Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Virtues of Equality and Dissensus: MacIntyre in a Dialogue with Rancière and Mouffe

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Research in business ethics has largely ignored questions of equality and dissensus, raised by theorists of radical democracy. Alasdair MacIntyre, whose work has been very influential in business ethics, has developed a novel approach to virtue ethics rooted in both Aristotelian practical philosophy and a Marxian appreciation of radical democracy. In this paper, we bring MacIntyre into conversation with Jacques Rancière and Chantal Mouffe and argue the following: first, MacIntyre’s work has significant similarities with Rancière and Mouffe, thus suggesting that MacIntyrean business ethics has the potential to address the concerns of radical democrats; second, the MacIntyrean business ethics literature has not adequately incorporated the aspects of Macntyre’s work addressing concerns regarding equality and dissensus and future work should pay more attention to these concerns.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Moore ( 2017, pp. 191–192) explains the MacIntyrean framework as follows: “The key to developing from the individual and communal virtue ethics approach, to explore what we might call the intermediate level of organizations was, of course, MacIntyre’s claim that practices have to be institutionalized if they are to survive for any length of time. And it was this idea of organizations as practice-institution combinations which gave us the particular way of thinking about—this particular metaphor for—organizations which we have explored at length. We saw how practices focus on the achievement of internal goods, and institutions on external goods, and, while they form a ‘single causal order,’ this also exposed a fundamental tension inherent in all organizations—the tension between the pursuit of internal versus external goods, in which ‘the ideals and the creativity of the practice are always vulnerable to the acquisitiveness of the institution, in which the cooperative care for common goods of the practice is always vulnerable to the competitiveness of the institution.’”

  2. See for example Rod Dreher’s (2017) The Benedict Option. MacIntyre (2007, p. xv) resolutely rejects conservatism: “[C]onservatism is in too many ways a mirror image of the liberalism that it professedly opposes. Its commitment to a way of life structured by a free market economy is a commitment to an individualism as corrosive as that of liberalism… Such conservatism is as alien to the projects of After Virtue as liberalism is. And the figure cut by present-day conservative moralists, with their inflated and self-righteous unironic rhetoric, should be set alongside those figures whom I identified in chapter 3 of After Virtue as notable characters in the cultural dramas of modernity: that of the therapist, who has in the last 20 years become bemused by biochemical discoveries; that of the corporate manager, who is now mouthing formulas that she or he learned in a course in business ethics, while still trying to justify her or his pretensions to expertise; and that of the aesthete, who is presently emerging from a devotion to conceptual art. So the conservative moralist has become one more stock character in the scripted conversations of the ruling elites of advanced modernity. But those elites never have the last word.”

  3. MacIntyre (2016, p. 131) says, “We thus find in two very different cultural settings, Japanese and British, with work that makes use of two very different technologies, those of automobile manufacture and of television, the same contrast between two kinds of activity, one a mode of practice in which workers are able to pursue ends that they themselves have identified as worthwhile, in the pursuit of which they hold themselves to standards of excellence that they have made their own, the other an organization of activity such that their work is directed toward ends that are the ends of administrators and managers imposed upon their activities. In the former the primary responsibility for the quality of the end products of the work lies with the workers, who in this respect are treated as agents with rational and aesthetic powers, even though their labor is still exploited.”

  4. Leist (2011) criticizes MacIntyre’s teleological conception of morality arguing that Mouffe’s agonistic theory avoids this problem. In responding to Leist, MacIntyre (2011) argues that any adequate account of human nature is necessarily be teleological, and careful analysis of “the virtues as specific to this or that time and place, provides us with grounds for making universal claims both about human nature and about the functioning of the virtues” (p. 309).

References

  • Althusser, L. (1971). Ideology and ideological state apparatuses (notes towards an investigation). In Brewster, B. (tr.), Lenin and philosophy and other essays. Monthly Review, New York.

  • Althusser, L. (2014). On the reproduction of capitalism: Ideology and ideological state apparatuses (trans. G. Goshgarian). New York: Verso.

  • Barney, J., & Hansen, M. (1994). Trustworthiness as a source of competitive advantage. Strategic Management Journal,15, 175–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beabout, G. (2012). Management as a domain-relative practice that requires and develops practical wisdom. Business Ethics Quarterly,22(2), 405–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R. (2008). Why business cannot be a practice. Analyse & Kritik,30, 229–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R. (2013). Managerial work in a practice embodying institution. Journal of Business Ethics,113(4), 679–690.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R. (2015). MacIntyre’s influence on business ethics. In A. Sison, G. Beabout, & I. Ferrero (Eds.), Handbook of virtue ethics in business and management (pp. 1–9). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R., & Knight, K. (2012). Virtue and meaningful work. Business Ethics Quarterly,22(2), 433–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R., & Moore, G. (2011). MacIntyre: Neo-Aristotelianism and organization theory. In H. Tsoukas & R. Chia (Eds.), Philosophy and organization theory, research in the sociology of organizations (Vol. 32, pp. 85–121). Binglry: Emerald Group Publishing Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C. (2014). Macintyre’s After virtue: A phenomenological reading. Cadernos do PET Filosofia,5(9), 42–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C. (2015). Rival versions of corporate governance as rival theories of agency. Philosophy of Management,14(1), 67–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C. (2018). Networks of giving and receiving in an organizational context: Dependent rational animals and MacIntyrean business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly,28(4), 377–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C., & Couch, R. (2015). The virtue of participatory governance: A MacIntyrean alternative to stakeholder maximization. Business Ethics: A European Review,24(S2), 130–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackledge, P. (2014). Alasdair MacIntyre as a Critic of Marxism. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly,88(4), 705–724.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackledge, P., & Davidson, N. (2011). Introduction: The unknown Alasdair MacIntyre. In P. Blackledge & N. Davidson (Eds.), Alasdair MacIntyre’s engagement with Marxism. Chicago: Haymarket Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breen, K. (2012). Production and productive reason. New Political Economy,17(5), 611–632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, T. (2011). Revolutionary Aristotelianism? The political thought of Aristotle, Marx, and MacIntyre. In P. Blackledge & K. Knight (Eds.), Virtue and politics: Alasdair MacIntyre's revolultionary Aristotelianism (pp. 35–53). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, O. (2010). Jacques Rancière. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreher, R. (2017). The Benedict option: A strategy for Christians in a post-Christian nation. New York: Sentinel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J. S. (2002). Deliberative democracy and beyond: Liberals, critics, contestations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero, I., & Sison, A. J. G. (2014). A quantitative analysis of authors, schools and themes in virtue ethics articles in business ethics and management journals (1980–2011). Business Ethics: A European Review,23(4), 375–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996). Between fact and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy (trans. W. Rehg). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Hallward, P. (2006). Staging equality: On Rancière’s theatocracy. New Left Review,37, 109–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. (1996). Organizational ethics and the good life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J., Moriarty, J., & Norman, W. (2010). Business ethics and (or as) political philosophy. Business Ethics Quarterly,20(3), 427–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. (2002). Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly,12(2), 235–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khan, G. (2013). Critical republicanism: Jürgen Habermas and Chantal Mouffe. Contemporary Political Theory,12(4), 318–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, K. (2007). Aristotelian philosophy: Ethics and politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre. London: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, K. (2008). Goods. Philosophy of Management,7(1), 107–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leist, A. (2011). Troubling oneself with ends. In P. Blackledge & K. Knight (Eds.), Virtue and politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s revolutionary Aristotelianism (pp. 195–227). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1957). What Morality Is Not. Philosophy,32, 325–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1973). Ideology, social science and revolution. Comparative Politics,5(3), 340–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1978). The end of ideology and the end of the end of ideology. Against the self-images of the age (pp. 3–11). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1984). Marxism and Christianity. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1989). Whose justice? Which rationality?. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1990). Three rival versions of moral enquiry: Encyclopaedia, genealogy, and tradition. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1998a). Plain persons and moral philosophy: Rules, virtues and goods. In K. Knight (Ed.), The MacIntyre reader (pp. 136–152). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1998b). The theses on Feuerbach: A road not taken. In K. Knight (Ed.), The MacIntyre reader (pp. 223–234). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1998c). Politics, philosophy, and the common good. In K. Knight (Ed.), The MacIntyre reader (pp. 235–252). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1999). Dependent rational animals. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2006a). The ends of life, the ends of philosophical writing. The tasks of philosophy: Selected essays, volume 1 (pp. 125–142). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2006b). Natural law as subversive: The case of Aquinas. Ethics and politics: Selected essays, volume 2 (pp. 41–63). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2006c). Social structures and their threats to moral agency. Ethics and politics: Selected essays, volume 2 (pp. 186–204). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2007). After virtue (3rd ed.). London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2011). Where we were, where we are, where we need to be. In P. Blackledge & K. Knight (Eds.), Virtue and politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s revolutionary Aristotelianism (pp. 307–334). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2016). Ethics in the conflicts of modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K. (1988). Economic and philosophical manuscripts of 1844. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2005a). Corporate character: Modern virtue ethics and the virtuous corporation. Business Ethics Quarterly,15(4), 659–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2005b). Humanizing business: A modern virtues ethics approach. Business Ethics Quarterly,15(2), 237–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2008). Re-imagining the morality of management: A modern virtue ethics approach. Business Ethics Quarterly,18(4), 483–511.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2012). The virtue of governance, the governance of virtue. Business Ethics Quarterly,22(2), 293–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2017). Virtue at work: Ethics for individuals, managers, and organizations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G., & Beadle, R. (2006). In search of organizational virtue in business: Agents, goods, practices, institutions and environments. Organization Studies,27(3), 369–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G., & Grandy, G. (2017). Bringing morality back in: Institutional theory and MacIntyre. Journal of Management Inquiry,26(2), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (2000). The democratic paradox. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (2005). On the political. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (2018). For a left populism. Brooklyn: Verso Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rancière, J. (1999). Disagreement (trans. J. Rose). University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

  • Rancière, J. (2003). The philosopher and his poor (trans. J. Drury, C. Oster, & A. Parker). Duke University Press, Durham.

  • Rancière, J. (2008). Jacques Rancière and indisciplinarity (interview conducted by M. Baronian & M. Rosello, trans. G. Elliot). Art & Research: A Journal of Ideas, Contexts, and Methods, 2(1), 1–10.

  • Rancière, J. (2010). Dissensus: On politics and aesthetics (trans. S. Corcoran). New York: Continuum.

  • Rancière, J. (2011). Althusser’s lesson (trans. E. Battista). London: Continuum.

  • Rancière, J. (2012). Proletarian nights: The workers’ dream in nineteenth-century France (trans. J. Drury). London: Verso.

  • Robson, A. (2015). Constancy and integrity: (un)measurable virtues? Business ethics: A European review,24(S2), S115–S129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandberg, J., & Tsoukas, H. (2011). Grasping the logic of practice: Theorizing through practical rationality. Academy of Management Review,36(2), 338–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnicks, M. (2014). Practices, governance, and politics: Applying MacIntyre’s ethics to business. Business Ethics Quarterly,24(2), 229–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanke, J. (2011). Jacques Rancière: An introduction. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas, H. (2018). Strategy and virtue: Developing strategy-as-practice through virtue ethics. Strategic Organization,16(3), 323–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Krogh, G., Haefliger, S., Spaeth, S., & Wallin, M. W. (2012). Carrots and rainbows: Motivation and social practice in open source software development. MIS Quarterly,36(2), 649–676.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilcox, T. (2012). Human resource management in a compartmentalised world: Whither moral agency. Journal of Business Ethics,111(1), 85–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeoman, R. (2014). Conceptualising meaningful work as a fundamental human need. Journal of Business Ethics,125(2), 235–251.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

No funding was receiving for this study.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Caleb Bernacchio.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

All authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Couch, R., Bernacchio, C. The Virtues of Equality and Dissensus: MacIntyre in a Dialogue with Rancière and Mouffe. J Bus Ethics 164, 633–642 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-019-04400-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-019-04400-8

Keywords

Navigation