1 Introduction

The aim of this paper is to show that the problem of peer disagreement can be analyzed from a game-theoretic perspective. The problem of peer disagreement, as it is presented in the literature (e.g., Kelly 2005, 167; Christensen 2009, 756; Elga 2007, 478; Feldman 2007, 201), is how to respond rationally to the disagreement from an epistemic peer, whereby epistemic peer is construed as an agent who has the same evidence and is comparably good at evaluating that evidence (Kelly 2005, 170; Christensen 2007, 188; Feldman 2007, 201; Lackey 2008, 274). Game theory, in turn, is the study of strategic decision making, where ‘strategic’ means that the decision of one decision maker may interact with that of another. This paper explains how the latter can be used to analyze the former.

To do so, we focus on two prominent strategies recommended in the literature about peer disagreement, namely the response advocated by the Conciliatory View and the one suggested by the Steadfast View.Footnote 1 On the Conciliatory View, it can not be rational for an agent to stick to her opinion when it is disputed by an epistemic peer. Instead, she should suspend judgment (Feldman 2007), split the difference (Elga 2007), or at least migrate her opinion significantly in the direction of her peer’s conflicting opinion (Christensen 2007). In this paper we focus on full belief states rather than degrees of belief, so that the subtle differences between these ‘Conciliatory Views’ can be dispensed with. According to the Steadfast View, on the other hand, it can be rational for an agent to retain her opinion in the face of peer disagreement (Kelly 2005; van Inwagen 2010).

The game-theoretic toolkit enables us to analyze the rationality of these responses (strategies) for disagreeing peers (players), relative to these peers’ epistemic goals (preferences). In the literature on peer disagreement, the epistemic goal is commonly understood to be believing the correct truth-value of the proposition under discussion (Christensen 2007, 216; Feldman 2007, 212; Elga 2007, 488; Kelly 2010, 17; and, even if only indirectly, White 2005, 450). Thus, the rationality of the available responses—i.e., the Conciliatory strategy and the Steadfast strategy—can be analyzed by investigating to what extent they satisfy the preferences (epistemic goals) of the disagreeing peers. In Sect. 2 we argue that existing formal approaches do not address this particular question. In Sects. 3 and 4 we explain the details of our approach to the problem of peer disagreement. Section 5 discusses the results of this model, Sect. 6 considers some possible extensions or variations of the model, and Sect. 7 wraps up by emphasizing some key take-aways.

2 Why a Game-Theoretic Approach?

Why should a game-theoretic analysis be a relevant contribution to the debate about peer disagreement? Our motivation is that the resources of game theory enable a clarification of the responses to peer disagreement—in particular, of the Conciliatory View and the Steadfast View—along an independently motivated and well-developed standard. In the debate about peer disagreement, it is not always clear how exactly rationality is understood, what exactly counts as a peer, what a disagreement is, or even what exactly the Conciliatory View and the Steadfast View amount to (cf. Jehle and Fitelson 2009; Moss 2011; Lasonen-Aarnio 2013).

A formalization along the lines of game theory forces us to be precise about these notions. And the fruit of such explicitness is that it helps us to gain a better understanding of the conditions under which a particular strategy (like the ones suggested by the Conciliatory View and the Steadfast View) can be considered a rational response to the disagreement from a peer.

We do not want to suggest that our game-theoretic model is the only way to make the machinery under the problem of peer disagreement formally precise. Here we consider some previous work along these lines.

First it is important to distinguish quantitative and qualitative cases of peer disagreement. In the quantitative case the agents assign different degrees of belief to a proposition, whereas the qualitative case concerns full belief states (belief, disbelief, and suspension of judgment). Some have argued that the quantitative model of epistemic agents should be taken as basic and the qualitative model should be reduced to it (Lin and Kelly 2012; Leitgeb 2014). Others have argued the reverse (Easwaran forthcoming). This debate remains unresolved. As a result, we can treat quantitative and qualitative cases of peer disagreement as separate problems. Our focus in this paper is on the qualitative case. But as the majority of the work in formal epistemology that is potentially relevant to peer disagreement focuses on the quantitative case, we discuss this work first.

There are two dominant models in the literature on revising degrees of belief in light of new information (here, the information that an epistemic peer assigns different degrees of belief). One is the (iterated) linear pooling model developed by French (1956), DeGroot (1974) and Lehrer and Wagner (1981). In this model, the revised degrees of belief are obtained by taking a weighted average of the agents’ opinions. This is consistent with both the Steadfast View and the Conciliatory View. The Steadfast View says an agent can rationally give weight one to her own opinion and zero to her peer’s, whereas the Conciliatory View says this is not rationally permissible.Footnote 2

However, it is not clear what gives linear pooling its normative force. Without an interpretation of the weights used, “it is not clear why we should change our beliefs according to the weighted linear average, instead of, for instance, the weighted geometric average” (Martini et al. 2013, 887).

Romeijn (2015) attempts to give such an interpretation. He shows that if the agents’ priors take a particular form, linear pooling can be construed as a special case of Bayesian conditionalization (the other dominant model for revising degrees of belief), where the weights assigned to agents are identified with the truth-conduciveness of those agents. On this construal, linear pooling inherits the normative force that Bayesian conditionalization is generally taken to have, although particular assumptions need to be in place in order for linear pooling to be sanctioned by the Bayesian model.

Two problems remain. First, there appears to be no normative reason for the agents’ priors to take the required form. Second, it does not settle the debate between the Steadfast and the Conciliatory View, as the formalism itself does not settle whether an agent is rationally permitted to give weight one to her own opinion.

The first problem can be circumvented by allowing the agents to have any priors, taking Bayesian conditionalization as the normative model for revising degrees of belief without requiring that it agrees with linear pooling. Under certain assumptions, the agents can be guaranteed to reach a consensus in this model (Aumann 1976; Geanakoplos and Polemarchakis 1982). But the second problem remains.Footnote 3

It appears, then, that none of the extant work in formal epistemology yields a view on the quantitative case of peer disagreement, although a focused discussion of the relations between the models we discussed and peer disagreement may still yield valuable insight. While we offer no view on the quantitative case here, the model we present could relatively easily be adapted to it.

In addition to the problems mentioned above, linear pooling and Bayesian conditionalization offer no solution to the qualitative case of peer disagreement, which will be our focus from here on out. For the qualitative case there are again two dominant classes of relevant formal models. The first is known as belief revision, usually (but not necessarily) using the so-called AGM model (Alchourrón et al. 1985). This model has been applied to peer disagreement (Cevolani 2014; Elkin 2015). While these papers are interesting, they beg the question in favor of the Conciliatory View: they explore ways in which a Conciliatory response to peer disagreement affects an agent’s other beliefs.

A similar problem holds for the second class of models, those based on judgment aggregation. Regardless of whether one follows the dominant axiomatic approach (List and Pettit 2002; List 2013) or focuses more directly on the reliability of aggregation methods (Hartmann et al. 2010; Hartmann and Sprenger 2012), these models already assume that one has decided to form a consensus opinion. Again, the Steadfast View is ruled out by the formal setup without argument.

It is also worth noting that most models of judgment aggregation and voting theory more generally concentrate on the case of at least three agents, whereas we, following the peer disagreement literature, focus on the case of two agents. Most of the prominent aggregation methods rely on some variation of majority voting, which does not yield very interesting results in the case of two disagreeing agents. We briefly return to the case of more than two agents in Sect. 6.

The model of the present paper addresses the peer disagreement debate head on, as we give a direct comparison of the Conciliatory and the Steadfast View. While some previous work has aimed to make ideas from the peer disagreement literature formally precise (Jehle and Fitelson 2009; Cevolani 2014; Elkin 2015), we are not aware of any formal work that makes this kind of direct comparison.Footnote 4 Some of the work mentioned above could perhaps be adapted to make such a comparison, which we think would be very interesting. But in the remainder of this paper we aim to argue (1) that the specific game-theoretic model we provide captures one interesting way to make the ideas underlying the peer disagreement debate more precise, and (2) that the model is flexible enough that it can be straightforwardly adapted to capture other ways of making these ideas more precise.

3 The Peer Disagreement Game

We introduce our game-theoretic setup with the help of an informal example. Imagine two detectives, call them Jane (Marple) and Hercule (Poirot), who both have been asked to go to a crime scene to investigate whether \(\phi \), say, whether the butler is the culprit. We make the following three assumptions about the detectives. First, they have the same evidence at their disposal to investigate \(\phi \), namely whatever traces are left at the crime scene. Second, the detectives can make an informed estimation of how reliable each of them is in investigating \(\phi \), based on their respective track-records; the number of crimes they have solved in the past compared to the number of crimes they did not solve. Third, the detectives really want to find out the truth regarding \(\phi \), they really want to solve the case.

We take it that the fulfillment of these three conditions is what is (at minimum) required for the two detectives to be called each other’s peers, considering the construals of peerhood by, for example, Kelly (2005, 175), Elga (2007, 484), Lackey (2008, 274) and Christensen (2009, 757). The attribution of peerhood then depends on how equal the detectives must be in their reliability. Our analysis accommodates this.

Jane and Hercule both go to the crime scene, and spend some time examining and evaluating the evidence. After some time, they meet up to report their findings.

Two things can happen at this point. Jane and Hercule have either formed the same belief about \(\phi \), or they have formed conflicting beliefs and disagree about \(\phi \). In the model, these beliefs are generated probabilistically (see the next section).

If the detectives have reached the same conclusion about \(\phi \), say, they agree that the butler is indeed the culprit, then there is no problem of peer disagreement. The detectives can go write their reports. The case that we are interested in is when the detectives have formed conflicting opinions regarding \(\phi \); for example, when Jane believes that the butler is the culprit and Hercule believes that the butler is innocent. And our question is what, in such a case, a rational response for Jane and Hercule can be, given their goal of finding out the truth about \(\phi \), and the information they have about each other’s track-records.

Based on the debate about peer disagreement, we distinguish three strategies that the detectives can choose. The first comes from the Steadfast View and is the strategy of staying with the initial belief. We call this strategy Stay. The second strategy is the Conciliatory View’s recommendation to suspend judgment.Footnote 5 This strategy is called Suspend. And third, for the sake of completeness, we include switching to the belief of the other detective as a third possible strategy, called Switch.

After Jane and Hercule find out that they disagree about whether the butler is the culprit, they each play one of these three strategies. When Jane plays Suspend, she withdraws her initial belief about \(\phi \), goes back to the crime scene to re-examine the evidence, and forms a new belief about \(\phi \). But when Jane plays Stay, she chooses to ignore the disagreement and maintains her initial opinion. And when Jane plays Switch, she chooses to ignore her own opinion and takes over the belief of Hercule.

So only when a detective plays Suspend she gets a chance to form a new opinion. It might be objected that acquiring a new belief is not a necessary consequence of suspending judgment. We agree. We should distinguish between two ways in which judgment can be suspended. The first is to suspend judgment indefinitely, or at least until new evidence comes in, because there is at present not enough evidence to form a rational belief. The second is to suspend judgment only momentarily, as an act of caution in light of unexpected counterevidence, but after which a new belief may be formed through a re-examination of the evidence. Such a momentary suspension of judgment is justified for cases in which a Peircean ‘irritation of doubt’ needs to be resolved, because it is unsatisfactory or unwarranted not to have a belief about the matter. We take it that this is the preferred form of suspension of judgment in the well-known restaurant case of Christensen (2007, 193), in which two peers disagree about the division of the bill, as well as in other influential examples of peer disagreement (e.g. Feldman 2007, 208–209). In this paper we also work with this short-term interpretation of suspension of judgment. A long-term interpretation would be a welcome extension of our analysis (see Sect. 6 and Appendix 2).

The disagreement game ends when the two detectives reach an agreement about \(\phi \). For example, suppose Jane believes that the butler did it, and Hercule believes that he did not do it, and Jane plays Suspend and Hercule plays Stay. Then the game ends when, after re-examining the evidence, Jane draws the same conclusion as Hercule, namely that the butler is innocent.Footnote 6 The same would happen when, for example, Jane plays Stay and Hercule plays Switch. But the game continues when, after one or both of them re-examine the evidence, the two detectives still disagree about \(\phi \).

For the purposes of this paper, we assume that the detectives do not change strategies throughout the disagreement game.Footnote 7 This means that the game might also continue forever. For example, when Jane believes that the butler is innocent and Hercule disagrees, and both detectives play Stay, then they will never come to an agreement. The same thing happens when both detectives play Switch.Footnote 8

And now we are in a position to analyze how well these strategies do in guiding each detective to the correct verdict on whether the butler did it. Which of these strategies gives a detective the best prospects of arriving at the truth?

Observe that which strategy is best will depend on two factors.Footnote 9 First, it depends on the reliability (i.e., the track-record) of each of the two detectives. For example, if Jane thinks that Hercule is better at evaluating correctly whether the butler did it, then it would be ill-advised for her to play Stay upon finding out that Hercule disagrees with her initial assessment. But when Jane thinks that she is more reliable than Hercule, then playing Stay may be sensible.

Second, which strategy is best depends also on the strategy of the other detective. For example, when Hercule plays Stay, it does not really matter for Jane whether she plays Suspend or Switch, because either way the game will end when Jane takes over the conclusion of Hercule. But when Hercule plays Switch, it does matter whether Jane plays Suspend or Switch, because playing Switch will bring them in a state of perpetual disagreement, whereas playing Suspend will make them agree eventually (due to the probabilistic way in which new beliefs are generated; see the next section). We will return to these points in Sect. 5.

This concludes our informal description of the peer disagreement game. In the next section we will provide the formal vocabulary, and then analyze this game.

4 Rationality for Jane and Hercule

Whenever Jane and Hercule investigate the evidence, they may conclude that the butler did it (\(\phi \)) or that he did not do it (\(\lnot \phi \)). One of these conclusions is true and one is false.

We will denote by p and q the reliability or truth-sensitivity of Jane and Hercule, respectively. Thus p is the probability, on any given investigation, that Jane draws a true conclusion from the evidence. \(1-p\) denotes the probability of a false belief. So if the butler really did it Jane believes that he did it with probability p and believes in his innocence with probability \(1-p\). Whereas if he is innocent she believes in his innocence with probability p and believes that he did it with probability \(1-p\). Hercule’s probabilities of drawing a true or a false conclusion from the evidence are denoted by q and \(1-q\), respectively.

We choose to model the probability of generating a true or false belief rather than the probability of generating a belief for or against \(\phi \) because we have evidence for the former but not the latter based on the respective track-records of the two detectives. We assumed at the start of Sect. 3 that this track-record information is known to the two detectives.

To avoid trivial cases, we assume that \(0 < p < 1\) and \(0 < q < 1\). We further assume that, if Jane or Hercule suspends judgment in response to disagreement, their new opinion is generated with the same probabilities as their initial opinion (so Jane believes correctly with probability p, and Hercule believes correctly with probability q). We also assume that each time an opinion is generated this is done independently (in the probabilistic sense) from the detective’s previous opinions and the other detective’s current or previous opinions.

We think the assumption that the detectives reason independently from each other is justified because they make their assessments separately. If they are likely to come to the same conclusion this must be because the evidence points in a particular direction, which is reflected in the model by the choice of p and q.Footnote 10 On the other hand, the assumption that newly generated opinions are independent from previously generated ones may be unrealistic, but it turns out not to have a strong influence on the results (see Sect. 6 and Appendix 1).

In the epistemology of peer disagreement—as we learn from, for example, Christensen (2007, 216), Feldman (2007, 212), Elga (2007, 488), and Kelly (2010, 17)—the objective of rational conduct is commonly understood to be believing the correct truth-value. This suggests the following epistemic norm.

Accuracy Norm (AN)

Having a true belief is more valuable than having a false belief.

We assume that Jane and Hercule share this noble goal, and that in fact obtaining a true belief about whether the butler did it is their only goal.Footnote 11 So the two detectives are not distracted by pragmatic concerns. This is a methodological rather than a substantive assumption: we are interested in the epistemology of peer disagreement, not its pragmatics.

(AN) determines the detectives’ preferences over outcomes of the disagreement game: Jane prefers an outcome in which she has a true belief about the butler’s guilt over one in which she has a false belief, and likewise for Hercule.Footnote 12 A detective receives utility 1 if her belief about the guilt or innocence of the butler at the end of the disagreement game is true, and utility 0 if it is false.Footnote 13

The expected utility of a detective in the game is then simply the probability of ending the game with a true belief. So Jane and Hercule prefer a strategy if it increases their probability of ending the disagreement game with a true belief concerning \(\phi \).

We can now determine the probabilities of ending the disagreement game with a true belief for each combination of strategies of the two detectives (a combination of strategies is called a strategy profile).

If both detectives play Stay, they never change their mind in response to disagreement, so their probability of ending with a true belief is simply the probability that they obtain a true belief initially: p for Jane and q for Hercule. In all other cases the probability of ending the disagreement game with a true belief is the same for both detectives. These probabilities are indicated in Table 1. The rows of Table 1 indicate Jane’s choice of strategy, and the columns indicate Hercule’s choice.Footnote 14

Table 1 Expected utilities associated with each strategy profile under (AN)

How can the detectives maximize their probability of ending the disagreement game with a true belief, given that the choice of strategy of the other detective influences their probability of attaining true belief, but they cannot control it? Game theorists have invented various concepts of rationality in a game to deal with this problem. We will use the notion of Nash equilibrium.

A Nash equilibrium is a profile—that is, an assignment of a strategy to each player—in which either player’s strategy is a best response to the other’s. In other words, in a Nash equilibrium, no player can get an outcome she prefers over the equilibrium outcome by unilaterally changing her strategy. In our game this means that in a Nash equilibrium Jane and Hercule are maximizing their respective probabilities of ending the game with a true belief, given (that is, keeping fixed) the other detective’s strategy. This is how we interpret (epistemic) rationality for Jane and Hercule.

5 Results and Discussion

What are the Nash equilibria of this game?Footnote 15 This turns out to depend on the values of p and q. Figure 1 shows which strategy profiles are Nash equilibria for any combination of values of p and q.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Nash equilibria of the peer disagreement game as a function of the truth-sensitivity of the detectives. E.g., if \(p = 0.4\) and \(q = 0.9\) then the Nash equilibria of the game are (Suspend,Stay) and (Switch,Suspend)

Recall that we noted in Sect. 3 that two factors would influence which strategy choice is best. First, the truth-sensitivity of the two detectives (modeled as p and q) and second, the strategy of the other detective. Both of these factors are shown in our results in Fig. 1.

The truth-sensitivity of the detectives clearly influences which strategy profiles are rational. For example, (Stay,Switch) is a Nash equilibrium whenever Hercule’s truth-sensitivity (his probability of drawing a true conclusion) is less than Jane’s truth-sensitivity and less than Jane’s probability of drawing a false conclusion (formally, \(q \le \min \{p,1-p\}\)). Similarly, (Switch,Stay) is a Nash equilibrium whenever Hercule’s truth-sensitivity is between Jane’s truth-sensitivity and Jane’s probability of drawing a false conclusion (formally, \(p \le q \le 1-p\)).

The other detective’s strategy also influences what it is rational for a detective to do. For example, if Hercule’s truth-sensitivity is higher than Jane’s probability of drawing a false conclusion, but less than one-half (formally, \(1-p \le q \le 1/2\)), the Nash equilibria are (Stay,Suspend) and (Suspend,Switch). So under these circumstances, if Hercule chooses the strategy Suspend, it is rational for Jane to choose Stay, while if Hercule chooses Switch, it is rational for Jane to choose Suspend.

The epistemic success of the two detectives (both in terms of which strategy promises the best probability of a true belief, and in terms of the value of that probability) thus depends on the choices made by the other detective. In this way the epistemology of this model is truly social.

One way to understand the results in Fig. 1 is to view the detectives as making a tradeoff between two competing risks. On the one hand, there is the ‘cost’ of giving up one’s initial opinion. On the other hand, there is the cost of ignoring the other detective. When one detective has a significantly better track-record than the other (as reflected in the values of p and q), it is too costly for that detective to give up her initial opinion and switch to the other’s opinion. She gains more by staying with the initial belief, or suspending judgment and acquiring a new belief.

For the other detective it is the other way around. In her case, it is too costly to ignore the opinion of the other detective. Since she does not have as good a track-record, she would not gain as much by staying with her initial belief, or suspending judgment and acquiring a new belief, as she will by switching to the opinion of the other detective. For her the cost of ignoring the other detective is higher than the cost of giving up her original opinion. The tipping points in these game-theoretic transactions can be read off from Fig. 1.

It is worth pointing out that the detectives’ desire to minimize these risks is not epistemically basic. We have assumed that the only thing the detectives (ultimately) care about is maximizing their probability of ending the peer disagreement game with a true belief about \(\phi \). We now see that this goal, as formalized in (AN), implies that the detectives should worry about these two risks, and gives the detectives an epistemically motivated basis for trading them off against one another. In this sense our results fit nicely with the emerging literature that aims to explain various epistemic norms as following from (AN) (Joyce 1998; Pettigrew 2013).

Of particular interest in evaluating the results in Fig. 1 are the profiles (Stay,Stay) and (Suspend,Suspend). This is because the former captures most directly the Steadfast View—according to which it can be rational to Stay in a case of peer disagreement—and the latter captures most directly the Conciliatory View—according to which the only rational option is to Suspend.

What is surprising, and running contra the peer disagreement literature, is that both (Stay,Stay) and (Suspend,Suspend) turn out to constitute Nash equilibria, under some conditions even both at once.

As we can see from Fig. 1, the Steadfast profile (Stay,Stay) is a Nash equilibrium when Jane and Hercule are each other’s equals in terms of how truth-sensitive their beliefs are (i.e., \(p = q\)). In such a case neither would gain anything by playing Suspend or Switch (provided the other detective continues to play Stay). This is because the probability that a detective ends up with a true belief by staying with her initial opinion is just as high as the probability that the opinion of the other detective or a newly generated opinion is true.

However, a mutual Conciliatory approach, as expressed in the strategy profile (Suspend,Suspend), can also be a Nash equilibrium. This happens when p and q are both greater than one-half and are relatively close to each other (see Fig. 1).Footnote 16 When both detectives have relatively good track-records, and they find out that they have formed conflicting beliefs, they stand to gain more when they both suspend judgment and acquire a new belief, than when they stick to their initial beliefs, or switch to the other detective’s belief.

An especially interesting scenario occurs whenever p and q are exactly equal and greater than one-half: then (Stay,Stay) and (Suspend,Suspend) are Nash equilibria at the same time. Under the definition of rationality we use, in such a case both Steadfast and Conciliatory strategies are rational.

We wish to stress the significance of this result. In the literature on peer disagreement, the Steadfast strategy and the Conciliatory strategy are typically presented as mutually exclusive; either it is rational to play Stay or it is rational to play Suspend, but they cannot both be rational. A surprising insight of our analysis is that this need not be accurate. Under certain conditions, namely when two agents are positively and equally reliable, both the Steadfast strategy and the Conciliatory strategy can be rational. Moreover, the case where the two agents are positively and equally reliable is exactly the case the peer disagreement literature has focused on.

So where does this leave us in the peer disagreement debate? If we take seriously the modalities in the definitions of the views, the Steadfast View ‘wins’: it can be rational to stick to one’s opinion in the face of peer disagreement; the Conciliatory View’s claim that this cannot be rational is false in our model. But if we take the views as recommending strategies (Stay for the Steadfast View and Suspend for the Conciliatory View) then we think the Conciliatory View has the advantage—even when both are Nash equilibria—for the following reasons.

First, whenever (Stay,Stay) and (Suspend,Suspend) are Nash equilibria simultaneously, (Suspend,Suspend) offers a higher utility (a higher probability of solving the case correctly) to both detectives.Footnote 17 In fact, (Suspend,Suspend) is Pareto efficient. So Jane and Hercule prefer to play (Suspend,Suspend) over (Stay,Stay). If they are allowed to discuss their strategy before the game starts, we should expect both detectives to play Suspend.

Second, Suspend is a weakly dominant strategy (for both detectives), while Stay is not. This means that playing Suspend pays off at least as well as playing Stay or Switch, regardless of what strategy the other detective chooses. So in this situation, playing Stay is only best for a detective who is absolutely certain that the other detective is playing Stay as well (and even then playing Suspend is equally good), whereas if there is only the slightest uncertainty about what the other detective is going to do, Suspend is the uniquely best strategy.

Third, we can see in Fig. 1 that when p and q are both greater than one-half there is a significant area in which the profile (Suspend,Suspend) is a Nash equilibrium, while (Stay,Stay) is a Nash equilibrium only when p and q are exactly equal.Footnote 18 This means that the strategy Suspend has a larger margin for error than the strategy Stay. If Jane and Hercule lack precise information about each other’s truth-sensitivity (as is reasonable to expect), playing Stay is ‘riskier’ than playing Suspend because the former requires exact and the latter only approximate equality of the detectives’ truth-sensitivities.

To sum up, a surprising result of this model is that if the detectives have equal track-records, and these track-records are ‘good’ (better than chance), then both the Steadfast profile and the Conciliatory profile are Nash equilibria. However, we have noted three reasons to think that in such cases the Conciliatory strategy should be preferred.

6 Limitations and Extensions of Our Analysis

We have limited our analysis to a particular game-theoretic formalization of a particular disagreement game between two detectives, Jane and Hercule. To what extent does our analysis generalize to other peer disagreements? And what variations or extensions of our formalization are possible?

Regarding the first question, our analysis applies to peer disagreements in general insofar as they satisfy the assumptions of our model. In particular, (1) peers are cashed out in terms of comparable reliability or truth-sensitivity, (2) the possible responses available to the peers are something like the strategies Stay, Suspend, and Switch as we model them, and (3) the rationality of a particular response is evaluated in terms of how well it tracks the truth.

Regarding the second question, there are many options for different peer disagreement games. Let us give eight variables that can be filled in differently.

First, doxastic attitudes: in our model, strategies act on full belief states, but strategies might also be interpreted as adjusting degrees of belief.

Second, we forced our detectives to generate a new belief whenever they suspend judgment on \(\phi \). A variation of our model might allow peers to persist in a state of suspension. This outcome could be assigned its own value, presumably worse than having a true belief but better than having a false belief. We consider this variation in Appendix 2. Unsurprisingly, the results depend on what epistemic value is assigned to the state of suspension.

Third, we assumed that whenever Jane or Hercule generates a new belief (i.e., at the end of a round on which they disagreed and the relevant detective is playing Suspend) the new belief generated is probabilistically independent of the belief held on the previous round. This may seem unrealistic. For example, Jane may generally be a reliable detective (\(p > 1/2\)) but she may be prone to repeat mistakes in her reasoning. In Appendix 1 we consider a version of the model in which newly generated beliefs are positively correlated with the belief held on the previous round. The results are qualitatively similar to those of Sect. 5.

Fourth, the number of peers. What happens if there are more than two disagreeing peers? Consider the case that we focused on above, where the peers’ truth-sensitivity is equal, and better than chance. The Condorcet Jury Theorem shows that if a moderately large number of peers simultaneously state their opinion, the majority opinion is highly likely to be correct.Footnote 19 But models of informational cascades show that if the peers state their opinion sequentially, the majority outcome is not nearly so informative (Bikhchandani et al. 1992, 996–999). This illustrates once again that the success of epistemic strategies—here majority voting, a plausible generalization of the Conciliatory View—can be quite sensitive to subtle contextual details, which formal models can focus attention on.

Fifth, we kept the peers’ strategies fixed throughout the game. The reason for this was to enable an evaluation of the Conciliatory and Steadfast strategies. But it would be an interesting extension of the game to allow peers to change their strategies during the game.

Sixth, we assumed that the game might go on indefinitely. This is not very realistic. In real life there are time and energy constraints. So another possible extension would be to let the game continue for a limited number of rounds, after which the agents must have made up their minds. We consider the case with only one round in Appendix 2. If the other assumptions are unchanged, the results favor the Conciliatory View slightly more than those of the main text (see Fig. 3 in Appendix 2).

Seventh, in our analysis the rationality of a strategy was evaluated using Nash equilibria. Although this is very natural in game theory, it has substantive normative implications. So one may want to consider alternatives. Available alternatives include various refinements of the notion of equilibrium, such as the trembling hand equilibrium, and alternative standards, such as weak dominance. Different strategies may turn out to be rational under such different standards of rationality.

Finally, we worked with only one epistemic norm, namely accuracy. But there are more epistemic goals. For example, many philosophers of science have argued, under the label of ‘epistemic diversity’, that maintaining diversity of opinion can have epistemic value to a population of scientists, stimulating new ideas and discoveries (Feyerabend 1975; Kitcher 1990; Zollman 2010). And the literature on epistemic rationality has identified a trade-off between truth and information (Levi 1967). For example, true beliefs could be maximized by believing only tautologies, but this is not informative. Either of these considerations could motivate augmenting or replacing (AN) with different norms.

7 Conclusion

By way of conclusion we emphasize four lessons that can be drawn from our preliminary game-theoretic investigation of the epistemology of peer disagreement.

First, in our model the Steadfast and Conciliatory strategies were sometimes both right: there were circumstances in which both staying with your own opinion and suspending belief were rational. The idea that staying and suspending can be rational simultaneously is underexplored in the literature and worth investigating more extensively.

Second, the rationality of a response to peer disagreement may depend on the truth-sensitivity of the peers. Both the peers’ relative truth-sensitivity (who has a better track-record and by how much?) and their absolute truth-sensitivity (are they better than chance, say, or some other objective threshold?) can make a difference.

Third, what is rational for a peer to do (e.g., whether to be Steadfast or Conciliatory) may depend on what the other peer is doing. This is a natural conclusion to draw in the game-theoretic context, but underexplored in the peer disagreement literature.

Fourth, analysis of other game-theoretic models of peer disagreement may shed more light on the above three points and other important questions about peer disagreement. We encourage anyone interested in our model (especially if they liked it but for one or two assumptions) to develop and analyze such an alternative game-theoretic model of peer disagreement. We hope to have provided a fruitful framework within with such further models can be developed.