Skip to main content
Log in

Philosophical problems, cluster concepts, and the many lives of Molyneux’s question

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Molyneux’s question, whether the newly sighted might immediately recognize tactilely familiar shapes by sight alone, has produced an array of answers over three centuries of debate and discussion. I propose the first pluralist response: many different answers, both yes and no, are individually sufficient as an answer to the question as a whole. I argue that this is possible if we take the question to be cluster concept of sub-problems. This response opposes traditional answers that isolate specific perceptual features as uniquely applicable to Molyneux’s question and grant viability to only one reply. Answering Molyneux’s question as a cluster concept may also serve as a methodology for resolving other philosophical problems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Frank Jackson,“Mind and Illusion,” in Nagasaw et al. (2004).

  2. See Byrne (2002).

  3. See Michael Tye, “Knowing What It Is Like: The Ability Hypothesis and the Knowledge Argument” in Ludlow et al. (2004).

  4. See David Chalmers, “Phenomenal Concepts and the Knowledge Argument” in Ludlow et al. (2004).

  5. Stalker (1994).

  6. Preston and Bishop (2002).

  7. Kirk (2006).

  8. Byrne (2006).

  9. Historically, the failure of the newly sighted to identify shapes was status quo, but even this admitted of multiple explanations For instance, though both Locke and the question’s author, William Molyneux, took the question as of support Empiricism, Molyneux argued that the question suggested the heterogeneity of the senses of sight and touch while Locke argued that the question showed how our visual perception requires perceptual learning or “improvement.” As Locke wrote: “This I have set down, and leave with my reader, as an occasion for him to consider how much he may be beholden to experience, improvement, and acquired notions, where he thinks he had not the least use of, or help from them”. (Essay II.ix.8) What Locke’s own specific explanation amounts to is one of the more intriguing debates in Lockean scholarship. See Bruno (2010).

  10. Leibniz likely answered the question by utilizing geometrical images of touch and sight for shape recognition. Whether he thought that the imagination was employed unconsonsciously or consciously is discussed by Glenney (2012a).

  11. Campbell (1996) suggests that only small differences exist between tactile and visual experiences of shape, akin to differences in accent rather than language.

  12. This distinction between optical and cognitive blindness indicates that most blind subjects are in fact “double blind.” See Noë (2004: 12).

  13. For a recent review of these studies, see Cattaneo and Vecchi (2011: 98–102).

  14. It should be noted that many different experimental paradigms have been utilized in answer to Molyneux’s question, from testing eye movements of newborn infants (Streri and Gentaz 2003), to phosphene pattern recognition in blind subjects (Delbeke and Veraart 2006), to sensory substitution devices on sighted subjects (Pacherie 1997).

  15. For a review of empirical work on Molyneux’s question see, Molyneux’s Question: Section 5 Development as an Empirical Problem.” See Glenney (2012b).

  16. Regarding the quickness of recovery of Cheselden’s subject, Adam Smith writes, “In him this instinctive power, not having been exerted at the proper season, may, from disuse, have gone gradually to decay, and at last have been completely obliterated. Or, perhaps, (what seems likewise very possible,) some feeble and unobserved remains of it may have somewhat facilitated his acquisition of what he might otherwise have found it much more difficult to acquire.” (Smith 1795, Section 69).

  17. Degenaar claims that the cataract paradigm is the only method for testing Molyneux’s question, but cannot do so. Thus, there is no answer to the question. This seemingly “literalist” reading of Molyneux’s question poses a unique challenge to the plurality reply that is distinct from the sectarian views of Hopkins and others. For instance, on the literalist reading, the cataract paradigm is the only way to empirically study the question. But this is precisely the problem with the literalist reading. Taken literally, the question does not prescribe the specific testing paradigm of cataract removal. In addition, most cataract patients have limited luminance detection and some can even detect differences in color. Though lacking in perception of form, are these good test subjects, given the fact that they are not completely blind? A literalist reading fails to provide a non-arbitrary answer to this important question. Molyneux’s question lacks the kind of specificity that the literalist reading requires, offering neither a specific testing paradigm nor a distinctive subject pool. Thus, the literalist reading preferred by Degenaar is a non-starter. In addition, as I will argue, Held et al. (2011) outright undercuts Degenaar’s proposal.

  18. For a recent appraisal, see Devitt and Sterelny (1999).

  19. Gaut (2000: 26–27).

  20. Premises 1–3 are developed from Longworth and Scarantino (2010).

  21. Cheselden’s subject had previously experienced colors as an infant—his cataracts were not congenital—and with cataracts he could even discern some colors in good lighting conditions.

  22. George Berkeley (1933/1975) considered Cheselden’s report confirmation of his negative reply, as did many French Philosophers such as Voltaire (1738/1967). The more recent reports confirmed Cheselden’s findings for many scientists, including the influential psychologist (Hebb 1949).

  23. “Or whether he could know by his sight, before he stretched out his hand, whether he could not reach them, tho they were removed 20 or 1,000 feet from him?” Locke (1978), Vol. III, July 7, 1688, letter 1064, pp. 482–483.

  24. Molyneux was an advocate for the “new learning”—the experimental philosophy of the Royal Society that advocated Locke’s empiricism. He founded The Dublin Philosophical Society, translated works by Galileo and Descartes, and published many papers in the Royal Society’s Philosophical Transactions. He also worked on problems of vision and optics, writing treatises on the moon illusion, double vision, and telescopes later collected and published in his book Dioptrica Nova Molyneux (2000). This background gave him a sufficient understanding and interest in experimental design and problems in vision with little indication of an interest in the relationship between vision and touch, further suggesting an alternative motive for his question.

  25. It might even be said that the delayed testing of the subjects in the modified version strengthens the support for a negative answer regarding visual deprivation effects, as it shows that the subjects eventually do have the capacity for recognizing tactually familiar shapes by sight alone though decidedly not at first sight.

  26. In addition, these explanations exist on the same level of explanation and discipline of study. As Held (2009) explains, the later recognition of shapes by the newly sighted is evidence of the function of neural processes—the neural representations underlying visual shape recognition, processes which are not utilizable until further visual and tactile experiences enable cognitive re-mapping of the cross-modal transfer pathways.

  27. Molyneux’s stated answer is ambiguous about a number of particulars and distinctions now common to any analysis of Molyneux’s Question. For instance, he employs what appears to be a proto-phenomenological reply, focused on what must be the case given the nature of the experience of the newly sighted. However, the context of the question; written as a query to Locke whom clearly influenced the Molyneux’s thought on this topic, suggests that Molyneux’s point of concern was the epistemology of concepts and their acquisition by experience alone.

  28. Molyneux conflates precisely what individuates the senses: the different properties of objects to which they are tuned to acquire or the different experiences that they generate.

  29. See Stratton (1897) for an early study on the experiential effects of inverted goggle use and Linden et al. (1999) for an update.

  30. “Subjects, who wore prism-and mirror-inverting spectacles over periods of 6–10 days, showed a rapid visuomotor adaptation and were able to interact correctly with the surrounding world after a few days.” Linden et al. (1999: 480).

  31. Held et al. (2011: 533).

  32. See also Grice (1962), whose reflection on possible alien senses and their individuation clearly applies to an answer to Molyneux’s question, though is never explicitly applied.

  33. While this is not direct empirical evidence for affirming Molyneux’s question, as real world visual and tactile experience is allowed in the interim between the first and second tests, it is suggestive that a more direct test might be administered that blindfolds subjects in the process of healing between testing, using novel stimuli in both occasions. This would generate data that is both empirically true and philosophically relevant, and likely in the affirmative given the initial data from the modified cataract paradigm.

  34. Another way to put this objection is to say that Molyneux’s question is really an empirical question and outside the scope of philosophical analysis. Still another way to make this point is to exploit the now common claim that ‘software’ is reducible to ‘hardware,’ wherein talk about the functionality of cross-modal concepts is really just talk of the functionality of cross-modal pathways.

References

  • Bechtel W (1990) Multiple levels of inquiry in cognitive science. Psychol Res 52(2–3):271–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley G (1933/1975) The theory of vision vindicated and explained in philosophical works. Including the works on vision edited by M. Ayers, Dent, London

  • Bermudez JL (2005) Philosophy of psychology: A contemporary introduction. Routledge

  • Bickle J (1998) Psychoneural reduction: The new wave. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruno M, Mandelbaum E (2010) Locke’s answer to molyneux’s thought experiment. History of Philosophy Quarterly 27(2):165–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne A (2002) Something about Mary. Grazer Philos Stud 62:123–140 (Essays in Honour of the Philosophy of Terence Horgan J Brandl, O Markic)

  • Byrne A (2006) Book Review: There’s Something About Mary. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/24952-there-s-something-about-mary

  • Campbell J (1996) Molyneux’s question. In: Villanueva E (ed) Perception: philosophical issues, vol 7. Ridgeview Publishing Company, California, pp 301–318

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell J (2005) Information-processing, phenomenal consciousness, and Molyneux’s question. In: Bermúdez JL (ed) Thought, reference, and experience. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 195–219

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cattaneo Z, Vecchi T (2011) Blind vision: the neuroscience of visual impairment. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheseldon W (1728) An account of some observations made by a young gentleman, who was born blind, or lost his sight so early, that he had no remembrance of ever having seen, and was couch’d between 13 and 14 years of age. Philosophical Transactions 35:447–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PS (1986) Neurophilosophy. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1989) A neurocomputational perspective: the nature of mind and the structure of science. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Degenaar M (1996) Molyneux’s problem: three centuries of discussion on the perception of forms (trans: Collins MJ) Kluwer, Boston

  • Delbeke J, Veraart C (2006) Visual Prostheses. In: John W (ed) Encyclopedia of medical devices and instrumentation. John Wiley and Sons, 530–549

  • Devitt M, Sterelny K (1999) Language and reality. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Diderot D (1749/1972) Letter on the blind for the use of those who see. In: Diderot’s early philosophical works (trans: Jourdain M) Burt Franklin, New York

  • Downing PE, Chan AW, Peelen MV, Dodds CM, Kanwisher N (2006) Domain specificity in visual cortex. Cereb Cortex 16(10):1453–1461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans G (1985) Molyneux’s question. In: McDowell J (ed) Collected papers. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Farah MJ (2004) Visual agnosia. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine I, Wade A, Brewer A, May M, Goodman D, Boynton G, Wandell B, MacLeod D (2003) Long-term deprivation affects visual perception and cortex. Nat Neurosci 6(9):909–910

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2005) Neurons and neonates: reflections on the Molyneux system. In: How the body shapes the mind. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 153–172

  • Gaut B (2000) Art’ as a cluster concept. In: Carroll N (ed) Theories of art today. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 25–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghazanfar AA, Turesson HK (2008) Speech production: how does a word feel? Current Biology. 18:R1142–R1144

  • Glenney B (2012a) Leibniz on Molyneux’s question. Hist Philos Q 29(3):247–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenney B (2012b) The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ISSN 2161-0002. http://www.iep.utm.edu/. 15 Feb 2012

  • Goodale MA, Milner DA (2004) Sight Unseen. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory RL (2003) Seeing after blindness. Nat Neurosci 6(9):909–910

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice HP (1962/2011) Some remarks about the senses. The senses: classical and contemporary philosophical perspectives. Oxford UP, New York, pp 83–100

  • Hebb D (1949/2002) Organization of behavior. Psychology Press, New Jersey

  • Held R (2009) Visual-haptic mapping and the origin of cross-modal identity. Optom Vis Sci 86(6):595–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Held R, Freedman S (1963) Plasticity in human sensorimotor control. Science 142:455–462

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Held R, Ostrovsky Y, de Gelder B, Gandhi T, Ganesh S, Mathur U, Sinha P (2011) The newly sighted fail to match seen with felt. Nat Neurosci 14(5):551–553

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins R (2005) Molyneux’s Question. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35(3):441–464

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacomuzzi A, Kobau P, Bruno P (2003) Molyneux’s question: redux. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 2:255–280

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jurin J (1738) A compleat system of opticks in four books. Robert Smith, Cambridge, pp 42–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirk R (2006) Zombies and consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • La Mettrie J (1750/1996) Treatise on the soul. In: A Thompson A (eds) Machine man and other writings. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 41–73

  • Leibniz G (1760/1981) New Essays on the Human Understanding [trans: Remnant P, Bennett J (eds)] Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Levin J (2008) Molyneux’s question and the individuation of perceptual concepts. Philos Stud 139:1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Linden D, Kallenbach U, Heinecke A, Singer W, Goebel R (1999) The myth of upright vision: a psychophysical and functional imaging study of adaptation to inverted spectacles. Perception 28:469–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1694/1979) An essay concerning human understanding. In: Nidditch PH (eds) Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Longworth F, Scarantino A (2010) The disjunctive theory of art: the cluster account reformulated. Br J Aesthet Advance Access, 10 March 2010

  • Ludlow P, Nagasawa Y, Stoljar D (2004) There’s something about Mary: essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus PD (2012) What species can teach us about theory. Unpublished manuscript. http://www.fecundity.com/job/paper.php?item=speciesanalogy

  • Marr D (1982) Vision. Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff AN (1993) Molyneux’s babies: cross-modal perception, imitation, and the mind of the preverbal infant. In N. Eilan, R. McCarthy, & B. Brewer (eds) Spatial representation: problems in philosophy and psychology. Blackwell, 219–235

  • Miller G (2011) Formerly blind children shed light on a centuries-old puzzle. Science Now, 10 April 2011

  • Molyneux W (2000) Dioptrica nova. Benjamin Tooke, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MJ (1977) Molyneux’s question: vision, touch, and the philosophy of perception. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasaw Y, Daniel S, Ludlow P (2004) There’s something about Mary: essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë A (2004) Action in perception. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrovsky Y, Andalman A, Sinha P (2006) Vision following extended congenital blindness. Psychol Sci 17(12):1009–1014

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie E (1997) Du problème de molyneux au problème de Bach-y-Rita (From Molyneux’s problem to Bach-y-Rita’s problem). In: Proust J (ed) Perception et intermodalité, approches actuelles du problème de molyneux. PUF, Paris, pp 255–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascual-Leone A, Hamilton R (2001) The metamodal organization of the brain. Prog Brain Res 134:427–445

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston JM, Bishop MA (2002) Views into the Chinese room: new essays on Searle and artificial intelligence. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2002) Furnishing the mind: concepts and their perceptual basis. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1962) The analytic and the synthetic in scientific explanation, space, and time. In: Herbert F, Grover M (eds) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol 3. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 358–397

  • Reid T (1764/1997) An inquiry into the human mind. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

  • Searle J (1958) Proper names. Mind 112:447–492

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1795/1982) On the external senses. In: Wightman WPD, Bryce JC (eds) Essays on philosophical subjects. Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, pp 133–170

  • Stalker D (ed) (1994) Grue! The new riddle of induction. Open Court, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Stratton GM (1897) Vision without inversion of the retinal image. Psychol Rev 4:341–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (1959) Individuals. Methuen, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Streri A, Gentaz E (2003) Cross-modal recognition of shape from hand to eyes and handedness in human newborns. Somatosens Mot Res 20(1):11–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve J (2007) Reid’s answer to Molyneux’s question. Monist 90(2):251–270

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire (1738/1967) Elements of newton’s philosophy. (trans: Hanna J) F. Cass, London

  • Von Senden M (1960) Space and sight (trans: Peter H) The Free Press, Illinois

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian R. Glenney.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Glenney, B.R. Philosophical problems, cluster concepts, and the many lives of Molyneux’s question. Biol Philos 28, 541–558 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9355-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9355-x

Keywords

Navigation