Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Catastrophic climate change, population ethics and intergenerational equity

  • Published:
Climatic Change Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Climate change threatens irreversible and dangerous impacts, possibly leading to extinction. The most relevant trade-off then may not be between present and future consumption but between present consumption and the mere existence of future generations. To investigate this trade-off, we build an integrated assessment model that explicitly accounts for the risk of extinction of future generations. Using the class of number-dampened utilitarian social welfare functions, we compare different climate policies that change the probability of catastrophic outcomes yielding an early extinction. We analyse the role of inequality aversion and population ethics. Low inequality aversion and a preference for large populations favour the most ambitious climate policy, although there are cases where the effect of inequality aversion on the preferred policy is reversed. This is due to the fact that a higher inequality aversion both decreases the welfare loss of reducing consumption of the current generation and also decreases the welfare gain of reducing the future risk of extinction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The stochastic nature of catastrophes is also sometimes explicitly accounted for (Peck and Teisberg 1995; Lontzek et al. 2015; Lemoine and Traeger 2016).

  2. This modelling strategy follows a strand of literature (Cropper 1976; Clarke and Reed 1994; Gjerde et al. 1999; Tsur and Zemel 2009) that considers that abrupt climate change introduces an irreversible regime shift. Characteristic (ii) is not an accurate description of how human extinction might come about (it may take several years). But this simplification can be justified by saying that the extinction process is predetermined and rapidly yields a situation that is equivalent to extinction in terms of welfare (for instance because the extinction may involve a lot of suffering for many years where people live very bad lives).

  3. See for instance Jamieson (2007) or Shue (2014) for examples of such approaches to climate justice.

  4. The economic literature usually uses the term ‘generalised utilitarian’ rather than prioritarian as we do in the introduction. The formula here is prioritarian with respect to consumption; it may be viewed as utilitarian if function \(u(c)=\frac {c^{1-\eta }}{1-\eta }\) is the true utility function. There exists a limited literature in population ethics proposing alternatives to this generalised utilitarian formula, for instance equally distributed equivalent criteria (Fleurbaey and Zuber 2015), egalitarian criteria (Blackorby et al. 1996) or rank-dependent criteria (Asheim and Zuber 2014; 2016).

  5. See Ramsey (1928) and Stern (2007) for arguments on why we should treat generations in a symmetric way. Observe that one reason for discounting, namely the possibility that future generations may not exist, is not yet accounted for, given that the existence (or non-existence) of generations is for the moment known for sure. The next section will show that the extinction risk creates endogenous discounting.

  6. The notion of the neutral level of utility is important in the literature on population axiologies, as many paradoxes or principles (for instance ‘avoiding a repugnant conclusion’ or the ‘mere addition principle’), rely on the notion (see Arrhenius (2020)). The notion has been defended for instance by Holtug (2001). Still, there are discussions about the exact meaning of ‘a life is worth living’ and the level of \(\underline {c}\).

  7. Section S.A. in the Electronic Supplementary Material considers the possibility that policy choices affect population size from a theoretical point of view.

  8. See also Section S.A.2. of the Electronic Supplementary Material for a clarification of the discount rate and the underlying Ramsey formula in our framework.

  9. In this paper, we assume a decreasing Total Factor Productivity (TFP) growth due to the very long time horizon considered (of the order of 10,000 years). Indeed, assuming constant TFP growth would bring unrealistically high levels of consumption per capita at the time scales considered. This issue is usually not discussed in the literature due to the shorter time horizon used in models (typically a few hundred years).

  10. We do not include the 2 C scenario in this section for the sake of clarity.

  11. The stream of consumption is lower over the whole period due to the fact that we do not account for climate damages. This is not the case if climate damages are accounted for, cf. Figure S.3 in the Electronic Supplementary Material

  12. See Section S.E.2. of the Electronic Supplementary Material for the comparison between the 3 C and BAU scenarios, and between the 3 C and 2 C scenarios.

  13. See Section S.E.2 of the Electronic Supplementary Material for the comparison between the 3 C and BAU scenarios, and between the 3 C and 2 C scenarios.

References

  • Ackerman F, Stanton EA, Bueno R (2010) Fat tails, exponents, extreme uncertainty: simulating catastrophe in DICE. Ecol Econ 69(8):1657–1665. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2010.03.013

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adler MD (2012) Well-being and fair distribution: beyond cost-benefit analysis. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Adler MD, Treich N (2015) Prioritarianism and climate change. Environ Resour Econ 62(2):279–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ambrosi P, Hourcade JC, Hallegatte S, Lecocq F, Dumas P, Duong MH (2003) Optimal control models and elicitation of attitudes towards climate damages. Environ Model Assess 8(3):133–147. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1025586922143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrhenius G (2020) Population ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Asheim G, Zuber S (2014) Escaping the repugnant conclusion: rank-discounted utilitarianism with variable population. Theor Econ 9:629–650

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim G, Zuber S (2016) Evaluating intergenerational risks. J Math Econ 65:73–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby C, Bossert W, Donaldson D (1996) Leximin population ethics. Math Soc Sci 31:115–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby C, Bossert W, Donaldson D (1997) Critical-level utilitarianism and the population-ethics dilemma. Econ Philos 13(02):197. https://doi.org/10.1017/S026626710000448X

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby C, Bossert W, Donaldson D (2005) Population issues in social choice theory, welfare economics, and ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bommier A, Lanz B, Zuber S (2015) Models-as-usual for unusual risks? On the value of catastrophic climate change. J Environ Econ Manag 74:1–22. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jeem.2015.07.003

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boucekkine R, Fabbri G, Gozzi F (2014) Egalitarianism under population size: age-structure does matter. J Math Econ 55:86–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2004) Weighing lives. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (2010) The most important thing about climate change. In: Boston J, Bradstock A, Eng D (eds) Public policy: why ethics matters, ANU Press, pp 101–116

  • Broome J (2012) Climate matters: ethics in a warming world, 1st edn. Amnesty International global ethics series W.W. Norton, New York

  • Cafaro P (2012) Climate ethics and population policy. Wiley Interdiscip Rev Clim Change 3(1):45–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke HR, Reed WJ (1994) Consumption/pollution tradeoffs in an environment vulnerable to pollution-related catastrophic collapse. J Econ Dyn Control 18(5):991–1010. https://doi.org/10.1016/0165-1889(94)90042-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cropper M (1976) Regulating activities with catastrophic environmental effects. J Environ Econ Manag 3(1):1–15. https://doi.org/10.1016/0095-0696(76)90009-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumas P, Espagne E, Perrissin-Fabert B, Pottier A (2012) Comprehensive description of RESPONSE. CIRED Working Paper 41-2012, CIRED

  • Field CB, Barros VR, Dokken DJ, Mach KJ, Mastrandrea MD (eds.) (2014) Climate change 2014: Impacts, adaptation, and vulnerability. part a: global and sectoral aspects. contribution of the working group ii to the fifth assessment report of the intergovernmental panel on climate change. Cambridge University Press

  • Fleurbaey M, Zuber S (2015) Discounting, beyond utilitarianism. Econ Open-Access Open-Ass E-J 9(2015-12):1–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaffin SR, O’Neill BC (1997) Population and global warming with and without co2 targets. Popul Environ 18(4):389–413

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gjerde J, Grepperud S, Kverndokk S (1999) Optimal climate policy under the possibility of a catastrophe. Resour Energy Econ 21(3-4):289–317. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0928-7655(99)00006-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holtug N (2001) On the value of coming into existence. J Ethics 5:361–384

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hope C (2006) The marginal impact of CO2 from PAGE2002: an integrated assessment model incorporating the IPCC’s five reasons for concern. Integr Assess 6(1):19–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Hope C, Anderson J, Wenman P (1993) Policy analysis of the greenhouse effect - an application of the PAGE model. Energy Policy 21(3):327–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsiang SM, Burke M, Miguel E (2013) Quantifying the influence of climate on human conflict. Science 341(6151):1235367–1235367. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1235367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka T (1982) Average utilitarianisms. Analysis 42(2):65–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • IIASA (2014) AR5 scenario database

  • Jamieson D (2007) When utilitarians should be virtue theorists. Utilitas 19:160–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly DL, Kolstad CD (2001) Malthus and climate change: betting on a stable population. J Environ Econ Manag 41(2):135–161

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolstad C, Urama K, Broome J, Bruvoll A, Cariño Olvera M, Fullerton D, Gollier C, Hanemann W, Hassan R, Jotzo F, Khan M, Meyer L, Mundaca L (2014) Social, economic, and ethical concepts and methods. In: Edenhofer O, Pichs-Madruga R, Sokona Y, Farahani E, Kadner S, Seyboth K, Adler A, Baum I, Brunner S, Eickemeier P, Kriemann B, Savolainen J, Schlömer S, Cv Stechow, Zwickel T, Minx J (eds) Climate change 2014: mitigation of climate change. Contribution of working group III to the fifth assessment report of the intergovernmental panel on climate change, cambridge university press, cambridge, United Kingdom and New york, NY, USA

  • Lawson N, Spears D (2018) Optimal population and exhaustible resource constraints. J Popul Econ 31(1):295–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lemoine D, Traeger CP (2016) Economics of tipping the climate dominoes. Nat Clim Chang 6(5):514–519. https://doi.org/10.1038/nclimate2902

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenton TM, Held H, Kriegler E, Hall JW, Lucht W, Rahmstorf S, Schellnhuber HJ (2008) Tipping elements in the Earth’s climate system. Proce Natl Acad Sci 105(6):1786–1793. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0705414105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lontzek TS, Cai Y, Judd KL, Lenton TM (2015) Stochastic integrated assessment of climate tipping points indicates the need for strict climate policy. Nat Clim Chang 5(5):441–444. https://doi.org/10.1038/nclimate2570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy JJ, Canziani OF, Leary NA, Dokken DJ, White KS (eds) (2001) Climate change 2001: impacts, adaptation, and vulnerability. Contribution of the Working Group II to the Third Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Millner A (2013) On welfare frameworks and catastrophic climate risks. J Environ Econ Manag 65(2):310–325. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jeem.2012.09.006

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ng YK (1986) Social criteria for evaluating population change: an alternative to the blackorby-Donaldson criterion. J Public Econ 29(3):375–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ng YK (1989) What should we do about future generations? Impossibility of Parfit’s theory x. Econ Philos 5:235–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus WD (1994) Managing the global commons: the economics of climate change. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus WD, Boyer J (2000) Warming the world: economic models of global warming. MIT Press, Cambridge Mass

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Peck SC, Teisberg TJ (1995) Optimal CO2 control policy with stochastic losses from temperature rise. Clim Chang 31(1):19–34. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01092979

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pottier A, Espagne E, Fabert BP, Dumas P (2015) The comparative impact of integrated assessment models’ structures on optimal mitigation policies. Environ Model Assess 20(5):453–473. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10666-015-9443-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey F (1928) A mathematical theory of saving. Econ J 38:543–559

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reuveny R (2007) Climate change-induced migration and violent conflict. Polit Geogr 26(6):656–673. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.polgeo.2007.05.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scovronick N, Budolfson MB, Dennig F, Fleurbaey M, Siebert A, Socolow RH, Spears D, Wagner F (2017) Impact of population growth and population ethics on climate change mitigation policy. Proc Natl Acad Sci 114(46):12338–12343

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherwood SC, Huber M (2010) An adaptability limit to climate change due to heat stress. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107(21):9552–9555. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0913352107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shue H (2014) Climate justice. vulnerability and protection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick H (1907) The methods of ethics. McMillan

  • Steffen W, Rockström J, Richardson K, Lenton TM, Folke C, Liverman D, Summerhayes CP, Barnosky AD, Cornell SE, Crucifix M, Donges JF, Fetzer I, Lade SJ, Scheffer M, Winkelmann R, Schellnhuber HJ (2018) Trajectories of the earth system in the anthropocene. Proce Natl Acad Sci 115(33):8252–8259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern NH (2007) The economics of climate change: the stern review. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tol RSJ (1997) On the optimal control of carbon dioxide emissions: an application of FUND. Environ Model Assess 2(3):151–163. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1019017529030

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsur Y, Zemel A (2009) Endogenous discounting and climate policy. Environ Resour Econ 44(4):507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner G, Weitzman ML (2015) Climate shock – the economic consequences of a hotter planet. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman ML (2012) GHG Targets as insurance against catastrophic climate damages. J Public Econ Theory 14(2):221–244. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9779.2011.01539.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank the reviewers and editors for their helpful comments. We thank Mark B. Budolfson, Francis Dennig, Maddalenna Ferranna, Noah Scovronick, Robert H. Socolow and audiences at workshops and seminars in Princeton and Paris for comments and advice.

Funding

This research has been supported by the Agence nationale de la recherche through the Fair-ClimPop project (ANR-16-CE03-0001-01) and Investissements d’Avenir program (ANR-10-LABX-93). Financial support from the Swedish foundation for humanities and social sciences (Anslag har erhallits från Stiftelsen Riksbankens Jubileumsfond) and from Princeton Universitys Program in Science, Technology and Environmental Policy (STEP) is also gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aurélie Méjean.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Author attributions

A.M., A.P., M.F. and S.Z. jointly wrote the paper, designed the research and analysed the results. A.M. and A.P. conducted model simulations. A.M. generated figures and tables. A.P. developed the original model.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(PDF 0.99 MB)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Méjean, A., Pottier, A., Fleurbaey, M. et al. Catastrophic climate change, population ethics and intergenerational equity. Climatic Change 163, 873–890 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10584-020-02899-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10584-020-02899-9

Keywords

Navigation