Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Beware of the Watchdog: Rethinking the Normative Justification of Gatekeeper Liability

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One of the prevailing explanations of the corporate scandals of the Enron era and the recent financial crisis is the failure of professional gatekeepers—such as auditors, corporate lawyers, and securities analysts—to detect and disrupt corporate misconduct. The alleged solution to this failure—typically proposed and justified on consequentialist grounds—is to impose legal liability on professionals. The purpose of this paper is to critically examine the normative foundations of gatekeeper liability. In the course of this paper, I shall defend the claim that gatekeeper liability may be morally objectionable not only on grounds of fairness but also on consequentialist grounds. The expected contribution of this paper is threefold. First, it systematizes the framing and moral justification of gatekeeping duties. Second, it calls into question the normative underpinnings for targeting intermediaries instead of primary wrongdoers. Third, it anticipates some negative (and often overlooked) results of gatekeeping strategies in the accounting profession, specifically in the realm of clientele selection, the expectation gap, and auditor compensation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As of January 2013 in the United States, 28 states have enacted social hosting laws, which hold party hosts liable for the property damages and personal injuries that any of their intoxicated guests cause to an innocent third person and/or property. National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism (2013). http://alcoholpolicy.niaaa.nih.gov/Prohibitions_Against_Hosting_Underage_Drinking_Parties.html.

  2. Technically, gatekeeper liability is a genre of collateral liability but in what follows, I shall use “collateral liability”, “gatekeeper liability”, and “secondary liability” interchangeably.

  3. Another gatekeeper’s failure, by credit rating agencies, explains the most recent financial crisis given the role of CRAs in developing structured financial products and downgrading sovereign debt. Credit rating agencies also failed as gatekeepers in the Enron’s collapse. Until four days before Enron declared bankruptcy its debt was still rated as investment grade by the major credit rating agencies (Payne 2014).

  4. “Non-ideal theory” is defined negatively, as either a complement or a rejection of an ideal theory (Rawls 1971; Simmons 2010). Ideal theories typically make some idealizing assumptions intended to simplify a complex problem (for example, the theory may assume that every member of a society will fully comply with such society’s principles of justice). The assumption underlying gatekeeper liability is that direct deterrence—the ideal theory—does not work effectively.

  5. In the U.S.A., when providing professional services, accountants may incur common law liabilities for negligence and fraud, and liabilities for the violation of federal and state statutes. In addition to common law liability, accountants have statutory law liability to third parties under the Securities Exchange Act of 1934 and the Securities Act of 1933. I cannot do justice to the history of legal liability in the accounting profession in the U.S.A. here but see Fischel (1981), Goldberg (1988), and Coates (2007).

  6. Privity is a doctrine in contract law according to which an agreement between two parties A and B cannot confer rights on C or impose obligations arising under it on C or any other except A and B. Only the parties to the contract should be allowed to enforce their rights and claim for compensation. See Lilienthal (1887).

  7. For example, accountants have a legal duty to report any illegal act of their clients to the company’s board of directors and the SEC (Private Securities Litigation Reform Act). Whistleblowing is not just a purely preventive role because it entails some punishment as well, as it reveals damaging information about attempted misconduct.

  8. The Code of Professional Conduct (Article 203) establishes that auditors may depart from GAAP to prevent financial statements from being misleading. The leading case is a 1969 criminal court case, Continental Vending (United States v. Simon) in which three auditors were found guilty of fraud for certifying their client’s annual report, which disclosed just enough to arguably comply with GAAP but concealed critical information to understanding the firm’s financial standing (the firm soon went bankrupt). If literal compliance with GAAP creates a fraudulent or materially misleading impression in the minds of shareholders, according to the courts, the auditors should be held liable (Zeff 2007; Duska et al. 2011).

  9. Or, one may argue, it is not that the implication really goes the other way: while “ought implies can” may just mean that one has an obligation to do A only if one can do A; “can implies ought” may mean that one ought to do A if one can do A and A is in some way morally praiseworthy. In either case, the claim is that gatekeepers have an obligation to frustrate bad behavior if they can. I am grateful to Ed Hartman for pressing this point.

  10. Although even non-consequentialist scholars may endorse the claim that social welfare may sometimes ground moral obligations. See Gauthier (1982) and Heath (2007).

  11. Boatright explains why the design of a comprehensive system of deterrence should take into account not only the cost and effectiveness of each means of deterrence but also how the selected means interact with each other as part of a whole system. It is possible, he suggests, that some responsibilities are too costly: “For example, if banks avoid risk by requiring significant additional information about a client's operations, or if some companies decline to deal with banks because of the information they require, then an unnecessary cost may be imposed on the economy.” (2007, p. 626) I thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing this point.

  12. Elsewhere, I have discussed the related question of whether these professional roles are consistent with the traditional ideals and identity of the accounting profession (Warren and Alzola 2009).

  13. Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act, Pub. L. No. 111 - 203, 124 Stat. 1376 (2010) 929O.

  14. Gatekeeper obligations are dependent on primary obligations not to wrong others in the first place. Gatekeeper responsibilities arise out of failures to discharge such primary responsibilities. Such primary responsibilities offer reasons to honor remedial responsibilities and shape the extent and scope of remedial responsibilities. Repairing injuries wrongly done is a second best way to comply with one’s duties not to do harm wrongly in the first place.

  15. Moreover, there is no penalty imposed on the firm resulting from the individual partner’s or manager’s misconduct because the civil law principle of respondeat superior does not apply in the accounting profession (Goldberg 1988) and the SEC has been reluctant to proceed against firms (Franco 2011). That is, the individual partner and the audit manager do not face serious risk of individualized sanctions. In addition, according to Coffee, the AICPA “lacks any real enforcement staff.” (2001, p. 47).

  16. The Sarbanes–Oxley Act ended the accounting profession’s long tradition of self-regulation and peer review with the creation of the Public Company Accounting Oversight Board to oversee auditors of public companies—including periodic inspections—and to set auditing standards (Coates 2007).

  17. In response to these concerns, the European Commission has issued a “Recommendation Concerning the Limitation of the Civil Liability of Auditors” which holds a proportionality principle: a limitation of the liability to the contribution of the audit firm to the damage suffered by the plaintiff. See “Study on the Economic Impact of Auditors’ Liability Regimes.” Available at http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/auditing/docs/liability/auditors-final-report_en.pdf.

  18. Available at https://www.trustedchoice.com/content/2013/12/social-liability/.

  19. Available at http://northdallasgazette.com/2013/11/22/could-you-be-serving-up-a-lawsuit-with-that-turkey-dinner-on-thanksgiving/.

  20. Note. Negligence—Social Host Liability—Social Hosts Not Liable For Accidents Caused By Intoxicated Guests, Harvard Law Review, Dec. (1988), 102(2), 553.

  21. My argument is not inconsistent with the claim that the professional roles ought to shift. Part of the problem with the current arrangement may be precisely that client firms have too great a tendency to think of their auditors as cooperative colleagues rather than cops on the beat. A young student who decides to pursue a career as an accountant or as a professor is not thinking that his or her job will be the job of a police officer. Maybe he or she should. And maybe many of us who see ourselves as academicians rather than cops on the beat are simply wrong (For a story about university professors as gatekeepers, see Bhasin (2011).

  22. Daniel Goelzer, a Board Member at the PCAOB, says that the evidence collected at the PCAOB indicates that some small public firms “are finding it harder to engage or retain a Big 4 audit firm.” “Sarbanes–Oxley and the Post-Enron Environment: Auditor Oversight” Available at http://pcaobus.org/News/Speech/Pages/08022005_GoelzerSOXAuditorOversight.aspx.

  23. The expression “expectation gap” comes from the 1978 AICPA’s Cohen Commission report, which concluded “a gap exists between the performance of auditors and the expectations of users of financial statements.” (Evans 1978).

  24. At this juncture, it might be helpful to examine some differences between corporate attorneys and auditors. The competent accountant may act as a gatekeeper given his or her non-adversarial role. But the lawyer cannot. Previous to Sarbanes–Oxley, the counsel’s role was zealous advocacy for his or her client (Daley and Karmel 1975). The attorney’s loyalty was then to the client and not to investors. Lawyers had no independent certification role, unlike auditors. And they were subject to a duty of confidentiality that is quite different from the auditor’s. Yet, after Sarbanes–Oxley, lawyers have a duty to monitor the client, to report wrongdoing to senior management and corporate boards, and to withdraw if the client refuses to comply with the law. Even if a particular transaction is perfectly legitimate, it can be fraudulent if its primary purpose or effect is to mislead investors. Hence, as in the case of accountants and social hosts, gatekeeper regimes will necessarily change, for better or worse, the nature of the attorney-client relationship. See Coffee (2006).

  25. Kraakman (1986) disagrees. He believes that gatekeepers must be punished for failure rather than paid for success because their cooperation is non-verifiable, in the sense that we can only observe ex-post whether gatekeepers failed to prevent misconduct ex-ante. However, when private enforcers can make easily observable enforcement contributions, recruiting private enforcers can rely on rewards (e.g. legal immunity).

  26. An earlier version of this essay was presented at IESE Business School in Barcelona in June 28, 2014 and at colloquia at ESSEC Business School in Paris in May 27, 2015. I have benefited from the input of both audiences. Written comments of Ed Hartman, Domenec Mele, Silvia Romero, and two anonymous reviewers enabled me to make a number of improvements in preparing the final version. I am also grateful to Fordham University for fellowship support during the period I was working on this paper.

References

  • Akerlof, G. A. (1970). The market for” lemons”: Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84, 488–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alzola, M. (2017a). Even when no one is watching. The Moral Psychology of Corporate Reputation. Business & Society.

  • Alzola, M. (2017b). Corporate roles and virtues. In A. J. Sison (Ed.), Handbook of virtue ethics in business and management (pp. 47–56). New York: Springer Publishing.

  • American Institute of Certified Public Accountants (AICPA). Auditing Standards Section 230 (Available at http://pcaobus.org/Standards/Auditing/Pages/AU230.aspx#ftn.au_230_fn1)

  • Applbaum, A. I. (1999). Ethics for adversaries: The morality of roles in public and professional life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1974). The limits of organization. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aubin, D., & Longstreth, A. (2011). Auditor defense may have holes in Deloitte case, Reuters (September 27). Available at http://www.reuters.com/article/2011/09/27/us-deloitte–lawsuit-idUSTRE78Q6FU20110927

  • Bainbridge, S. M. (2011). Corporate governance after the financial crisis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bampton, R., & Cowton, C. J. (2013). Taking stock of accounting ethics scholarship: A review of the journal literature. Journal of Business Ethics, 114(3), 549–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M. H., Loewenstein, G., & Moore, D. A. (2002). Why good accountants do bad audits. Harvard Business Review, 80(11), 96–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M. H., Morgan, K. P., & Loewenstein, G. F. (1997). The impossibility of auditor independence. Sloan Management Review, 38, 89–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress, J. F. (2001). Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benson, P. (1995). The basis for excluding liability for economic loss in tort law. In D. G. Owen (Ed.), Philosophical foundations of tort law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhasin, K. (2011). NYU professor catches 20 % of his students cheating, and he’s the one who pays for it. business insider. Available at http://www.businessinsider.com/nyu-professor-class-cheating-2011-7

  • Bierstaker, J. L., Hunton, J. E., & Thibodeau, J. C. (2012). Does fraud training help auditors identify fraud risk factors? Advances in Accounting Behavioral Research, 15, 85–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (2007). Reluctant guardians: The moral responsibility of gatekeepers. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(4), 613–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calabresi, G. (2008). The cost of accidents: A legal and economic analysis. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S. (1998). Market lessons for gatekeepers. Northwestern University Law Review, 92(3), 916–966.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clikeman, P. M., & Lemon, W. M. (2010). Called to account: fourteen financial frauds that shaped the american accounting profession. The Accounting Review, 85(5), 1811–1814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, J. C. (2007). The goals and promise of the Sarbanes–Oxley Act. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21, 91–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coffee, J. C, Jr. (2001). The acquiescent gatekeeper: Reputational intermediaries, auditor independence, the governance of accounting. New York: Columbia Law School, The Center for Law and Economic Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffee, J. C, Jr. (2002). Understanding Enron: It’s about the Gatekeepers, Stupid. The Business Lawyer, 57(4), 1403–1420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffee, J. C, Jr. (2006). Gatekeepers: The professions and corporate governance. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J. (1992). Risks and wrongs. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, C., & Bryan Low, C. (2002). After scandals, audit fees rise, and investors may pay the price wall street journal (August 12). Available at: http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB1029097037499427475

  • Daley, J. C., & Karmel, R. S. (1975). Attorneys’ responsibilities: Adversaries at the bar of the SEC. Emory Law Journal, 24, 747.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duska, R. (2005). The good auditor–Skeptic or Wealth accumulator? Ethical lessons learned from the Arthur Andersen debacle. Journal of Business Ethics, 57(1), 17–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duska, R., Duska, B. S., & Ragatz, J. A. (2011). Accounting ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Easterbrook, F. H., & Fischel, D. R. (1984). Mandatory disclosure and the protection of investors. Virginia Law Review, 70, 669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichler, L. (2009). The book of etiquette (Vol. I). New York: Cosimo Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. A. (1985). Products liability as an insurance market. The Journal of Legal Studies, 14, 645–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. R. (1978). Improving the accounting profession: A Shared responsibility. Securities and Exchange Commission News. Available at http://www.sec.gov/news/speech/1978/120878evans.pdf

  • Fischel, D. R. (1981). Secondary Liability under Section 10(b) of the securities act of 1934. California Law Review, 69, 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franco, J. A. (2011). Of complicity and compliance: A rules-based anti-complicity strategy under federal securities law. University of Pennsylvania Journal of Business Law, 14, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fried, C. (1976). The lawyer as friend: The moral foundations of the lawyer-client relation. Yale Law Journal, 85, 1060–1089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J. (2007). Complicity and causality. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 1(2), 127–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1982). No need for morality: The case of the competitive market. Philosophic Exchange, 3, 41–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geistfeld, M. (2001). Economics, moral philosophy, and the positive analysis of tort law. In Gerald Postema (Ed.), Philosophy and the law of torts. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth, A. (1978). Reason and morality. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilson, R. (1984). Value creation by business lawyers: Legal skills and asset pricing. Yale Law Review, 94(2), 239–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilson, R. J., & Kraakman, R. H. (1984). The mechanisms of market efficiency. Virginia Law Review, 70, 549–644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, V. P. (1988). Accountable accountants: Is third-party liability necessary? The Journal of Legal Studies, 17, 295–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (1985). Protecting the vulnerable: A reanalysis of our social responsibilities. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordley, J. (1995). Tort law in the Aristotelian tradition. In D. G. Owen (Ed.), Philosophical foundations of tort law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gossman, T. L. (1988). The fallacy of expanding accountants’ liability. Columbia Business Law Review, (1), 213–241.

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1955). Are there any natural rights? Philosophical Review, 64, 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, T. (1985). Causation in the law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. (1996). Organizational ethics and the good life. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Heath, J. (2007). An adversarial ethic for business: Or when Sun-Tzu met the stakeholder. Journal of Business Ethics, 72(4), 359–374.

  • Holt, E. (2005). Encyclopedia of etiquette: A book of manners for everyday use. New York: Cosimo Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1740, 1978). A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press

  • Kraakman, R. H. (1986). Gatekeepers: The anatomy of a third-party enforcement strategy. Journal of Law, Economics & Organizations, 2, 53–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutz, C. (2000). Complicity: Law and ethics for a collective age. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, W. M., & Posner, R. A. (1975). The private enforcement of law. Journal of Legal Studies, 4(1), 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, W. M., & Posner, R. A. (1978). Salvors, finders, good samaritans, and other rescuers: An economic study of law and altruism. Journal of Legal Studies, 7, 83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lilienthal, J. W. (1887). Privity of contract. Harvard Law Review, 1, 226–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowenfels, L. D. (1974). Expanding public responsibilities of securities lawyers: An analysis of the new trend in standards of care and priorities of duties. Columbia Law Review, 74, 412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malm, H. M. (1995). Liberalism, bad Samaritan law, and legal paternalism. Ethics, 106(1), 4–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McEnroe, J. E., & Martens, S. C. (2001). Auditors’ and investors’ perceptions of the “Expectation Gap”. Accounting Horizons, 15(4), 345–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, A. (1994). Guilty bystanders? On the legitimacy of duty to rescue statutes. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 23(2), 157–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLean, B., & Elkind, P. (2004). The smartest guys in the room: The amazing rise and scandalous fall of Enron. New York: Penguin Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2005). Ethical education in accounting: Integrating rules, values and virtues. Journal of Business Ethics, 57(1), 97–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, L. (1967). The encyclopedia of etiquette: A guide to good manners in today’s world. New York: Crown Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism (2013). http://alcoholpolicy.niaaa.nih.gov/Prohibitions_Against_Hosting_Underage_Drinking_Parties.html. (Last visited 1 Nov 2016).

  • Nelson, K. K., Price, R. A., & Rountree, B. R. (2008). The market reaction to Arthur Andersen’s role in the Enron scandal: Loss of reputation or confounding effects? Journal of Accounting and Economics, 46(2), 279–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Payne, J. (2014). The role of gatekeepers. In N. Moloney, E. Ferran, & J. Payne (Eds.), Oxford handbook of financial regulation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polinsky, A. M., & Shavell, S. (1994). Should liability be based on the harm to the victim or the gain to the injurer? Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 10, 427–437.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. A. (1981). The concept of corrective justice in recent theories of tort law. The Journal of Legal Studies, 10, 187–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. L. (1985). The invention of enterprise liability: A critical history of the intellectual foundations of modern tort law. The Journal of Legal Studies, 14, 461–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radtke, R. R. (2008). Role morality in the accounting profession: How do we compare to physicians and attorneys? Journal of Business Ethics, 79(3), 279–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapoport, M. (2011). Deloitte settles suits over Taylor Bean audits. The Wall Street Journal (October 3). Available at http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052702304906704579113561152129866

  • Rawls, J. (1964). Legal obligation and the duty of fair play. In S. Hook (Ed.), Law and philosophy. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recent Cases. Negligence. Social Host Liability. Social Hosts Not Liable for Accidents Caused by Intoxicated Guests. Burkhart v. Harrod, 110 Wash. 2d 381, 755 P.2d 759 (1988) Harvard Law Review, 102(2), 549–555.

  • Reffett, A. B. (2010). Can identifying and investigating fraud risks increase auditors’ liability? The Accounting Review, 85(6), 2145–2167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiter, S. A., & Williams, P. F. (2004). The philosophy and rhetoric of auditor independence concepts. Business Ethics Quarterly, 14(3), 355–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romero, S. (2010). Auditor independence: Third party hiring and paying auditors. EuroMed Journal of Business, 5(3), 298–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, G. T. (1981). The vitality of negligence and the ethics of strict liability. Georgia Law Review, 15, 963–1004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, J., & Marshall, G. 2014. Oxford dictionary of sociology. Available at: http://www.oxfordreference.com/view/10.1093/acref/9780199533008.001.0001/acref-9780199533008-e-1843

  • Simmons, A. J. (1979). The principle of fair play. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 8(4), 307–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A. J. (2010). Ideal and nonideal theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(1), 5–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, R., & Rapoport, M. (2011). Deloitte and touche sued over Taylor Bean collapse. The Wall Street Journal (September 27). Available at http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052970204010604576595133072373372

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1(1), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, F. A., Stout, F., Whetten-Goldstein, K., & Liang, L. (Eds.). (2000). Drinkers, drivers, and bartenders: Balancing private choices and public accountability. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C., & Williams, B. (1973). Utilitarianism: For and against. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. (1992). Corporate roles, personal virtues: An Aristotelian Approach to Business Ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 2(3), 317–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Statement on Auditing Standards (SAS) 99, Consideration of Fraud in a Financial Statement Audit.

  • Vandekerckhove, W., & Tsahuridu, E. E. (2010). Risky rescues and the duty to blow the whistle. Journal of Business Ethics, 97(3), 365–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, D., & Alzola, M. (2009). Ensuring independent auditors: increasing the saliency of the professional identity. Group Decisions and Negotiation, 18(1), 41–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinert, H. R. (1985). Social hosts and drunken drivers: A duty to intervene? University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 133, 867–894.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib, E. J. (1980). The case for a duty to rescue. Yale Law Journal, 90(2), 247–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Persons, character and morality, in moral luck. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. E. (1983). Credible commitments: Using hostages to support exchange. The American Economic Review, 73(4), 519–540.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeff, S. A. (2007). The primacy of “Present Fairly” in the auditor’s report. Accounting Perspectives, 6(1), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miguel Alzola.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Alzola, M. Beware of the Watchdog: Rethinking the Normative Justification of Gatekeeper Liability. J Bus Ethics 140, 705–721 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-017-3460-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-017-3460-3

Keywords

Navigation