Skip to main content
Log in

A commentary on “The Formal Darwinism Project”: there is no grandeur in this view of life

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Formal Darwinism Project is an attempt to use mathematical theory to prove the claim that fitness maximization is the outcome of evolution in nature. Grafen’s (2014, p. 12) conclusion from this project is that “….there is a very general expectation of something close to fitness maximisation, which will convert into fitness-maximisation unless there are particular kinds of circumstances—and further, that fitness is the same quantity for all genetic architectures.” Grafen’s claim appears to mean to him that natural populations are expected to contain individuals whose traits are optimal, i.e., any given trait outperforms all reasonable alternatives. I describe why Grafen’s attempt can never provide a meaningful expectation as to the ubiquity of optimal traits in nature. This is so because it is based upon a misconception of the relationship between theory and empirical analysis. Even if one could use theory in the way Grafen proposes, I describe how his theory is causally incomplete. Finally, I describe how Grafen’s conceptual framework is ambiguous. The Formal Darwinism Project has been inspired by “On The Origin of Species” by Darwin. The great lesson of this book was Darwin’s demonstration of the necessary dialog between theory and data, with each influencing and being influenced by the other. Grafen’s Formal Darwinism Project, an attempt to create understanding of nature by removing data from this dialog, reflects a failure to understand Darwin’s great lesson.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Brandon R, Rausher MD (1996) Testing adaptationism: a comment on Orzack and Sober. Am Nat 148:189–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brockmann HJ, Dawkins R (1979) Joint nesting in a digger wasp as an evolutionarily stable preadaptation to social life. Behaviour 71:203–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brockmann HJ, Grafen A, Dawkins R (1979) Evolutionarily stable nesting strategy in a digger wasp. J Theor Biol 77:473–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cain AJ (1989) The perfection of animals. Biol J Linn Soc Lond 36:3–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chamary JV, Parmley JL, Hurst LD (2006) Hearing silence: non-neutral evolution at synonymous sites in mammals. Nat Rev Genet 7:98–108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charnov E (1982) The theory of sex allocation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein J (1985) Phylogenies and the comparative method. Am Nat 125:1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginzburg LR (1979) Why are heterozygotes often superior in fitness? Theor Popul Biol 15:264–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2001) Three kinds of adaptationism. In: Orzack SH, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 335–357

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1999) Formal Darwinism, the individual-as-maximising-agent analogy, and bet-hedging. Proceedings of the Royal Society, Series B 266:799–803

  • Grafen A (2000) Developments of Price’s Equation and natural selection under uncertainty. Proceedings of the Royal Society, Series B 267:1223–1227

  • Grafen A (2002) A first formal link between the Price equation and an optimisation program. J Theor Biol 217:75–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2006a) Optimisation of inclusive fitness. J Theor Biol 238:541–563

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2006b) A theory of Fisher’s reproductive value. J Math Biol 53:15–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2014) The formal darwinism project in outline. Biol Philos 29(2). doi:10.1007/s10539-013-9414-y

  • Hansen TF, Orzack SH (2005) Assessing current adaptation and phylogenetic inertia as explanations of trait evolution: the need for controlled comparisons. Evolution 59:2063–2072

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen TF, Pienaar J, Orzack SH (2008) A comparative method for studying adaptation to a randomly evolving environment. Evolution 62:1965–1977

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey PH, Pagel MD (1991) The comparative method in evolutionary biology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Herre EA (1987) Optimality, plasticity and selective regime in fig wasp sex ratios. Nature 329:627–629

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karlin S, Lieberman U (1975) Random temporal variation in selection intensities: case of large population size. Theor Popul Biol 6:355–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimura M (1983) The neutral theory of molecular evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kolman W (1960) The mechanism of natural selection for the sex ratio. Am Nat 94:373–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leigh EG Jr (1986) Ronald Fisher and the development of evolutionary theory. I. The role of selection. Oxf Surv Evolut Biol 3:187–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC, Ginzburg L, Tuljapurkar S (1978) Heterosis as an explanation for large amounts of genic polymorphism. Genetics 88:149–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (1989) Phylogenetic hypotheses under the assumption of neutral quantitative-genetic variation. Evolution 43:1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May RM (1973) Stability and complexity in model ecosystems. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH (1990) The comparative biology of second sex ratio evolution within a natural population of a parasitic wasp, Nasonia vitripennis. Genetics 124:385–396

    Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Hines WGS (2005) The evolution of strategy variation: will an ESS evolve? Evolution 59:1183–1193

    Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1993) A critical look at Richard Levins’ ‘‘The strategy of model building in population biology.” Q Rev Biol 68:533–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1994a) Optimality models and the test of adaptationism. Am Nat 143:361–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1994b) How (not) to test an optimality model. Trends Ecol Evol 9:265–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1996) How to formulate and test adaptationism. Am Nat 148:202–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (2001) Adaptation, phylogenetic inertia, and the method of controlled comparisons. In: Orzack SH, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 45–63

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Parker ED Jr, Gladstone J (1991) The comparative biology of genetic variation for conditional sex ratio adjustment in a parasitic wasp, Nasonia vitripennis. Genetics 127:583–599

    Google Scholar 

  • Poethke HJ (1988) Sex ratio polymorphism: the impact of mutation and drift on evolution. Acta Biotheor 37:121–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227:520–521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rice SH (2008) A stochastic version of the price equation reveals the interplay of deterministic and stochastic processes in evolution. BMC Evol Biol 8:262–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rice SH, Papadopoulos A (2009) Evolution with stochastic fitness and stochastic migration. PLoS ONE 4(10):e7130. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0007130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shpak M, Orzack SH, Barany E (2013) The influence of demographic stochasticity on evolutionary dynamics and stability. Theor Popul Biol 88:47–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suzuki Y, Iwasa Y (1980) A sex ratio theory of gregarious parasitoids. Res Popul Ecol 22:366–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thornhill R, Alcock J (1983) The evolution of insect mating behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers R (1985) Social evolution. Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Co., Menlo Park

    Google Scholar 

  • Waage JK, Lane JA (1984) The reproductive strategy of a parasitic wasp II. Sex allocation and local mate competition in Trichogramma evanescens. J Anim Ecol 53:417–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werren JH (1980) Sex ratio adaptations to local mate competition in a parasitic wasp. Science 208:1157–1159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werren JH (1983) Sex ratio evolution under local mate competition in a parasitic wasp. Evolution 37:116–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werren JH (1987) Labile sex ratios in wasps and bees. Bioscience 37:498–506

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA (2009) Sex allocation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1932) The roles of mutation, inbreeding, cross-breeding and selection in evolution. Proc VI Int Congr Genet 1:356–366

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Brian McLoone, Samir Okasha, Sean Rice, Elliott Sober, and Bill Stubblefield for advice and comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Hecht Orzack.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Orzack, S.H. A commentary on “The Formal Darwinism Project”: there is no grandeur in this view of life. Biol Philos 29, 259–270 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9423-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9423-x

Keywords

Navigation