Skip to main content
Log in

Are homologies really natural kinds?

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The metaphysical nature of homologies has been variously characterized as natural kind, individualist, and pluralist-pragmatic. In this essay, I aim to build on the work of proponents of a natural kinds ontology for homologies using Richard Boyd’s influential HPC account of natural kinds. I aim to advance this position by showing the unique fit of extending the HPC account to homologies, deflecting individualist critiques, as well as the pluralist-pragmatic alternative, showing that homologies have a determinate metaphysical character as kinds. As an important extension of this position, I attempt to explain away how the mistaken metaphysics of the individualist, and derivatively the pluralist-pragmatic approach that contextually embraces it, can facilitate certain elements of biological practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I do not want to diminish the importance or difficulty of a fully satisfactory definition of homology. The historical characterization of homology is itself contentious (Nelson and Platnick 1981). One could also envision issues of the proximity of the historical relation and serial homology raising questions. As will become apparent, I maintain that the HANK thesis is most fitting with a “developmental” definition and I will ultimately align my HPC view with Wagner’s (2007, 2014) analysis of the homology concept. Again though, my hope is that the discussion of homology’s metaphysics requires little beyond accepting the minimal historical definition adopted here.

  2. Later, as I discuss in relation to the pluralist-pragmatic approach to homology, Boyd comes to blur the strict distinction between kinds and individualist views of species. But as I aim to show, species and homology are importantly differently in their metaphysical character, such that only an HPC kinds approach will fit for homology.

  3. In introducing this contrast between “Aristotelian” and “Millian” frameworks I want to emphasize that I am not making any substantive commitments to Aristotle’s and Mill’s actual views on kinds. The labels are historically inspired, of course, but the rationale is largely just a matter of convenient labeling for alternative views on kinds and the associated ideas of essentialism and laws of nature.

  4. Thanks to Jay Odenbaugh for noting this point.

  5. The idea here draws from efforts such as Lange (1995, 2000), Sober (1997), Mitchell (2000), and Woodward (2001) to make sensible the idea of laws in biology.

  6. This, of course, is a weighty metaphysical presupposition that appropriately might be flagged as a problem for the individualist. For the sake of argument, however, I’ll grant the presumption and attempt to show that kinds proponents can accommodate radical evolutionary transformation.

  7. I’m indebted to an anonymous reviewer for urging me to deal with this possibility. Notably, the point bears a resemblance to the earlier mentioned competitor critique from Ereshefsky and Reydon.

  8. As an aside, I’ve focused here on Wagner’s ChIN framework, since I think it is the best developed, but one might consider alternative developmental approaches to homology (e.g. Van Valen 1982), which would also fulfill the fundamental demand on a persistent mechanism.

  9. An alternative conceptual anchor for this point is that of integration, particularly as it’s applied to understanding the individuality of distinct organisms (see for example Clark’s 2016 idea of “individuating mechanisms”). There is good reason to think that integration and cohesion pick out distinct means of establishing individuality (see Mishler and Brandon 1987), but since cohesion represents what I think is the relevant dimension of SAI as it concerns HAI, I’ll focus my attention on cohesion.

  10. Though the point should be apparent from the discussion and illustration, it may be worth making explicit that I do not take mere historical relatedness to be a CGR. The languages illustration presents a pretty clear counter, but there is an abundance of possibilities that do the same. For example, various chemical elements—the paradigmatic case of natural kinds—stand in historical relationships to one another.

  11. Note here that the analogy should not be extended too far. I am not claiming that languages have metaphysical individuality. The point is merely to show the effects of branching within a lineage on individuality. This requires only the minimal, and I take it uncontroversial, notion of there being individual languages. ‘German’ designates an individual linguistic unit in a way that ‘German + English’ does not.

References

  • Anttila R (1989) Historical and comparative linguistics. John Benjamins Publishing Company, Amsterdam

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Assis L, Brigandt I (2009) Homology: homeostatic property cluster kinds in systematics and evolution. Evol Biol 36:248–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1991) Realism, anti-foundationalism, and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philos Stud 61:127–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigand I (2009) Natural kinds in evolution and systematics: metaphysical and epistemological considerations. Acta Biotheor 57:77–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark E (2016) A levels-of-selection approach to evolutionary individuality. Biol Philos 31:893–911

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane J (2004) On the metaphysics of species. Philos Sci 71:56–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (2008) Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philos Sci 75(3):344–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2010) What’s wrong with the new biological essentialism. Proc 2008 Bienn Meet Philos Sci Assoc 77:674–685

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M, Reydon T (2015) Scientific kinds. Philos Stud 172:969–986

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fautin DG (2009) Structural diversity, systematics, and evolution of cnidae. Toxicon 54:1054–1064

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin M (1974) A radical solution to the species problem. Syst Zool 23:536–544

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin M (2005) Homology as a relation of correspondence between parts of individuals. Theory Biosci 124:91–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant T, Kluge A (2004) Transformation series as an ideographic character concept. Cladistics 20:23–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1999) Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species, new interdisciplinary essays. Bradford/MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 209–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2015) Sameness, novelty, and nominal kinds. Biol Philos 30:857–872

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton A, Smith NR, Haber MH (2009) Social insects and the individuality thesis: cohesion and the colony as a selectable individual. In: Gadau J, Fewell J (eds) Organization of insect societies: from genome to sociocomplexities. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 570–587

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoenigswald HM (1960) Language change and linguistic reconstrucction. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull D (1976) Are species really individuals? Syst Zool 25:174–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull D (1980) Individuality and Selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 11:311–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffers RJ, Lehiste I (1979) Principles and methods for historical linguistics. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (1995) Are there natural laws concerning particular biological species? J Philos 92:430–451

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (2000) Natural laws in scientific practice. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (2002) An introduction to the philosophy of physics: locality, fields, energy, and mass. Blackwell Publishing, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Lankester ER (1870) On the use of the term homology in modern zoology, and the distinction between homogenetic and homoplastic agreements. J Nat Hist 6(31):34–43

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte J (2003) Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mishler B, Brandon R (1987) Individuality, plurality, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biol Philos 2:397–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell S (2000) Dimensions of scientific law. Philos Sci 67:242–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson G, Platnick N (1981) Systematics and biogeography. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen R (1848) The archetype and homologies of the vertebrate skeleton. John Von Voorst, Paternoster Row, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2004) Modules, kinds and homology. J Exp Zool B 304:18–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2007) The poverty of taxonomic characters. Biol Philos 22:95–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater M (2015) Natural kindness. Br J Philos Sci 66(2):375–411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1993) The philosophy of biology. Westview Press, Bolder

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1997) Two outbreaks of lawlessness in recent philosophy of biology. Philos Sci 64:458–467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suzuki DG, Tanaka S (2017) The phenomological and dynamic view of homology: homologs as persistently reproducible modules. Biol Theory 12:169–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Valen LM (1982) Homology and causes. J Morphol 173:305–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner G (1996) Homologues, natural kinds and the evolution of modularity. Am Zool 36:36–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner G (2001) Characters, units, and natural kinds. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner G (2007) The developmental genetics of homology. Nat Rev Genet 8:473–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner G (2014) Homology, genes, and evolutionary innovation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2006) Evolutionary essentialism. Br J Philos Sci 57(2):425–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2001) Law and explanation in biology: invariance is the kind of stability that matters. Philos Sci 68:1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher H. Pearson.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pearson, C.H. Are homologies really natural kinds?. Biol Philos 34, 42 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9696-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9696-9

Keywords

Navigation