Skip to main content
Log in

Why Explanatory Considerations Matter

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper aims at elucidating the connection between explanatory considerations and epistemic justification stipulated by explanationism which take epistemic justification to be definable in terms of best explanations. By relying on the notion of truthlikeness, this paper argues that it is rational for a subject to expect the best explanation she has for her evidence to be more truthlike than any of the other potential explanations available to her by virtue of containing a class of propositions that, given her evidence, she is justified in believing. Based on this elucidation of the connection between explanatory considerations and epistemic justification, an explanationist account of the evidential support relation is then offered.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is common to distinguish propositional justification from doxastic justification. Propositional justification requires only that the content of a subject’s beliefs be supported by the evidence she has at a certain time. Doxastic justification, in contrast, requires that, in addition to that support, her beliefs be properly based on the evidence she has. This paper’s primary focus is propositional justification.

  2. A first version of McCain’s (2013, 2014) account of the evidential support relation was challenged by two varieties of cases due to Byerly (2013) and Byerly and Martin (2014). To accommodate these cases, McCain (2015) offered an amended version of his account. Byerly and Martin (2016) then raised further objections against McCain’s second account to which he (2017) recently reacted.

  3. Regarding the role of abductive inferences in scientific contexts, see McMullin (1992) and Lipton (2004). Regarding the role of such inferences in everyday contexts see Harman (1965) and Adler (1994).

  4. See Lombrozo and Carey (2006), Douven and Verbrugge (2010) and Lombrozo and Gwynne (2014).

  5. e represents S’s overall evidence at t.

  6. Note that, irrespective of cases such as the Animal Case, conceiving explanations as theories is also a quite natural way to delimitate their semantical content. If an explanation states that \( p_{i} \) is true and states that This case represents a problem for Explanationism\( p_{j} \) is true, then it is quite natural to consider that it also states that \( p_{i} \wedge p_{j} \) is true.

  7. According to Hempel (1965), explanations consist of deductive (or inductive) arguments in which the explained event is derived from certain laws and initial conditions. Kitcher (1989) and Friedman (1974) before him, while preserving Hempel’s initial idea, conceive explanations as patterns of derivations of different events which provide a unifying systemization of initially dissimilar phenomena. Salmon (1984), on the other hand, abandons the Hempelian conception of explanations as arguments and takes explaining to be fundamentally a matter of showing how the explained event fits into the causal patterns found in the world. Alternative causal models of explanations have been proposed by Woodward (2003) and Strevens (2008).

  8. This hypothesis has been defended by Lipton (2003, 2004) with respect to abductive inferences. According to him, the potential ability of an explanation to provide an understanding of why e is a good guide to estimate its probability conditional on e.

  9. Elsewhere, I (Belkoniene 2017) consider another possible answer suggested by McCain and Poston (2014). I provide other reasons to consider that this answer is also unsatisfying.

  10. Kuipers (2004) and Niiniluoto (2004, 2005) both worked on the relation between theories’ expected degree of truthlikeness and abductive inferences in order to formulate rules of abductive inference that conform to our intuitions regarding the ways subjects should revise their beliefs. The rule formulated by Kuipers prescribes one to infer that the best explanation available to a subject is more truthlike than any other potential explanation available to this subject and relies, therefore, on the same plausible connection that I just stressed between explanatory considerations and the relative truthlikeness of potential explanations.

  11. The present paper focuses exclusively on definitions of comparative truthlikeness and not on definitions of quantitative truthlikeness and measures of expected quantitative truthlikeness that have been offered, inter alia, by Niiniluoto (2011) and Cevolani and Schurz (2017). The reason for this focus is that the truthlikeness hypothesis relies on a comparative notion of truthlikeness and, therefore, to see how this hypothesis can help to answer the main question that this paper aims at addressing, a definition of comparative truthlikeness is required.

  12. This result is due to the fact that if the falsity-content of a theory \( {\text{H}} \) is not empty, \( {\text{H}} \)’s truth-content cannot be increased without thereby increasing its falsity-content. By adding a true proposition \( p_{i} \) to \( {\text{C}}\left( {\text{H}} \right) \) one, thereby, adds a false proposition \( p_{i} \wedge p_{j} \) to \( {\text{C}}\left( {\text{H}} \right) \) where \( p_{j} \) is a false consequence of \( {\text{H}} \) already contained in \( {\text{C}}\left( {\text{H}} \right) \).

  13. See Mott (1978), Burger and Heidema (1994), Gemes (2007), Schurz and Weingartner (1987, 2010) and Cevolani et al. (2013) for definitions of a theory’s truthlikeness based on this observation.

  14. Schurz and Weingartner (2010, pp. 425–426) propose as conventions to write all members \( {\text{E}}\left( {\text{H}} \right) \) in their negation normal form—namely by writing them only with the logical operators “\( \wedge , \vee , \neg \)”, by putting all negations in front of propositional variables and by eliminating all double negations and associative brackets—and that all disjunctions of literals (propositional variables or their negation) in \( {\text{E}}\left( {\text{H}} \right) \) be written as clauses—that is, as disjunctions of literals in distinct and alphabetically ordered propositional variables.

  15. Note that, according to this definition, a proposition \( p \) such that \( p \) \( \in {\text{C}}\left( {\text{H}} \right) \) can be an elementary consequence of \( {\text{H}} \) without being a relevant consequence of \( {\text{H}} \). Likewise, \( p \) can be a relevant consequence of \( {\text{H}} \) without being an elementary consequence of \( {\text{H}} \).

  16. SW-Truthlikeness is formulated in terms of entailments of classes of relevant elements instead of inclusions because classes of relevant elements are not themselves closed under logical consequence.

  17. To say that \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{i} } \right)_{T} \) exceeds \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{j} } \right)_{T} \) means that some members of \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{i} } \right)_{T} \) are not deducible from \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{j} } \right)_{T} \) but that all members of \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{j} } \right)_{T} \) are deducible from \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{i} } \right)_{T} \). Thus, \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{i} } \right)_{T} \) exceeds \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{j} } \right)_{T} \) just in case all true relevant elements of \( {\text{H}}_{j} \) are part of \( {\text{H}}_{i} \)’s semantic content but some of \( {\text{H}}_{i} \)’s true relevant elements are not part of \( {\text{H}}_{j} \)’s semantic content. The same holds for \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{i} } \right)_{F} \) and \( {\text{E}}\left( {{\text{H}}_{j} } \right)_{F} \).

  18. As a theory’s class of relevant elements represents its entire semantic content, condition (ii) guarantees that \( p \) is part of \( {\text{H}}_{i} \)’s semantic content but is not part of the semantic content of at least one other potential explanation of e available to S at t.

  19. Byerly and Martin (2014, p. 783) offer a case in which, according to McCain’s account of the evidential support relation which is equivalent to the version of Explanationism considered in Sect. 2, a subject is justified in believing that \( p \) while \( p \) is not probable conditional on her overall evidence. Based on this case, they argue that McCain’s account is too permissive as, intuitively, the subject involved in that case is not justified in believing that \( p \). See Belkoniene (2017) for a more detailed discussion of that case.

  20. The first case offered by Gettier involves the formation of a lucky true belief concerning an existential proposition that is inferred from a non-quantified proposition. While Schurz and Weingartner’s definition of a theory’s relevant consequences’ class does not deal with quantified propositions, Gemes’s definition, for instance, which is developed for higher-order logics, typically excludes such consequences from the class of \( {\text{H}} \)’s relevant consequences.

References

  • Adler, J. (1994). Testimony, trust, knowing. Journal of Philosophy, 91, 264–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belkoniene, M. (2017). What are explanatory virtues indicative of? Logos and Episteme, 8, 179–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burger, I. C., & Heidema, J. (1994). Comparing theories by their positive and negative contents. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45, 605–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byerly, R. (2013). Explanationism and justified beliefs about the future. Erkenntnis, 78, 229–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byerly, R., & Martin, K. (2014). Problems for explanationism on both sides. Erkenntnis, 80, 773–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byerly, R., & Martin, K. (2016). Explanationism, super-explanationism, ecclectic explanationism: Persistent problems on both sides. Logos & Episteme, 7, 201–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G. (2013). Truth approximation via abductive belief change. Logic Journal of IGPL, 21, 999–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G., Festa, R., & Kuipers, T. (2013). Verisimilitude and belief change for nomic conjunctive theories. Synthese, 190, 3307–3324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G., & Schurz, G. (2017). Probability, approximate truth, and truthlikeness: More ways out of the preface paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95, 209–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2008). Evidence. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays (pp. 83–104). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Schupbach, J. (2015). Probabilistic alternatives to Bayesianism: The case of explanationism. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Verbrugge, S. (2010). The adams family. Cognition, 117, 302–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, К. (2007). Verisimilitude and Content. Synthese, 154, 293–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2011). Toward a synthesis of reliabilism and evidentialism? Or: Evidentialism’s troubles, reliabilism’s rescue package. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 254–280). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. (2004). Inference to the best theory, rather than inference to the best explanation—Kinds of abduction and induction. In F. Stadler (Ed.), Induction and deduction in the sciences (pp. 25–51). Dordrecht: Springer Science.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2003). Is explanation a guide to inference? A reply to Wesley Salmon. In G. Hon & S. Rakover (Eds.), Explanation: Theoretical approaches and applications (pp. 93–120). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T., & Carey, S. (2006). Functional explanation and the function of explanation. Cognition, 99, 167–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T., & Gwynne, N. (2014). Explanation and inference: Mechanical and functional explanations guide property generalization. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2013). Explanationist evidentialism. Episteme, 10, 299–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2014). Evidentialism and epistemic justification. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2015). Explanationism: Defended on all sides. Logos & Episteme, 6, 61–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2017). Undaunted explanationism. Logos & Episteme, 8, 117–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K., & Poston, T. (2014). Why explanatoriness is evidentially relevant. Thought, 3, 145–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1992). The inference that makes science. Zygon, 48, 143–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1974). Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 166–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mott, P. (1978). Verisimilitude by means of short theorems. Synthese, 38, 247–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2004). Truth-seeking by abduction. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, 11, 57–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2005). Abduction and truthlikeness. In R. Festa, A. Aliseda, & J. Peijnenburg (Eds.), Confirmation, empirical progress, and truth approximation: Essays in debate with Theo Kuipers (pp. 255–275). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2011). The development of the Hintikka Program. In D. M. Gabbay, J. Woods, & S. Hartmann (Eds.), Handbook of the history of logic: Inductive logic (pp. 311–356). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Weingartner, P. (1987). Verisimilitude defined by relevant consequence-elements. In T. A. Kuipers (Ed.), What is closer-to-the-truth? (pp. 47–78). Amsterdam: Rodopl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Weingartner, P. (2010). Zwart and Franssen’s impossibility theorem holds for possible-world-accounts but not for consequence-accounts to verisimilitude. Synthese, 172, 415–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tichý, P. (1974). On popper’s definitions of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 155–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks are due to Professors Gianfranco Soldati, Fabian Dorsch (1974–2017), Lara Buchak and two anonymous referees from this journal for their insightful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. This publication was made possible through the support of a grant from the Swiss National Science Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miloud Belkoniene.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Belkoniene, M. Why Explanatory Considerations Matter. Erkenn 86, 473–491 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00114-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00114-5

Navigation