=0.5 &{} P(P_1=1|P_0=0)=0.25 &{} P(P_2=1|P_1=0)=0.25 \\ &{} P(P_1=0|P_0=1)=0.25 &{} P(P_2=0|P_1=1)=0.25 \\ &{} P(P_1=1|P_0=1)=0.75 &{} P(P_2=1|P_1=1)=1.75 \\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
Summarizing, it turned out that three of the four possible combinations of the positions discussed exclude a notion of free will committed to both (PDO) and (CTRL). Both versions of non-reductive physicalism, the deterministic as well as the indeterministic one, exclude an agent’s ability to control her environment (CTRL). (PDO), on the other hand, is only excluded in the deterministic setting. So in the end, given non-reductive physicalism were true, only indeterminism does not exclude one of the requirements for free will discussed, viz. (PDO). If reductionism were true, on the other hand, (CTRL) is always satisfiable, while (PDO) is only satisfiable in the indeterministic setting and excluded in the deterministic setting. The following table summarizes these results:
| Determinism | Indeterminism |
---|
Non-reductive physicalism | \(\times \) | (PDO) |
Reductive physicalism | (CTRL) | (PDO) + (CTRL) |