Skip to main content
Log in

Behavioral Ethics: A Critique and a Proposal

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In behavioral ethics today, there is debate as to which theory of moral development is the best for understanding ethical decision making, thereby facilitating ethical behavior. This debate between behavioral ethicists has been profoundly influenced by the field of moral psychology. Unfortunately, in the course of this marriage between moral psychology and business ethics and subsequent internal debate, a simple but critical understanding of human being in the field of management has been obscured; i.e., that morality is not a secondary phenomenon arising out of something else. Therefore, in this paper, we will argue that there is a need in behavioral ethics to shift our understanding away from the influence of contemporary moral psychology and back to management theorist Ghoshal’s (Acad Manag Learn Educ 4(1):75–91, 2005) view of what it means to be human in which the moral is fundamental. To assist in this labor, we will build on the philosophical work of Emmanuel Levinas who sees ethics, regardless of the setting, as a metaphysical concern. What this means is that Levinas sees the essential moral character of human life and the reality of human agency as ontologically fundamental, or constitutive of human nature itself. In other words, the ethical is the “first cause” in regard to understanding the nature and action of the individual, including within organizations. Thus, morality in any sphere of human endeavor, including in business, is not merely epiphenomenal to some more fundamental reality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The “is to ought” dilemma (known as Hume’s guillotine) has been articulated most notably by the Scottish philosopher Hume (1739/2001). He observed that many writers in his day made claims about what ought to be, on the basis of statements about what is. He asserts that there is a significant difference (or what we term in this paper as an ontological gap) between descriptive statements (about what is) and prescriptive statements (about what ought to be).

  2. In “From Is to Ought: How to Commit the Psychological Fallacy and Get Away with It in the Study of Moral Development,” Kohlberg sought to solve the “is to ought” dilemma by demonstrating a “parallelism” between psychological descriptions and philosophical-normative analyses of his stages. This parallelism, he contended, led to a kind of complementarity and even a convergence of the two analyses (see Power et al. 1989).

  3. It should be noted that "ethics," in Levinas's philosophical project does not mean what is typically referred to as ethics or even morality, that is—a code of conduct that cultivates virtues or employs rationalist self legislation about how one should act. Derrida (1976) notes that Levinas does not want to propose laws or moral rules but to propose an ethics of ethics. In other words, Levinas does not seek to determine a morality, but rather the essence of the ethical relation in general. Since “the moral” in this paper is also defined in a broader sense as beyond rationality and fundamental to humanity (see p. 9 herein), for the purposes of this paper, the terms “ethical” and “moral” will be used interchangeably.

  4. Agency defined as “having the world truthfully,” rather than merely making free choices from among alternatives is to say that “living truthfully” is the proper, effective, appropriate recognition of the differences inherent in an act or situation. Agents participate in the world in a way that truthfully articulates the differences something makes, or rather, the morality of the activity (Williams and Gantt 2002).

  5. In continental philosophy, the Constitutive Other often denotes persons identified as “different” and in Levinas’s case as “infinite.” It denotes “alterity” or “otherness” in general, not specifically. Thus, the term “other” often is capitalized to signify this representation of difference, of alterity, of infiniteness.

References

  • Aquino, K., & Reed, A, I. I. (2002). The self-importance of moral identity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83(6), 1423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A., Barbaranelli, C., Caprara, G. V., & Pastorelli, C. (1996). Mechanisms of moral disengagement in the exercise of moral agency. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71(2), 364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A. (1989). Conditional automaticity: Varieties of automatic influence in social perception and cognition. In J. S. Uleman & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), Unintended thought (pp. 3–51). NewYork: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A. (1990). Auto-motives: Preconscious determinants of thought and behavior. In E. T. Higgins & R. M. Sorrentino (Eds.), Handbook of motivation and cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 93–130). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A. (1996). Principles of automaticity. In E. T. Higgins & A. Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 169–183). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A. (1997). The automaticity of everyday life. In R. S. Wyer Jr (Ed.), The automaticity of everyday life, advances in social cognition (Vol. 10, pp. 1–61). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A. (2005). Bypassing the will: Toward demystifying the nonconscious control of social behavior. In R. R. Hassin, J. S. Uleman, & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), The new unconscious (pp. 37–60). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist, 54, 462–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., & Pratto, F. (1986). Individual construct accessibility and perceptual selection. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 22(4), 293–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M. H., & Gino, F. (2012). Behavioral ethics: Toward a deeper understanding of moral judgment and dishonesty. Annual Review of Law and Social Science, 8, 85–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergman, R. (2002). Why be moral? A conceptual model from developmental psychology. Human Development, 45, 104–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blasi, A. (1983). Moral cognition and moral action: A theoretical perspective. Developmental Review, 3(2), 178–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blasi, A. (1984). Moral identity: Its role in moral functioning. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and moral development (pp. 129–139). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blasi, A. (1995). Moral understanding and the moral personality: The process of moral integration. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Moral development: An introduction (pp. 229–253). Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blasi, A. (2009). The moral functioning of mature adults and the possibility of fair moral reasoning. In D. Narvaez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), Personality, identity, and character (pp. 396–440). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brief, A. P. (2012). The good, the bad, and the ugly: What behavioral business ethics researchers ought to be studying. In Behavioral business ethics: Shaping an emerging field (pp. 17–46). New York: Routledge.

  • Cervone, D., & Tripathi, R. (2009). The moral functioning of the person as a whole: On moral psychology and personality science. In D. Narvaez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), Personality, identity and character, explorations in moral psychology (pp. 30–51). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Colby, A., & Damon, W. (1993). The uniting of self and morality in the development of extraordinary moral commitment. In G. G. Noam & T. E. Wren (Eds.), The moral self (pp. 149–174). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1976). Of Grammatology. (G. C. Spivak, Trans., pp. 242–272). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP.

  • Eisenberg, N. (1986). Altruistic emotion, cognition, and behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

  • Flanagan, O. J. (2007). The really hard problem: Meaning in a material world. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. (1988). Passions within reason: The strategic role of the emotions. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frimer, J. A., & Walker, L. J. (2008). Towards a new paradigm of moral personhood. Journal of Moral Education, 37(3), 333–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S. (2005). Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 4(1), 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2008). Moral intuitions = fast and frugal heuristics? In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. Moral Psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 1–26). Cambridge: MA, MIT Press.

  • Gino, F., Schweitzer, M. E., Mead, N. L., & Ariely, D. (2011). Unable to resist temptation: How self-control depletion promotes unethical behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 115(2), 191–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glannon, W. (2007). Defining right and wrong in brain science: Essential readings in neuroethics. New York: Dana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Bjorklund, F. (2007). Social intuitionists answer six questions about morality. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. Moral Psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 181–217). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: How innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133(44), 55–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hershfield, H. E., Cohen, T. R., & Thompson, L. (2012). Short horizons and tempting situations: Lack of continuity to our future selves leads to unethical decision making and behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 117(2), 298–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, M. L. (1970). Moral development. In P. Mussen (Ed.), Handbook of child psychology (pp. 261–361). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739/2001). In D. F. Norton & M. J. Norton (Eds.), A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kagan, J. (1984). The nature of the child. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1785/1993). Grounding for the metaphysics of morals (3rd ed.) (J. W. Ellington, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.

  • Kern, M. C., & Chugh, D. (2009). Bounded ethicality: The perils of loss framing. Psychological Science, 20(3), 378–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The cognitive-developmental approach to socialization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of socialization theory and research (pp. 347–480). Chicago: Rand McNally.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1971a). Stages of moral development as a basis for moral education. In C. M. Beck, B. S. Crittenden, & E. V. Sullivan (Eds.), Moral education: Interdisciplinary approaches (pp. 23–92). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1971b). From is to ought: How to commit the naturalistic fallacy and get away with it in the study of moral development. In T. Mischel (Ed.), Psychology and genetic epistemology (pp. 151–235). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1981). The philosophy of moral development. Essays on Moral Development (Vol. 1). San Francisco: Harper & Row.

  • Kohlberg, L., Levine, C., & Hewer, A. (1983). Moral stages: A current formulation and a response to critics. Basel, NY: Karger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lapsley, D. K., & Hill, P. L. (2008). On dual processing and heuristic approaches to moral cognition. Journal of Moral Education, 37(3), 313–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lapsley, D. K., & Hill, P. L. (2009). The development of the moral personality. In D. Narvaez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), Moral personality, identity and character: An integrative future (pp. 185–213). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1969). Totality and infinity: An essay on exteriority (A. Lingis, Trans.). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press. (Original work published 1961).

  • Levinas, E. (1987). Time and the other (R. A. Cohen, Trans.). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press. (Original work published 1947).

  • MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue: A study in moral theory (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAdams, D. P. (2009). The moral personality. In D. Narváez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), Moral self, identity and character (pp. 11–29). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monin, B., Pizarro, D., & Beer, J. (2007). Deciding vs. reacting: Conceptions of moral judgment and the reason-affect debate. Review of General Psychology, 11, 99–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez, D. (2008a). The social-intuitionist model: Some counter-intuitions. In W. A. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. Moral Psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 233–240). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Narvaez, D. (2008b). Triune ethics: The neurobiological roots of our multiple moralities. New Ideas in Psychology, 26, 95–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez, D., & Lapsley, D. K. (2005). The psychological foundations of everyday morality and moral expertise. In D. Lapsley & C. Power (Eds.), Character psychology and character education (pp. 140–165). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez, D., & Lapsley, D. K. (2009). Personality, identity, and character explorations in moral psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez, D., Lapsley, D. K., Hagele, S., & Lasky, B. (2006). Moral chronicity and social information processing: Tests of a social cognitive approach to the moral personality. Journal of Research in Personality, 40, 966–985.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2000). Moral theory: A non-consequentialist approach. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Power, F. C., Higgins, A., & Kohlberg, L. (1989). Lawrence Kohlberg’s approach to moral education. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rest, J. R. (1984). The major components of morality. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and moral development (pp. 24–38). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rest, J. R. (1999). Postconventional moral thinking: A Neo-Kohlbergian approach. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. N. (2008). Consciousness and mental life. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2001). The nature of consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, B. R., Miller, M. L., & Johnson, R. M. (2009). Moral identity, integrity, and personal responsibility. In D. Narváez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), Moral self, identity and character (pp. 316–340). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shweder, R. A., & Haidt, J. (1993). The future of moral psychology: Truth, intuition, and the pluralist way. Psychological Science, 4, 360–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slife, B. D., & Hopkins, R. H. (2004). Alternative assumptions for neuroscience: Formulating a true monism. In B. D. Slife, J. S. Reber, & F. C. Richardson (Eds.), Critical thinking about psychology: Hidden assumptions and plausible alternatives (pp. 35–54). Washington, DC: APA Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slife, B. D., Reber, J. S., & Richardson, F. C. (2005). Critical thinking about psychology: Hidden assumptions and plausible alternatives. Washington, DC: APA Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slife, B. D., & Williams, R. N. (1995). What’s behind the research? Discovering hidden assumptions in the behavioral sciences. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Moral heuristics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 531–573.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenbrunsel, A. E., & Smith-Crowe, K. (2008). Ethical decision making: Where we’ve been and where we’re going. The Academy of Management Annals, 2(1), 545–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treviño, L. K., Weaver, G. R., & Reynolds, S. J. (2006). Behavioral ethics in organizations: A review. Journal of Management, 32(6), 951–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevino, L. K., & Youngblood, S. A. (1990). Bad apples in bad barrels: A causal analysis of ethical decision-making behavior. Journal of Applied Psychology, 75(4), 378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uleman, J. S., & Bargh, J. A. (Eds.). (1989). Unintended thought. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, L. J., & Frimer, J. A. (2009). Moral personality exemplified. In D. Narváez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), Moral self, identity and character (pp. 316–340). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, R. N. (2005a). Self-betraying emotions and the psychology of heteronomy. European Journal of Psychotherapy, Counseling and Health, 7(1–2), 7–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, R. N. (2005b). Agency: Philosophical and spiritual foundations for applied psychology. In A. P. Jackson & L. Fischer (Eds.), Turning Freud upside down: Gospel perspectives on psychotherapy’s fundamental problems (pp. 116–142). Provo, UT: BYU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, R. N., & Gantt, E. E. (2002). Pursuing psychology as science of the ethical: Contributions of the work of Emmanual Levinas. In R. N. Williams & E. E. Gantt (Eds.), Psychology for the other, Levinas, ethics and the practice of psychology (pp. 1–31). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, R. N., & Gantt, E. E. (2009, July). Felt moral obligation and the moral judgment-moral action gap: An alternative ontological starting point. Paper presented at the The Association for Moral Education Conference, Utrecht.

  • Wilson, J. Q. (1993). The moral sense. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to gratefully acknowledge Terrance D. Olson, Edwin E. Gantt, Sam A. Hardy, Daniel K. Judd, Daniel N. Ellertson, Edmund Byrne, two anonymous reviewers, and Sivakani Jayaprakash for their patience, kindness, and meaningful intellectual and logistical guidance throughout the process of bringing this paper to publication.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc-Charles Ingerson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ellertson, C.F., Ingerson, MC. & Williams, R.N. Behavioral Ethics: A Critique and a Proposal. J Bus Ethics 138, 145–159 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-015-2628-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-015-2628-y

Keywords

Navigation