Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Illusion of Merit and the Demons of Economic Meritocracy: Which are the Legitimate Expectations of the Market?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“The ideas in the minds of men correspond to the word merit, shall, as everyone knows, be infinitely different: they change the subject, grade, purpose, measuring not only between nations and peoples, but likewise between classes and classes of the same city” (Melchiorre Gioja, Del Merito e Delle Ricompense).

“Success is an ugly thing. Men are deceived by its false resemblances to merit.... They confound the brilliance of the firmament with the star-shaped footprints of a duck in the mud” (Victor Hugo, Les Misérables).

Abstract

Meritocracy is gaining momentum in public discourse, being close to the determinants of people’s demand of social justice (equality of opportunity, social mobility). Conversely, in Academia meritocracy is the object of harsh critiques. The meritocratic rhetoric brings people to overlook the factors which contributed to their success (unequal starting conditions, luck) over their individual actions, legitimating socioeconomic inequalities. Recently, it has been argued that market-driven societies foster the problems related to meritocracy. The concept of merit, conceived as the value of the individual contribution to the common good of society, is absorbed by market value. While we share the concerns on meritocracy, we question the idea that those are necessarily connected to the market sphere. To prove that, our paper digs in the theological roots of the concept of merit to better understand meritocracy. We inquire Pelagius–Augustine debate on human merit and salvation, and its influence on Rawls’s critique of meritocracy. We base on the “Augustinian” Rawls our argument that market is not a meritocratic domain, but that in market there is space for merit conceived as ‘legitimate expectations.’ Our aim is to prove that merit can find some space in market societies without incurring in the problems of meritocracy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The Pelagius/Augustine debate, in fact, has had a great impact on the history of Western thought. The logic of merit has always been widespread because it was often linked to the concepts of virtue and reward. The Greek and Roman philosophers made significant use of the concept of merit and its cognates, as did non-Western religions such as Buddhism, Confucianism, and Judaism (it would be enough to consider the book of Job, centered on a critique of the “illusion” of merit). We chose Pelagius and Augustine because they are strictly connected to the economic developments of meritocratic discourse. A key period in the interconnectedness of theology and the economy is the Protestant Reformation and Catholic Controriforma in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. A millennium later, the revival of meritocracy was also a revival of Augustine’s polemic against Pelagius (Luther was an Augustinian monk), and the original spirit of capitalism was in reality generated by a radical critique of the theology of merit that Luther expressed. Paradoxically, even though it was initially rejected, this aspect has become the cornerstone of a new meritocratic, capitalistic logic that exists at the heart of the very countries built on the ancient anti-meritocratic protestant ethics. The idea of Augustinian salvation for sola gratia rather than based on merit was at the center of the Protestant Reformation; however, this notion eventually produced market societies that realized the exact opposite approach.

  2. This is not to say that the young Rawls conceived of himself as an Augustinian author. He believed that Augustine, together with Aquinas, was responsible for the naturalization of Christian ethics, with which he strongly contrasted (See Weithman 2016).

  3. In the market, the credit acquired through individual performance does not always correspond to the return the individual gets from a mutually beneficial transaction. Merit is also a backward-looking concept: what people deserve can depend on how they behaved in the past. But mutual benefit is defined in terms of people’s circumstances and beliefs at the time at which they trade. Whereas the logic of merit lies in the temporal dimensions of past and future, legitimate expectations of economic actors could be predicated only through the present tense or the conditional tense. This is because economic circumstances can change unpredictably, and thus efforts that were made with reasonable expectations of return may turn out not to be rewarded by the market. This proves once more that other logics rule market transactions together with the meritocratic one and that the object of merit is defined more by mutual benefit than by individual efforts. Given these premises, meritocracy should find very little space in the market.

  4. Economics is all built on the idea of perfection—perfect competition, perfect rationality, perfect information. Every deviation from perfection has been classified as a failure of the market. Perfectionism seems well-suited for the meritocratic logic that, as we showed through Pelagius, was born as a discourse for the élite. Aristocracy, virtue, and rewards are all concepts intimately related to merit. Hence, could we assume that in circumstances of perfect concurrence the market is ruled by the logic of merit? Is it correct to argue that perfectly rational economic actors, endowed with perfect information, will get returns corresponding to the net-worth of their individual actions? The axioms of micro-economics prove how erroneous such inferences can be. Thus, when we affirm that meritocracy is not a market virtue, we mean that even in its perfect form the market is ruled by elements other than individual merits. Since we know that markets are not perfect and that neither are the individuals who every day produce and exchange goods and services, we should avoid looking for merits in a non-meritocratic domain.

  5. From the microeconomic side, it emerges clearly that meritocracy—when merit becomes the only parameter to describe markets—is not only against equality, but it can lead also to inefficiency. A person who expects a return major than the benefits she provides to the trading party, that is, a person who refuses the notion that the trading party freely judges the value of the services they perform or the goods they need, creates barriers to the achievement of mutual benefit. The opportunity of mutual advantage, the incentive mechanism that the market spontaneously produces (Sugden 2018) to lead people where they can benefit and be benefitted most by each other, risks being distorted by individuals’ beliefs in the deserving nature of their actions.

References

  • Alesina, A., & Angeletos, G. M. (2005). Fairness and redistribution. American Economic Review, 95(4), 960–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alesina, A., Stantcheva, S., & Teso, E. (2018). Intergenerational mobility and preferences for redistribution. American Economic Review, 108(2), 521–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (1993). Value in ethics and economics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, A. K. 2018. The myth of meritocracy: Who really gets what they deserve? The guardian. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/news/2018/oct/19/the-myth-of-meritocracy-who-really-gets-what-they-deserve.

  • Arrow, K., Bowles, S., & Durlauf, S. N. (Eds.). (2000). Meritocracy and economic inequality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banner, M. (2009). Christian ethics: A brief history (Vol. 19). Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D. (1972). Meritocracy and equality. The Public Interest, 29, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D. A. (2012). Meritocracy is a good thing. New Perspectives Quarterly, 29(4), 9–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bénabou, R., & Tirole, J. (2006). Incentives and prosocial behavior. American Economic Review, 96(5), 1652–1678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloodworth, J. (2016). The myth of meritocracy: Why working-class kids still get working-class jobs (provocations series). London: Biteback Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradstock, A., & Rowland, C. (Eds.). (2008). Radical Christian writings: A reader. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bray, G. (1998). Romans. Chicago: Fitzroy Deadborn Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, P. (1968). Pelagius and his supporters: Aims and environment. The Journal of Theological Studies, 19(1), 3–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, P. (1970). The patrons of pelagius: The roman aristocracy between east and west. The Journal of Theological Studies, 21(1), 56–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, P. (2012). Through the eye of a needle: Wealth, the fall of Rome, and the making of Christianity in the west, 350–550 AD. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, P. (2013). Augustine of Hippo: A biography. Univ of California Press.

  • Bruni, L., & Sugden, R. (2008). Fraternity: Why the market need not be a morally free zone. Economics & Philosophy, 24(1), 35–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruni, L., & Sugden, R. (2013). Reclaiming virtue ethics for economics. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 27(4), 141–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnevale, A. P., Schmidt, P., & Strohl, J. (2020). The merit myth: How our colleges favor the rich and divide America. New York: New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, S. D. (1986). Aristocracy and meritocracy in merchant banking. The British Journal of Sociology, 37(2), 180–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charité, J., Fisman, R., & Kuziemko, I. (2015). Reference points and redistributive preferences: Experimental evidence (No. w21009). Cambridge: National Bureau of Economic Research.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Bruyn, T. (1993). Pelagius’s commentary on St. Paul’s Epistle to Romans. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dempsey, J. J. 1937. Pelagius’s Commentary on St. Paul. A theological studies.

  • Evans, R. F. (2010). Pelagius: Inquiries and Reappraisals. Eugene: Wipf and Stock Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. H. (2016). Success and luck: Good fortune and the myth of meritocracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2015). Communication and the evolution of society. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1998). Law, legislation and liberty: A new statement of the liberal principles of justice and political economy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, C. (2013). Twilight of the Elites: America after Meritocracy. Portland: Broadway Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heiserman, N., & Simpson, B. (2017). Higher inequality increases the gap in the perceived merit of the rich and poor. Social Psychology Quarterly, 80(3), 243–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrnstein, R. J., & Murray, C. A. (1994). The bell curve: Reshaping of American life by differences in intelligence. Mumbai: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jost, J. T., Pelham, B. W., Sheldon, O., & Ni Sullivan, B. (2003). Social inequality and the reduction of ideological dissonance on behalf of the system: Evidence of enhanced system justification among the disadvantaged. European Journal of Social Psychology, 33(1), 13–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. H. (1935). The ethics of competition. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laird, P. W. (2017). How business historians can save the world-from the fallacy of self-made success. Business History, 59(8), 1201–1217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Littler, J. (2017). Against meritocracy. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. ([1983]2013). After virtue. A&C Black.

  • Markovits, D. (2019). The Meritocracy Trap: Or. Penguin UK: The Tyranny of Just Deserts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matteoli, S. 2011. Alle origini della teologia di Pelagio: Tematiche e fonti della Expositiones XIII epistularum Pauli (Vol. 6). Fabrizio Serra Editore.

  • McGrath, A. E. (2005). Iustitia Dei: A history of the Christian doctrine of justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milbank, J. (2003). Being reconciled: Ontology and pardon. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, E. (2019). The theology of liberalism: Political philosophy and the justice of God. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piff, P. K., Kraus, M. W., & Keltner, D. (2018). Unpacking the inequality paradox: The psychological roots of inequality and social class. Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 57, pp. 53–124). Cambridge: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piketty, T. (2020). Capital and ideology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice (Revised). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J., Cohen, J., & Adams, R. M. (2010). A brief inquiry into the meaning of sin and faith. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. J. (2012). What money can’t buy: The moral limits of markets. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. J. (2020). The tyranny of merit: What’s become of the common good? London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. J. (2013). Market reasoning as moral reasoning: Why economists should re-engage with political philosophy. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 27(4), 121–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satz, D. (2010). Why some things should not be for sale: The moral limits of markets. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scaggs, A. 2018. How to make a living in the cult of meritocracy. Financial Times. Retrieved from https://ftalphaville.ft.com/2018/07/09/1531120621000/How-to-make-a-living-in-the-cult-of-meritocracy/.

  • Schaff, P. (2007). Augustine of Hippo. Saint’s Augustine Anti-Pelagian Works. New York: Cosimo Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. (1985). Political theology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2000). Merit and justice. In K. J. Arrow, S. Bowles, & S. N. Durlauf (Eds.), Meritocracy and economic inequality (pp. 5–18). Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Son Hing, L. S., Bobocel, D. R., Zanna, M. P., Garcia, D. M., Gee, S. S., & Orazietti, K. (2011). The merit of meritocracy. Journal of personality and social psychology, 101(3), 433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2018). The community of advantage: A behavioural economist’s defence of the market. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, M. (2013). The mirage of merit: Reconstituting the ‘ideal academic.’ Australian Feminist Studies, 28(76), 127–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valero, J. B. (1982). El estoicismo de Pelagio. Estudios Eclesiasticos Madrid, 57(220), 39–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vlastos, G. (1975). Human worth, merit, and equality. Moral concepts (pp. 141–152). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinzierl, M. (2017). Popular acceptance of inequality due to innate brute luck and support for classical benefit-based taxation. Journal of Public Economics, 155(C), 54–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weithman, P. (2016). Rawls, political liberalism and reasonable faith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young, M. (1958). The rise of the meritocracy 1870–2033: An essay on education and society. London: Thames and Hudson.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

To the editor and the two anonymous referees goes our gratitude. Their comments helped significantly to improve the quality of our manuscript and coherence of our argument. We thank also Robert Sugden and Francesco Guala for their comments on the earlier version of this manuscript.

Funding

The authors received no specific funding for this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paolo Santori.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bruni, L., Santori, P. The Illusion of Merit and the Demons of Economic Meritocracy: Which are the Legitimate Expectations of the Market?. J Bus Ethics 176, 415–427 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-020-04727-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-020-04727-7

Keywords

Navigation