Skip to main content
Log in

How Science and Semantics Settle the Issue of Natural Kind Essentialism

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Standard arguments for essentialism with respect to natural kinds such as gold, star, water or tiger enlist essentialist principles or essentialist intuitions. I argue that we need neither. All it takes to establish essentialism for the kinds in question are insights from science and semantics. Semantics establishes that natural kind predicates such as “is gold” or “is a star” are paradigm terms whose application conditions are relationally determined, object involving, and actuality dependent. Science assures us that a posteriori hypotheses such as “∀x(x is gold ↔ x is Au)” are deeply explanatory, as well as true. Taken together, these results establish essentialism for kinds such as gold, star, water or tiger. I consider this a deflationary result. When it comes to natural kind essentialism, there is no need for substantial metaphysics, be it essentialist or otherwise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. With Soames (2002, p. 255ff), I accept biconditionals like this as theoretical identifications. See Kripke (1980, p. 116, 138).

  2. Strictly speaking, paradigm terms form a meta-semantic category. See Nimtz (2018), esp. §3. Nothing hinges on this here. So I simplify this to “semantics” throughout.

  3. Features that are usually considered as distinctive of natural kind terms are commonly shared by paradigm terms in general. See Nimtz (2017) for details.

  4. I understand an intension to be a function from worlds to extensions.

  5. See e.g. Beebee and Sabbarton-Leary (2010), Bird and Tobin (2017), Roca-Royes (2011), Robertson and Atkins (2016), Ereshefsky (2010), Mackie (2006). More narrow versions build further requirements into the concept—“traditional essentialism” (Ereshefsky 2010, p. 675, Fn.1) requires essential properties to be intrinsic, and “scientific essentialism” (Slater and Borghini 2011, p. 14) requires essential properties to be dispositional. These are of no concern to us.

  6. I abbreviate this to “is an lsf object”. See Angelo (2006) and Schulz (2007).

  7. pt” abbreviates a proper specification of the relevant clade, which LaPorte describes as “the lineage descending from population P and terminating in speciation or extinction” (2004, p. 61). See Davis et al. (2010) for details.

  8. See McLeod (2005, p. 236, Fn.4) for further references.

  9. I ignore subsequent changes in the meter convention.

  10. I assume throughout that R is an equivalence relation. This is a simplification. A paradigm term might well enlist a relation such as, say, has double the length as.

  11. That a bears the equivalence relation R to b trivially guarantees that a and b share the property of bearing R to a. I do not accept such trivializing instances as realizers for R. – Maybe you think that R holds because its relata share a determinate property. I merely commit to the iff-claim made in REL.

  12. As Salmon (2005, p. 166) reports, Donnellan also stresses the “doubly exotic” nature of this venture.

  13. I class two-dimensionalists such as Jackson (1998, pp. 46–52) as upholding a Kripke-Putnam view. So do Häggqvist and Wikforss (2018).

  14. See Nimtz (2017, pp. 3–5) for a closer look at Putnam and Kripke. See Koslicki (2008, p. 797) for a summary of the Putnam-Kripke view that portrays natural kind terms as paradigm terms in my sense.

  15. See Nimtz (2017, pp. 5–7) and Nimtz (2018, §3), where I use paradigm term semantics to account for additional characteristics of natural kind terms.

  16. I generally use “paradigmatic F” in this sense.

  17. The explanatory range required varies with the scientific context. It may spell out as almost all, a weighted majority of, or simply a sufficient selection from.

  18. Let us agree that pivotal explanatory properties foremost aim to explain why paradigmatic (rather than all) instances exhibit those characteristics the respective science (rather than other sciences, or common sense) deem crucial. Then (3*) and (4*) become more tractable. Assume that paradigmatic samples of water are puddle-sized portions under normal environmental conditions. The key chemical characteristics of such samples under such conditions can be traced back to the traits of H2O-molecules and the (notably: bonding) behavior they show when in close proximity. This makes being H2O the pivotal explanatory property for water, even though non-paradigmatic portions conspicuously lack many of these explananda. See for discussion Hendry (2006), Needham (2011), Hendry (2010), Schulte (2018). See Stanford and Kitcher (2000, p. 112f) for basically the same argument. As for “is a tiger”, within current biology, there is no consensus on which properties of paradigmatic tigers a pivotal explanatory property needs to account for. If we assume this settled, say in favor of a cladistics approach aiming to account for evolutionary dynamics, arguing that (4*) is a deeply explanatory hypothesis becomes much easier.

  19. Compare Nimtz (2017, pp. 10–13), where I use a similar argument to a different end.

  20. See Burgess (2014) for details and clarifications.

References

  • Angelo, J. (2006). Encyclopedia of space and astronomy. New York: Facts on File.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H., & Sabbarton-Leary, N. (Eds.). (2010). The semantics and metaphysics of natural kinds. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2009). Essences and natural kinds. In R. Le Poidevin (Ed.), The Routledge companion to metaphysics (pp. 497–506). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2010). Discovering the essences of natural kinds. Beebee/Sabbarton-Leary, 2010, 125–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2012). Referring to natural kind thingamajigs, and what they are: A reply to Needham. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26(1), 103–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2018). The metaphysics of natural kinds. Synthèse, 195(4), 1397–1426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A., & Tobin, E. (2017). Natural kinds. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/natural-kinds/. Accessed 1 Dec 2018.

  • Burgess, J. P. (2014). On a derivation of the necessity of identity. Synthèse, 191(7), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corrigan, D. (2005). Gold. In G. D. Considine (Ed.), Van Nostrand’s Encyclopedia of Chemistry (pp. 735–737). Hoboken (NJ): Wiley-Interscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, B. W., Li, G., & Murphy, W. J. (2010). Supermatrix and species tree methods resolve phylogenetic relationships within the big cats, Panthera (Carnivora: Felidae). Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, 56(1), 64–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75(3), 344–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. L. (2004). Real natures and familiar objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2010). What’s wrong with the new biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 77(5), 674–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gimeno, M. C. (2008). The chemistry of gold. In A. Laguna (Ed.), Modern supramolecular gold chemistry: Gold–Metal interactions and applications (pp. 1–63). Weinheim: Wiley-VCH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häggqvist, S., & Wikforss, Å. (2018). Natural kinds and natural kind terms: Myth and reality. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(4), 911–933. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axw041.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (2003). Knowledge of possibility and of necessity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (2013). Necessary beings: An essay on ontology, modality, and the relations between them. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haukioja, J. (2015). On deriving essentialism from the theory of reference. Philosophical Studies, 172(8), 2141–2151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K., & Bird, A. (2011). What are natural kinds? Philosophical Perspectives, 25(1), 205–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, R. F. (2006). Elements, compounds and other chemical kinds. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 864–875.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, R. F. (2010). The elements and conceptual change. Beebee/Sabbarton-Leary, 2010, 137–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hussong, M., et al. (2015). Copper and silver carbene complexes without heteroatom-stabilization: Structure, spectroscopy, and relativistic effects. Angewandte Chemie International Edition, 54, 10331–10335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, B. F. G., & Davis, R. (1973). Gold. In J. C. Bailar, et al. (Eds.), Comprehensive inorganic chemistry (pp. 132–186). Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2008). Natural kinds and natural kind terms. Philosophy Compass, 3(4), 789–802.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1971). Identity and necessity. In M. Munitz (Ed.), Identity and individuation (pp. 135–164). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (2013). Reference and existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte, J. (2004). Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, S. (2016). Natural kinds of substance. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(2), 283–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2007). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2011). The rationality of metaphysics. Synthèse, 178(1), 99–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, P. (2006). How things might have been: A study in essentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2012). Scientific enquiry and natural kinds: From planets to mallards. Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2018). Taxonomy, ontology, and natural kinds. Synthèse, 195(4), 1427–1439.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLeod, S. (2005). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Books, 46(3), 235–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1874). A system of logic ratiocinative and inductive part II. In J. M. Robson (Ed.), The collected works of John Stuart Mill (Vol. 8). Toronto: University of Toronto Press 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • Needham, P. (2011). Microessentialism: What is the argument? Noûs, 45(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Needham, P. (2012). Natural kind thingamajigs. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26(1), 97–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nimtz, C. (2017). Paradigm terms: The necessity of kind identifications generalized. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(1), 124–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nimtz, C. (2018). Kripkean meta-semantics and generalised rigidity. Forthcoming in Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqy059.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthèse, 131(2), 191–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language, and reality. Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renner, H., & Johns, M. (2000). Gold, gold alloys, and gold compounds. Ullmann’s Encyclopedia of Industrial Chemistry, A12, 499–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, T., & Atkins, P. (2016). Essential vs. accidental properties. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/essential-accidental/. Accessed 1 Dec 2018.

  • Roca-Royes, S. (2011). Essential properties and individual essences. Philosophy Compass, 6(1), 65–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruphy, S. (2010). Are stellar kinds natural kinds? A challenging newcomer in the monism/pluralism and realism/antirealism debates. Philosophy of Science, 77(5), 1109–1120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (2005). Reference and essence (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulte, P. (2018). Why mental content is not like water: Reconsidering the reductive claims of teleosemantics. Synthèse, 9, 99. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1808-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, N. S. (2007). From dust to stars. Studies of the formation and early evolution of stars. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siekierski, S., & Burgess, J. (2002). Concise chemistry of the elements. Philadelphia: Woodhead Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. H., & Borghini, A. (2013). Introduction: Lessons from the scientific butchery. In J. K. Campbell, M. O'Rourke, & M. H. Slater (Eds.), Carving nature at its joints (pp. 1–31). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity: The unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K., & Kitcher, P. (2000). Refining the causal theory of reference for natural kind terms. Philosophical Studies, 97(1), 97–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, T. E. (2015). Natural Kind essentialism revisited. Mind, 124(495), 795–822.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Tim Henning, Peter Schulte, Steven Kindley, Fabian Hundertmark, Martin Korth and audiences at Bielefeld, Tampere and Edinburgh for discussions of earlier versions of this paper. I am particularly indebted to two anonymous referees for Erkenntnis whose comments allowed me to substantially improve the argument.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Nimtz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nimtz, C. How Science and Semantics Settle the Issue of Natural Kind Essentialism. Erkenn 86, 149–170 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0098-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0098-1

Navigation