Skip to main content
Log in

An Automatic Ockham’s Razor for Bayesians?

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is sometimes claimed that the Bayesian framework automatically implements Ockham’s razor—that conditionalizing on data consistent with both a simple theory and a complex theory more or less inevitably favours the simpler theory. It is shown here that the automatic razor doesn’t in fact cut it for certain mundane curve-fitting problems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Rosenkrantz (1983, p. 82), Jefferys and Berger (1992), McKay (2003, ch. 28), White (2005), and Henderson et al. (2010, §4). It will be assumed throughout that Bayesian priors are probability measures—and in particular that they are both normalized and countably additive.

  2. For these cases, see, e.g., Henderson et al. (2010, §4) and Kelly and Glymour (2004, §4.4). For claims that the automatic razor should function beyond these special cases, see, e.g., Rosenkrantz (1983, p. 82) and White (2005, §3).

  3. Here and throughout, these theories are to be understood as being incompatible: a polynomial of degree k is required to have a non-zero coefficient for \(x^k.\)

  4. The basic phenomenon that drives the argument of Sect. 3 below arises whether we work with real or rational variables and polynomial coefficients: whatever probability a prior assigns to the linear polynomials, it assigns almost all of this probability to some bounded subset of the space of linear polynomials, and hence all but rules out linear polynomials of relatively large slope or with relatively large intercepts (thanks to an anonymous referee for this way of putting the point). The restriction to rational variables and coefficients allows the consequences of this phenomenon to be brought out in an especially stark fashion.

  5. For a related point made in a somewhat different context, see Seidenfeld (1979, pp. 414 f.).

  6. For a claim that something along these lines does in fact hold in contexts like ours, see Rosenkrantz (1983, p. 82).

  7. Bayesians might rather rely on a Pr-relative notion of typicality of data sets at this point. But such a notion is not easy to come by in our context, since Pr doesn’t assign probabilities to the proposition that the first data points are given by D or that the first values of x sampled are given by \(\Delta .\)

References

  • Henderson, L., Goodman, N., Tenenbaum, J., & Woodward, J. (2010). The structure and dynamics of scientific theories: A hierarchical Bayesian perspective. Philosophy of Science, 77, 172–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jefferys, W., & Berger, J. (1992). Ockham’s razor and Bayesian analysis. American Scientist, 80, 64–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, K., & Glymour, C. (2004). Why Bayesian confirmation does not capture the logic of scientific justification. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 94–114). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, D. (2003). Information theory, inference, and learning algorithms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenkrantz, R. (1983). Why Glymour is a Bayesian. In J. Earman (Ed.), Testing scientific theories (pp. 69–97). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidenfeld, T. (1979). Why I am not an objective Bayesian; some reflections prompted by Rosenkrantz. Theory and Decision, 11, 413–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2005). Why favour simplicity? Analysis, 65, 205–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This material was presented at the Ninth Workshop in Decisions, Games, and Logic at the University of Michigan and at the Workshop on Probability and Learning at Columbia University. For helpful comments and discussion, thanks to Kenny Easwaran, Jim Joyce, Laura Ruetsche, and three very helpful anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gordon Belot.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Belot, G. An Automatic Ockham’s Razor for Bayesians?. Erkenn 84, 1361–1367 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0011-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0011-y

Navigation