Skip to main content
Log in

Evaluating Change in Objective Ambiguous Mortality Probability: Valuing Reduction in Ambiguity Size and Risk Level

  • Published:
Environmental and Resource Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article develops a valuation model to evaluate mortality probability changes under objective ambiguity, where multiple mortality probabilities are exogenously given. We construct the valuation model based on \(\upalpha \)-maxmin expected utility to evaluate the reduction in ambiguity size and risk level as well as estimate the subjects’ ambiguity attitude. Our model can bring an interesting policy implication. If the subjects are ambiguity-averse, a reduction in ambiguity size with a constant risk level can increases welfare. Thus, even if risk level cannot be lowered, reduction in ambiguity size can also be used as a measure toward increasing welfare. Our model can empirically estimate this welfare change resulting from the reduction in ambiguity size. To demonstrate how our model works, we apply it to survey data on a public program that reduces mortality probability in accidents caused by wildlife.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Camerer and Weber (1992) and Etner et al. (2012) provide summarized discussions on ambiguity.

  2. When a unique subjective probability is derived, the typical decision model is Savage’s (1954) subjective expected utility model.

  3. Ghirardato et al. (2004) have provided a set of axioms for \(\upalpha \)-MEU under subjective ambiguity.

  4. Not many studies that have shown ambiguity attitudes in the context of environmental valuation. Riddel and Shaw (2006) and Riddel (2011) have demonstrated ambiguity attitudes using second-order probability models. These are, however, based on subjective ambiguity.

  5. This expected utility setting is based on the standard model of mortality risk (e.g., Jones-Lee 1974; Viscusi 1993; Hammitt 2000).

  6. See also the appendix for an intuitive interpretation of the ambiguity parameter \(\upalpha \).

  7. Note that \(\dfrac{\partial \textit{EU}^{\alpha }}{\displaystyle \partial {R}}=\dfrac{\displaystyle \partial \textit{EU}^{\alpha }}{\displaystyle \partial {p}^{\alpha }}\dfrac{\displaystyle \partial {p}^{\alpha }}{\displaystyle \partial {R}}=\left( {{V}\left( {y} \right) -{U}\left( {y} \right) } \right) \cdot \small \left( {{\alpha }-\frac{1}{2}} \right) , \dfrac{\displaystyle \partial \textit{EU}^{\alpha }}{\displaystyle \partial {m}}=\dfrac{\displaystyle \partial \textit{EU}^{\alpha }}{\displaystyle \partial {p}^{\alpha }}\dfrac{\displaystyle \partial {p}^{\alpha }}{\displaystyle \partial {m}}=\small \left( {{V}\left( {y} \right) -{U}\left( {y} \right) } \right) \), and \(\dfrac{\displaystyle \partial \textit{EU}^{\alpha }}{\displaystyle \partial {y}}=\small \left( {1-{p}^{\alpha }} \right) {U}^{{\prime }}\left( {y} \right) +{p}^{\alpha }{V}^{{\prime }}\left( {y} \right) \).

  8. Because we include a constant term \({c}_{j} \), it does not matter if we assume that the mean of \({\epsilon }_{{ji}} \) is 0.

References

  • Ahn DS (2008) Ambiguity without a state space. Rev Econ Stud 75:3–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer C, Weber M (1992) Recent developments in modeling preferences: uncertainty and ambiguity. J Risk Uncertain 5:325–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron TA (2005) Individual option prices for climate change mitigation. J Public Econ 89:283–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron TA, Englin J (1997) Welfare effects of changes in environmental quality under individual uncertainty. Rand J Econ 28:45–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carson R, Hanemann WH (2005) Contingent valuation. In: Mäler K-G, Vincent JR (eds) Handbook of environmental economics, vol 2. Amsterdam, North-Holland, pp 821–936

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg D (1961) Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Q J Econ 75:643–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etner J, Jeleva M, Tallon J-M (2012) Decision theory under ambiguity. J Econ Surv 26:234–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato P, Maccheroni F, Marinacci M (2004) Differentiating ambiguity and ambiguity attitude. J Econ Theor 118:133–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa I, Schmeidler D (1989) Maxmin expected utility with a non-unique prior. J Math Econ 18:141–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gravel N, Marchant T, Sen A (2012) Uniform expected utility criteria for decision making under ignorance or objective ambiguity. J Math Psychol 56:297–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammitt JK (2000) Valuing mortality risk. Environ Sci Technol 34:1396–1400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz L (1951) Optimality criterion for decision making under ignorance. Cowles commission discussion paper, Statistics 370

  • Jaffray J-Y (1994) Dynamic decision making with belief functions. In: Yager RR, Fedrizzi M, Kacprzyk J (eds) Advances in the Dempster-Shafer theory of evidence. Wiley, New York, pp 331–352

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones-Lee M (1974) The value of changes in the probability of death of injury. J Polit Econ 82:835–849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kameda M, Maruyama H (2003) Public attitudes and behaviors towards brown bears in the Oshima Peninsula. Memoirs of the Muroran Institute of Technology, 53, 6576 (In Japanese)

  • Kahn BE, Sarin RK (1988) Modeling ambiguity in decisions under uncertainty. J Consum Res 15:265–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohira M, Nakanishi HOM, Yamanaka M (2009) Modeling the effects of human-caused mortality on the brown bear population on the Shiretoko Peninsula, Hokkaido, Japan. Ursus 20:12–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff P, Marinacci M, Mukerji S (2005) A Smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica 73:1849–1892

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krinsky I, Robb AL (1986) On approximating the statistical properties of elasticities. Rev Econ Stat 68:715–719

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomis JB, du Vair PH (1993) Evaluating the effect of alternative risk communication devices on willingness to pay: results from a dichotomous choice contingent valuation experiment. Land Econ 69:287–298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meinshausen M, Meinshausen N, Hare W, Raper SCB, Frieler K, Knutti R, Frame DJ, Allen MR (2009) Greenhouse-gas emission targets for limiting global warming to 2\(^\circ \)C. Nature 458:1158–1162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merz B, Thieken AH (2009) Flood risk curves and uncertainty bounds. Nat Hazards 51:437–458

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ohta U, Jusupa M, Mano T, Tsuruga H, Matsuda H (2012) Adaptive management of the brown bear population in Hokkaido, Japan. Ecol Modell 242:20–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olszewski W (2007) Preferences over sets of lotteries. Rev Econ Stud 74:567–595

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riddel M (2011) Uncertainty and measurement error in welfare models for risk changes. J Environ Econ Manage 61:341–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riddel M, Shaw WD (2006) A theoretically-consistent empirical model of non-expected utility: an application to nuclear-waste transport. J Risk Uncertain 32:131–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato Y, Aoi T, Kaji K, Takatsuki S (2004) Temporal changes in the population density and diet of brown bears in eastern Hokkaido, Japan. Mamm Stud 29:47–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage LJ (1954) The Foundations of Statistics. Wiley, New York. (2nd edn (1972) Dover, New York)

  • Smith VK, Desvousges WH (1987) An empirical analysis of the economic value of risk changes. J Polit Econ 95:89–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi WK (1993) The value of risks to life and health. J Econ Lit 31:1912–1946

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful for the significant comments from Richard Carson, Theodore Groves, Mark Jacobsen, and participants of the Environmental Economics Seminar at University of California, San Diego. In addition, we appreciate the helpful comments from the editor, Alistair Munro, as well as the two anonymous referees. We would like to thank Yukichika Kawata for helping us obtain the survey data. This work was supported by Grant-in-Aid for Young Scientists (B) Grant Number 2578176.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Masahide Watanabe.

Appendices

Appendix 1

The ambiguity attitude parameter, \({\alpha }\), can be intuitively interpreted by considering the familiar Ellsberg’s (1961) urn example. An urn contains 30 red balls and 60 green and blue balls in unspecified proportions. The subjects are asked to compare between bets on a red and a green ball. If they win (or lose), they get $100 (or $0). According to many experimental results, most people choose to bet on red, because they dislike an ambiguous situation but favor certain probability. Let the subjects be \(\upalpha \)-MEU maximizers. Then, the expected utility of a bet on a red ball is \(\frac{1}{3}{u}\left( \$ 100 \right) +\frac{2}{3}{u}(\$ 0)\), while that on a green ball is

$$\begin{aligned}&{\alpha }\; {\min }_{{p}\in \left[ {0,\frac{2}{3}} \right] } \left\{ {{pu}\left( {\$ 100} \right) +\left( {1-{p}} \right) {u}\left( {\$ 0} \right) } \right\} \nonumber \\&\qquad +\left( {1-{\alpha }} \right) {\max }_{{p}\in \left[ {0,\frac{2}{3}} \right] } \left\{ {{pu}\left( {\$ 100} \right) +\left( {1-{p}} \right) {u}\left( {\$ 0} \right) } \right\} , \end{aligned}$$

which is equivalent to \(\frac{2}{3}\left( {1-{\alpha }} \right) {u}\left( {\$ 100} \right) +\left( {\frac{1}{3}+\frac{2}{3}{\alpha }} \right) {u}\left( {\$ 0} \right) \). Thus, in this example, for them to bet on a red ball (i.e., have an ambiguity-averse attitude), \({\alpha }\) has to be greater than \(\frac{1}{2}\).

Appendix 2

Here, we show the detailed derivation of Eq. (9).

$$\begin{aligned} \Pr \left( {{A}_{ i} } \right)&= \Pr \left( {\textit{EU}^{\alpha }\left( {{p}_{1{i}}^{ h} ,{p}_{1{i}}^{ l}, {y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} ,{\alpha }} \right) >\textit{EU}^{\alpha }\left( {{p}_{0{ i}}^{ h}, {p}_{0{ i}}^{ l} ,{y}_{ i}, {\alpha }} \right) } \right) \\&= \Pr \left( {\textit{EU}\left( {{p}_{1{i}}^{\alpha } ,{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) >\textit{EU}\left( {{p}_{0{ i}}^{\alpha }, {y}_{ i} } \right) } \right) \\&= \Pr \left( \beta {\ln }\left( {{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) +\theta {p}_{1{i}}^{\alpha } {\ln }\left( {{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) +{c}_1 +{\epsilon }_{1{i}} >\beta \ln \left( {{y}_{ i} } \right) \right. \nonumber \\&\left. \quad +\theta {p}_{0{ i}}^{\alpha } {\ln }\left( {{y}_{ i} } \right) +{c}_0 +{\epsilon }_{0{ i}} \right) \\&= \Pr \left( {\epsilon }_{0{ i}} -{\epsilon }_{1{i}} <\beta \ln \left( {\frac{{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} }{{y}_{ i} }} \right) +{\theta }\left( {\alpha {p}}_{1{i}}^{ h} +\left( {1-{\alpha }} \right) {p}_{1{i}}^{ l} \right) {\ln }\left( {{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) \right. \\&\quad \left. -{\theta }\left( {{\alpha {p}}_{0{ i}}^{ h} +\left( {1-{\alpha }} \right) {p}_{0{ i}}^{ l} } \right) {\ln }\left( {{y}_{ i} } \right) +{c}_1 -{c}_0 \right) \\&= \Pr \left( {\epsilon }_{0{ i}} -{\epsilon }_{1{i}} <\beta \ln \left( {\frac{{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} }{{y}_{ i} }} \right) +\theta \alpha \ln \left( {\frac{\left( {{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) ^{{ p}_{1{i}}^{ h} }}{{y}_{ i}^{{ p}_{0{ i}}^{ h} } }} \right) \right. \\&\quad \left. +{\theta }\left( {1-{\alpha }} \right) \ln \left( {\frac{\left( {{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) ^{{ p}_{1{i}}^{ l} }}{{y}_{ i}^{{ p}_{0{ i}}^{ l} } }} \right) +{c}_1 -{c}_0 \right) \\&= \Pr \left( {\epsilon }_{ i} <\beta \ln \left( {\frac{{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} }{{y}_{ i} }} \right) +\theta \alpha \ln \left( {\frac{\left( {{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) ^{{ p}_{1{i}}^{ h} }}{{y}_{ i}^{{ p}_{0{ i}}^{ h} } }} \right) \right. \\&\quad \left. +{\theta }\left( {1-{\alpha }} \right) \ln \left( {\frac{\left( {{y}_{ i} -{t}_{ i} } \right) ^{{ p}_{1{i}}^{ l} }}{{y}_{ i}^{{ p}_{0{ i}}^{ l} } }} \right) +{c} \right) , \end{aligned}$$

where \({\epsilon }_{i} \equiv {\epsilon }_{0{i}} -{\epsilon }_{1{i}} ,{c}\equiv {c}_1 -{c}_0 \). The second, third, and fourth equalities hold—the second because of Eq. (2), the third because of Eq. (8), and the fourth because of the definition of \({p}_{j}^{\alpha } \).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Watanabe, M., Fujimi, T. Evaluating Change in Objective Ambiguous Mortality Probability: Valuing Reduction in Ambiguity Size and Risk Level. Environ Resource Econ 60, 1–15 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-013-9754-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-013-9754-8

Keywords

JEL Classification:

Navigation