Skip to main content
Log in

Exclusion Criteria in Experimental Philosophy

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When experimental philosophers carry out studies on thought experiments, some participants are excluded based on certain exclusion criteria, mirroring standard social science vignette methodology. This involves excluding people that do not pay attention or who miscomprehend the scenario presented in thought experiments. However, experimental philosophy studies sometimes exclude an alarmingly high number of participants. We argue that this threatens the external and internal validity of the conclusions being drawn and we show how a simple visualization of thought experiments can reduce exclusion rates significantly. Furthermore, we argue that focus should not merely be on how many are excluded, but also why they are excluded, and we highlight the role of comprehension questions in this regard. Philosophical thought experiments often rely on the acceptance of certain key premises that may be regarded contestable, and asking comprehension questions involving such key assumptions could be problematic as that may result in some participants being inadvertently excluded from the study, potentially creating a selection bias.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Interestingly Starmans and Friedman (2012) point out that their results are qualitatively the same regardless of whether they include or exclude those subjects having failed comprehension questions. Philosophers cannot however ignore comprehension questions simply on those grounds. For studies including thought experiments to be methodologically sound, comprehension questions must be included, but the observation made by Starmans et al. suggests that we need to look further into the role of comprehension questions and how they are posed. Who do they exclude and why?

  2. An obvious reason for this high number is that the study is carried out in subcontinent India and subjects are reading a case presented in English while selfreporting different levels of language skills.

  3. A simple calculation shows that in a small sample (N < 25) even a 30% failure rate would be statistically indistinguishable from a random answer to a binary question, assuming a 0.05 p value cut-off.

  4. Turri (2013) is arguably doing something to this effect by way of structuring thought experiment presentation so as to help people better understand the structure of the situation presented, but his focus is not to improve comprehension rates.

  5. We should also add that by replicating Colaço et al. (2014), we do not thereby endorse what may be characterised as an instance of ‘negative’ experimental philosophy (branch of experimental philosophy on a quest to eradicate any assumed reliance on intuitive judgments)—even if Colaço et al. so qualifies. Our project is merely to contribute to the continued improvement of the methodology of experimental philosophy and (here, at least) we take no stance on whether experimental philosophy should be positive or negative in nature.

  6. All reported results are unchanged when including respondents with a philosophy degree or excluding respondents report to they have heard about the Gettier problem before.

  7. We chose to rely on several comprehension questions (and an attention check). Another approach to ensure actual comprehension is to require different types of answers, e.g. both negative and positive answers, making it less likely that people pass a test by chance.

  8. 73 participants are over 50 years of age and the result is thus not driven by relatively few old participants. We also note that none of the 18 participants aged 60 or above failed the comprehension test.

  9. We thank an anonymous reviewer for this observation.

References

  • Alexander, C. S., & Becker, H. J. (1978). The use of vignettes in survey research. Public Opinion Quarterly, 42, 93–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W. (2013). Gettier made ESEE. Philosophical Psychology, 27(3), 368–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1966). Theory of knowledge. N.J.: Englewood Cliffs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, C. J., Winegard, B. M., & Baumeister, R. F. (2019). Forget the folk: Moral responsibility preservation motives and other conditions for compatibilism. Frontiers in Psychology, 10, 215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M. (1999). 101 philosophy problems. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colaço, D., Buckwalter, W., Stich, S., & Machery, E. (2014). Epistemic intuitions in fake-barn thought experiments. Episteme, 11(02), 199–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, K., Otto, R., Desmarais, S., & Borum, R. (2001). Clinical forensic psychology. In I. B. Weiner, J. A. Schinka, & W. F. Velicer (Eds.), Handbook of psychology, research methods in psychology. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S. (2005). Cognitive reflection and decision making. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19(4), 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J. (2010). How (not) to react to experimental philosophy. Philosophical Psychology, 23, 447–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary didn’t know. Journal of Philosophy, 83(5), 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, M., & Yuan, Y. (2014). No cross-cultural differences in the Gettier car case intuition: A replication study. Episteme, 12(3), 355–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, R. A., Vianello, M., Hasselman, F., Adams, B. G., Adams, R. B., Jr., Alper, S., et al. (2018). Many Labs 2: Investigating variation in replicability across samples and settings. Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science, 1, 443–490. https://doi.org/10.1177/2515245918810225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, W. H., & Lentz, R. (1982). Effects of text illustrations: A review of research. Educational Communication and Technology Journal, 30(4), 195–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Little, R. J. A., & Rubin, D. B. (2014). Statistical analysis with missing data. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., Struchiner, N., et al. (2015). Gettier across cultures. Noûs, 51(3), 645–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maniaci, M., & Rogge, R. (2014). Caring about carelessness: Participant inattention and its effects on research. Journal of Research in Personality, 48(1), 61–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meade, A. W., & Craig, S. B. (2012). Identifying careless responses in survey data. Psychological Methods, 17, 437–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, D., & Nahmias, E. (2014). Explaining away incompatibilist intuitions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 434–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., Coates, D. J., & Kvaran, T. (2007). Free will, moral responsibility, and mechanism: Experiments on folk intuitions. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31(1), 214–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (2005). Surveying freedom: Folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Philosophical Psychology, 18(5), 561–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Bruno, M. (2010). Intuitions about personal identity: An empirical study. Philosophical Psychology, 23, 293–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous, 41, 663–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheimer, D., Meyvis, T., & Davidenko, N. (2009). Instructional manipulation checks: Detecting satisficing to increase statistical power. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45(4), 867–872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paolacci, G., Chandler, J., & Ipeirotis, P. G. (2010). Running experiments on Amazon Mechanical Turk. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 411–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Philips, J. & Cushman, F. (2017) Replication of Nahmias, Coates, & Kavarn (2007) Free will, moral responsibility, and mechanism: Experiments on folk intuitions. https://osf.io/n4573/.

  • Polonioli, A., Vega-Mendoza, M., Blankinship, B., & Carmel, D. (2018). Reporting in experimental philosophy: Current standards and recommendations for future practice. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0414-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(3), 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyedsayamdost, H. (2015). On normativity and epistemic intuitions: Failure of replication. Episteme, 12(1), 95–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (1992). Thought experiments. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2009). A defense of the use of intuitions in philosophy. In M. Bishop & D. Murphy (Eds.), Stich and his critics (pp. 101–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starmans, C., & Friedman, O. (2012). The folk conception of knowledge. Cognition, 124, 272–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, K., & Clifford, S. (2017). Validity and Mechanical Turk: An assessment of exclusion methods and interactive experiments. Computers in Human Behavior, 77, 184–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2013). A conspicuous art: Putting Gettier to the test. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • van’t Veer, A. E., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2016). Pre-registration in social psychology discussion and suggested template. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 67, 2–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical topics, 49(1&2), 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1973). Problems of the self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2011). Philosophical expertise and the burden of proof. Metaphilosophy, 42, 215–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank Vilius Dranseika, Oana Vuculescu and two anonymous reviewers for valuable comments and suggestions. Research for this publication was supported by grants from the Carlsberg Foundation (CF15-0943) and the Independent Research Fund Denmark (DFF-4180-00071).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jacob Busch.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bergenholtz, C., Busch, J. & Praëm, S.K. Exclusion Criteria in Experimental Philosophy. Erkenn 86, 1531–1545 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00168-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00168-5

Navigation