Skip to main content
Log in

Environmental risks, the judgment-proof problem and financial responsibility

  • Published:
European Journal of Law and Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper examines a setting in which a firm is liable to pay environmental damages caused by its activity but may not have sufficient wealth for repair of damages. In order to induce the full internalization of the environmental cost, the firm is required to demonstrate a financial guarantee from a solvent party that covers this cost. Since the firm and the guarantor are joint liable for the harm caused by the firm, it is in the interest of the guarantor to design the guarantee contract in order to induce the firm to take an adequate level of prevention. First, I show that financial responsibility regime may achieve the social optimum. Secondly, I identify a particular form of contract in the set of contracts which induce the socially optimal level of prevention. This contract is closed to an alternative risk transfer product referred to as the spread loss treaty.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Ringleb and Wiggins (1990) show that after the enactment of CERCLA, large companies strategically subcontracted their dangerous activities to small ones in order to shield assets from liability in the case of environmental accident.

  2. The lender pays for the full amount of the damages and recovers a part of this from the borrower.

  3. Monotone Likelihood Ratio Property (MLRP).

  4. Concavity of Distribution Function Condition (CDFC).

  5. Apart from the deep-pockets argument, this rule ensures the financial participation of the guarantor even if he argues that his agent does not respect a clause in the contract.

  6. This assumption is similar to the one of Pitchford (1995) who considered that in the case of accident, the lender pays for compensation.

  7. In agency literature, when the agent faces bounded penalty, the principal can use rewards to incite him.

  8. It is the so-called first-order approach that consists to take into account just the FOC of the optimization problem of the firm. Rogerson (1985) has shown that this approach is valid under assumptions 1 and 2.

  9. The hardening of the traditional insurance market notably concerning environmental risks has increased the demand for ART (Alternative Risk Transfer) products which cover finite risk solutions, cat bonds, captives and risk retention groups.

  10. Contrary to a traditional insurance contract, a finite risk contract spreads the risk of the same client over time.

  11. Proof upon request.

  12. Proof upon request.

  13. Proof upon request.

References

  • Balkenborg, D. (2001). How liable should a lender be? The case of judgment-proof firms and environmental risk: Comment. American Economic Review, 91, 731–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beard, R. (1990). Bankruptcy and care choice. RAND Journal of Economics, 21, 626–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, M., & Laffont, J.-J. (1997). Environmental risks and bank liability. European Economic Review, 41, 1427–1459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dari-Mattiacci, G., & De Geest, G. (2005). Judgment Proofness under four different precaution technologies. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 161(1), 38–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dionne, G., & Spaeter, S. (2003). Environmental risk and extended liability: The case of green technologies. Journal of Public Economics, 87(5–6), 1025–1060.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feess, E., & Hege, U. (2000). Environmental harm and financial responsibility. Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, Issues and Practice, 25(2), 220–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feess, E., & Hege, U. (2003). Safety monitoring, capital structure and financial responsibility. International Review of Law and Economics, 23, 323–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison, E., & Van’t Veld, K. (2005). Extended liability for environmental accidents: What you see is what you get. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 49, 157–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jost, P. (1996). Limited liability and the requirement to purchase insurance. International Review of Law and Economics, 16, 259–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, T., & Sappington, D. (1999). Using decoupling and deep pockets to mitigate judgment-proof problems. International Review of Law and Economics, 19, 275–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, T., & Sappington, D. (2001). How liable should a lender be? The case of judgment-proof firms and environmental risk: Comment. American Economic Review, 91, 724–730.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipowsky-Posey, L. (1993). Limited liability and incentives when firms can inflict damages greater than worth. International Review of Law and Economics, 13, 325–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitchford, R. (1995). How liable should a lender be? The case of judgment-proof firms and environmental risk. American Economic Review, 85, 1171–1186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polborn, M. (1998). Mandatory insurance and the judgment proof problem. International Review of Law and Economics, 18, 141–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ringleb, A. H., & Wiggins, S. N. (1990). Liability and large-scale long-term hazards. Journal of Political Economy, 98, 574–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogerson, W. (1985). The first-order approach to principal-agent problems. Econometrica, 53, 1357–1367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shavell, S. (1986). The judgment proof problem. International Review of Law and Economics, 6, 45–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Summers, J. S. (1983). The case of disappearing defendant: An economic analysis. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 132, 145–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to an anonymous referee and to the editor for helpful remarks on a previous version of the paper. I would like to thank Jean-Marc Bourgeon, Georges Dionne, Marie-Cécile Fagart, Mahamadou Fall, Claude Fluet, Bruno Jullien, Anne Lavigne, Rémi Moreau, Pierre Picard, Sandrine Spaeter, Jean-Marc Tallon and Daniel Zajdenweber. The paper also benefited from the comments of session participants of the 2005 SCSE congress in Charlevoix, 2005 AFSE congress in Paris and seminar participants at HEC Montréal, Université d’Orléans, Université de Sherbrooke and Université du Québec à Montréal. Financial support by CREF-HEC and the hospitality of the Canada Research Chair in risk management are acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bidénam Kambia-Chopin.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of lemma 1

The social optimum e* is the solution of the following problem:

$$ \mathop {\min }\limits_{e} \int\limits_{0}^{L} {\ell f\left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell + c\left( e \right)} $$

The associated first-order condition is given by:

$$ c_{e} \left( {e*} \right) = \int\limits_{0}^{L} {F_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)d\ell } . $$
(6)

The firm’s problem can be written as:

$$ \mathop {\max }\limits_{e} \pi - c\left( e \right) - \int\limits_{0}^{\pi - c(e)} {\ell f\left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell - \left[ {1 - F\left( {\pi - c\left( e \right)} \right)} \right]\left[ {\pi - c(e)} \right]} $$

If we denoted by e P the interior solution to the above problem, it solves the following first-order-condition:

$$ c_{e} \left( {e^{P} } \right)F\left( {\pi - c\left( {e^{P} } \right)} \right) = \int\limits_{0}^{{\pi - c\left( {e^{P} } \right)}} {F_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell {e^{P} }}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e^{P} }}} \right)d\ell } . $$
(7)

The left-hand-side term of Eq. 6 (7) represents the social (private) expected marginal cost of prevention and the right-hand-side represents the social (private) expected marginal benefit. From the comparison of (6) and (7) e P can be lower or higher than e*.

1.2 Proof of proposition 2

Part 1: \( u \in \left[ {\underline{u,} \pi - c\left( e \right) - B} \right] \)

Every level of utility u is given by the following expression:

$$ u = \pi - c\left( e \right) - \int\limits_{0}^{L} {t(\ell )f\left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell } $$

Taking into account this expression, the objective function of the guarantor becomes:

$$ \pi - c(e) - u - \int\limits_{0}^{L} {\ell f\left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell } $$

Moreover, (2) and (3) imply:\( \pi - c\left( e \right) \ge \int_{0}^{L} {t(\ell )} f\left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell \ge B; \) thus \( 0 \le u \le \pi - c\left( e \right) - B \)

Consequently, the existence of a transfers scheme verifying (1), (2) and (3) implies that the utility of the firm is bounded: \( u \in \left[ {\underline{u,} \pi - c\left( e \right) - B} \right] \). Note that the principal’s objective function depends only on the expected transfer (by u). Therefore, all solutions that verify the agent’s incentive constraint and that have the same expectation are equivalent from the principal’s point of view. However, the existence of such solutions is not guaranteed. Indeed, if the problem does not admit a solution, then it is not possible to implement a given level of prevention e for a given level of utility u.

Part 2: \( \left[ {\pi - c\left( e \right) - B} \right]F_{e} \left( {{{\hat{\ell }} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\ell }} e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right) \ge c_{e} \left( e \right) \)

Let us assume that \( u \in \left[ {\underline{u,} \pi - c(e) - B} \right] \), then the next step consists to establish conditions under which the incentive constraint (4) is satisfied. Let \( \Im = \left\{ {t(\ell )/B \le t(\ell ) \le \pi - c(e)\forall \ell } \right\}, \) be the set of admissible transfers. Let us define:\( G\left[ {t\left( \cdot \right)} \right] = \int_{0}^{L} {t\left( \ell \right)f_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell } ; \) \( m = \mathop {\min }\limits_{t\left( \ell \right) \in \Im } \int_{0}^{L} {t\left( \ell \right)f_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell } \) and \( M = \mathop {\max }\limits_{t\left( \ell \right) \in \Im } \int_{0}^{L} {t\left( \ell \right)f_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell } \).

We can establish that m is strictly negative and M strictly positive.Footnote 11 Thus the function \( G\left[ {t(.)} \right] \) is bounded in the set of admissible transfers. Then the validity of the incentive constraint depends on the value taken by m as follows.

Lemma 2

the incentive constraint is satisfied for a given e and u if and only if:

$$ \min \int\limits_{0}^{L} {t\left( \ell \right)f_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell \le - c_{e} \left( e \right)} $$

Lemma 3

the scheme of transfers\( \hat{t}(\ell ) \)which minimizes the function\( G\left[ {t\left( \cdot \right)} \right] = \int_{0}^{L} {t\left( \ell \right)f_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell } \)has the following formFootnote 12:

$$ \hat{t}(\ell ) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}c} B \hfill & {\forall \ell < \hat{\ell }} \hfill \\ {\pi - c\left( e \right)} \hfill & {\forall \ell > \hat{\ell }} \hfill \\ \end{array} } \right.\quad {\text{with}}\,\hat{\ell } = F^{ - 1} \left[ {{{\frac{u}{\pi - c\left( e \right) - B}}}} \right][] $$

The second part of proposition 2 follows from lemmas 2 and 3.

1.3 Proof of proposition 3

From proposition 2, we can derive that when the guarantor’s problem (P1) admits at least one solution, it is equivalent to the following problem (P1bis):

$$ \mathop {\max }\limits_{t(\ell ),e} \pi - c\left( e \right) - u - \int\limits_{0}^{L} {\ell f\left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right)d\ell } $$

subject to

$$ \underline{u \, } \le u \le \pi - c\left( e \right) - B $$
(8)
$$ \left[ {\pi - c\left( e \right) - B} \right]F\left( {{{\hat{\ell }} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\ell }} e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}} \right) = u $$
(9)
$$ \left[ {\pi - c\left( e \right) - B} \right]F_{e} ({{\hat{\ell }} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\ell }} e}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} e}) \ge c_{e} \left( e \right) $$
(10)

Conditions (9) and (10) imply proposition 3.

1.4 Proof of proposition 4

From the proposition 3 we know that the socially optimal prevention level can be achieved if \( {\frac{{F_{e} \left( {{{\hat{\ell }} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\ell }} {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}{{F\left( {{{\hat{\ell }} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\ell }} {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}} \ge {\frac{{c_{e} \left( {e*} \right)}}{{\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle-}$}}{u} }}} \). Moreover, we can demonstrate that the function \( {\frac{{F_{e} \left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}{{F\left( {{\ell \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {\ell {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}} \) is not increasing in ℓ.Footnote 13 Consequently, if \( {\frac{{F_{e} \left( {{{\hat{\ell }} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\ell }} {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}{{F\left( {{{\hat{\ell }} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\ell }} {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}} \ge {\frac{{c_{e} \left( {e*} \right)}}{{\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle-}$}}{u} }}} \), there is a level of damages \( \hat{\hat{\ell }} > \hat{\ell } \) such that \( {\frac{{F_{e} \left( {{{\hat{\hat{\ell }}} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\hat{\ell }}} {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}{{F\left( {{{\hat{\hat{\ell }}} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{\hat{\hat{\ell }}} {e*}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {e*}}} \right)}}} = {\frac{{c_{e} \left( {e*} \right)}}{{\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle-}$}}{u} }}} \).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kambia-Chopin, B. Environmental risks, the judgment-proof problem and financial responsibility. Eur J Law Econ 30, 77–87 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-009-9134-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-009-9134-6

Keywords

JEL classification

Navigation