Advertisement

Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 29, Issue 5, pp 747–759 | Cite as

Revisiting recent etiological theories of functions

  • Daniel M. KraemerEmail author
Article

Abstract

Arguably, the most widely endorsed account of normative functions in philosophy of biology is an etiological theory that holds that the function of current traits is fixed by the past selection history of other traits of that type. The earlier formulations of this “selected-effects” theory had trouble accommodating vestigial traits. In order to remedy these difficulties, the influential recent selection or modern history selected-effects theory was introduced. This paper expands upon and strengthens the argument that this theory has trouble stemming from recent “no variation” cases. In addition, several influential arguments for the necessity of including a selection requirement in a theory of normative biological functions are contested. It is suggested that accounting for biological functions in certain areas of biology (such as physiology and the neurosciences) does not require adverting to selection.

Keywords

Functions Malfunctions Normative functions Selected-effects theory of functions 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Robert Brandon, the late Fred Dretske, and especially Karen Neander for helpful comments on previous versions of this paper. I also benefitted from suggestions made by an anonymous reviewer and by the editor of this journal, Kim Sterelny.

References

  1. Boorse C (1977) Health as a theoretical concept. Philos Sci 44(4):542–573CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Boyko A, Williamson S, Indap A, Degenhardt J, Hernandez R, Lohmueller K, Adams M, Schmidt S, Sninsky J, Sunyaev S, White T, Nielsen R, Clark A, Bustamante C (2008) Assessing the evolutionary impact of amino acid mutations in the human genome. PLoS Genet 4(5):1–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bufe B, Breslin P, Kuhn C, Reed D, Tharp C, Slack J, Kim U-K, Drayna D, Meyerhof W (2005) The molecular basis of individual differences in phenylthiocarbamide and propylthiouracil bitterness perception. Curr Biol 15(4):322–327CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Campbell M, Ranciaro A, Froment A, Hirbo J, Omar S, Bodo J-M, Nyambo T, Lema G, Zinshteyn D, Drayna D, Breslin P, Tishkoff S (2011) Evolution of functionally diverse alleles associated with PTC bitter taste sensitivity in Africa. Molecular Biology and Evolution, Advance Access, pp. 1–37Google Scholar
  5. Cummins R (1975) Functional analysis. J Philos 72(20):741–765CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Drayna D (2005) Human taste genetics. Annu Rev Genom Human Genet 6:217–235CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Godfrey-Smith P (1994) A modern history theory of functions. Nous 28(3):344–362CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Greene L (1974) Physical growth and development, neurological maturation, and behavioral functioning in two ecuadorian andean communities in which goiter is endemic II. PTC taste sensitivity and neurological maturation. Am J Phys Anthropol 41:139–152CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Griffiths P (1993) Functional analysis and proper functions. Br J Philos Sci 44:409–422CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Jobling M (2012) Significant others. Investig Genet 3:21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Kim U-K, Drayna D (2004) Genetics of individual differences in bitter taste perception: lessons from the PTC gene. Clin Genet 67:275–280CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Kim U-K, Jorgenson E, Coon H, Leppert M, Risch N, Drayna D (2003) Positional cloning of the human quantitative trait locus underlying taste sensitivity to phenylthiocarbamide. Science 299:1221–1225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Kraemer D (2012) Making sense of normative functions and information in neurobiological systems. PhD Dissertation, Duke University, Durham, USAGoogle Scholar
  14. Kraemer D (2013) Statistical theories of functions and the problem of epidemic disease. Biol Philos 28:423–438Google Scholar
  15. Lynch M (2010) Rate, molecular spectrum, and consequences of human mutation. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107(3):961–968CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Mennella J, Pepino YM, Duke F, Reed D (2010) Age modifies the genotype-phenotype relationship for the bitter receptor TAS2R38. BMC Genet 11(60):1–9Google Scholar
  17. Millikan R (1989a) In defense of proper functions. Philos Sci 56(2):288–302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Millikan R (1989b) An ambiguity in the notion “function”. Biol Philos 4:172–176CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual analyst’s defense. Philos Sci 58(2):168–184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Neander K (2002) Why history matters: four theories of functions, published as “Warum Geschichte Zahlt: Vier Theorien von Funktionen” in M Weingarten, G Schlosser (eds) Formen der Erklaerung in der Biologie (Verlag fuer Wissenchaft und Bildung)Google Scholar
  21. Neander K (2006) Moths and metaphors. Review essay on organisms and artifacts: design in nature and elsewhere by Tim Lewens. Biol Philos 21:591–602CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Prodi DA, Drayna D, Forabosco P, Palmas MA, Maestrale GB, Piras D, Pirastu M, Angius A (2004) Bitter taste study in a sardinian genetic isolate supports the association of phenylthiocarbamide sensitivity to the TAS2R38 bitter receptor gene. Chem Senses 29:697–702CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Roach J, Glusman G, Smit A, Huff C, Hubley R, Shannon P, Rowen L, Pant K, Goodman N, Bamshad M, Shendure J, Drmanac R, Jorde L, Hood L, Galas D (2010) Analysis of genetic inheritance in a family quartet by whole-genome sequencing. Science 328:636–639CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Roe K, Murphy D (2011) Function, dysfunction and adaptation? In: Adriaens P, De Block A (eds) Maladapting minds: philosophy, psychiatry, and evolutionary theory. Oxford University Press, USA, pp 216–237CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Schwartz P (1999) Proper function and recent selection. Philosophy of Science (66) Supplement, p. s210–s222Google Scholar
  26. Schwartz P (2002) The continuing usefulness account of proper function. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) Functions: new essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  27. Sharma K, Sharma P, Sharma A, Singh G (2008) Phenylthiocarbamide taste perception and susceptibility to motion sickness: linking higher susceptibility with higher phenylthiocarbamide taste acuity. J Laryngol Otol 122:1064–1073Google Scholar
  28. Tepper B (2008) Nutritional implications of genetic taste variation: the role of PROP sensitivity and other taste phenotypes. Annu Rev Nutr 28:367–388CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Walsh D, Ariew A (1996) A taxonomy of functions. Can J Philos 26(4):493–514Google Scholar
  30. Wright L (1973) Functions. Philos Rev 82(2):139–168CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Florida Atlantic UniversityBoca RatonUSA

Personalised recommendations