Skip to main content
Log in

Explaining how and explaining why: developmental and evolutionary explanations of dominance

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There have been two different schools of thought on the evolution of dominance. On the one hand, followers of Wright [Wright S. 1929. Am. Nat. 63: 274–279, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago; 1934. Am. Nat. 68: 25–53, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago; Haldane J.B.S. 1930. Am. Nat. 64: 87–90; 1939. J. Genet. 37: 365–374; Kacser H. and Burns J.A. 1981. Genetics 97: 639–666] have defended the view that dominance is a product of non-linearities in gene expression. On the other hand, followers of Fisher [Fisher R.A. 1928a. Am. Nat. 62: 15–126; 1928b. Am. Nat. 62: 571–574; Bürger R. 1983a. Math. Biosci. 67: 125–143; 1983b. J. Math. Biol. 16: 269–280; Wagner G. and Burger R. 1985. J. Theor. Biol. 113: 475–500; Mayo O. and Reinhard B. 1997. Biol. Rev. 72: 97–110] have argued that dominance evolved via selection on modifier genes. Some have called these “physiological” versus “selectionist,” or more recently [Falk R. 2001. Biol. Philos. 16: 285–323], “functional,” versus “structural” explanations of dominance. This paper argues, however, that one need not treat these explanations as exclusive. While one can disagree about the most likely evolutionary explanation of dominance, as Wright and Fisher did, offering a “physiological” or developmental explanation of dominance does not render dominance “epiphenomenal,” nor show that evolutionary considerations are irrelevant to the maintenance of dominance, as some [Kacser H. and Burns J.A. 1981. Genetics 97: 639–666] have argued. Recent work [Gilchrist M.A. and Nijhout H.F. 2001. Genetics 159: 423–432] illustrates how biological explanation is a multi-level task, requiring both a “top-down” approach to understanding how a pattern of inheritance or trait might be maintained in populations, as well as “bottom-up” modeling of the dynamics of gene expression.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Allchin D. 2005. The dilemma of dominance Biol. Philos. 20: 427–451

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin D. 2002. Dissolving dominance. In: Parker L., Ankeny R. (eds) Mutating Concepts, Evolving Disciplines: Genetics, Medicine and Society. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 43–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Bürger R. 1983a. Dynamics of the classical genetic model for the evolution of dominance Math. Biosci. 67: 125–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bürger R. 1983b. Nonlinear analysis of some models for the evolution of dominance J. Math. Biol. 16: 269–280

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castle W.E. 1906. Yellow mice and gametic purity Science 31: 275–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castle W.E. 1914. Piebald rats and selection: an experimental test of the effectiveness of selection and of the theory of gametic purity in Mendelian crosses Carnegie Inst. Publ. 195: 1–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Correns C. G. (1900) (1950). “Mendel’s law concerning the behavior of progeny in varietal hybrids” (Eng. Trans.), Genetics 35(5:2): 33–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T. 1927. Studies on the manifold effects of certain genes in Drosophila Melanogaster. Z. Indukt. Abstamm. Vererbungfl. 43: 330–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • East E.M. 1910. A Mendelian interpretation of variation that is apparently continuous. Am. Nat. 44:65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk R. 2001. The rise and fall of dominance Biol. Philos. 16: 285–323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R.A. 1922. On the dominance ratio Proc. R. Soc. Edinburgh 42: 321–341

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R.A. 1928a The possible modification of the response of the wild type to recurrent mutations Am. Nat. 62: 15–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R.A. 1928b. Two further notes on the origin of dominance. Am. Nat. 62: 571–574

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R.A. 1929. The evolution of dominance: a reply to Professor Sewall Wright Am. Nat. 63: 553–556

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R.A. 1930a. The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford: Clarendon press. 2nd ed., 1958. New York: Dover

  • Fisher R.A. 1930b. The distribution of gene ratios for rare mutations. Proc. R. Soc. Edinburgh 50: 205–220

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R.A. 1931. Evolution of dominance. Biol. Rev. 6: 345–368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilchrist M.A., Nijhout H.F. 2001. Nonlinear developmental processes as sources of dominance. Genetics 159: 423–432

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane J.B.S. 1930. A note on Fisher’s theory of the origin of dominance and linkage. Am. Nat. 64: 87–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane J.B.S. 1939. The theory of the evolution of dominance. J. Genet. 37: 365–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kacser H., Burns J.A. 1981. The molecular basis of dominance. Genetics 97: 639–666

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J. 1989. Evolutionary Genetics Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo O., Reinhard B. 1997. The evolution of dominance: a theory whose time has passed? Biol. Rev. 72: 97–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan T.H., Bridges C., Sturtevant A. 1925. The Genetics of Drosophila. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendel, G. 1865. Experiments in Plant Hybridization. Proceedings of the Natural History Society of Bruenn, pp. 3–47

  • Nijhout H.F., Paulsen S.M. 1997. Developmental models and polygenic characters Am. Nat. 149: 394–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul D. 1995. Controlling Human Heredity: 1865 to the Present Humanity Books

  • Provine W. 1986a. Sewall Wright and Evolutionary Biology University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine W. 1986b. Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine, W. 1992. The R.A. Fisher–Sewall Wright controversy. In: Sarkar (ed.), The Founders of Evolutionary Genetics, pp. 201–229

  • Sarkar S. 1998. Genetics and Reductionism Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L., Sober E. 2006. Epiphenomenalism – The Do’s and The Don’ts. In: Wolters G., Machamer P. (eds) Studies in Causality: Historical and Contemporary. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Tschermark E. 1900 (1950). Concerning Artificial crossing in Pisum sativum.” Genetics 35(5:2): 42–47

  • Wagner G., Bürger R. 1985. On the evolution of dominance in modifiers. II A non-equilibrium approach to the evolution of genetic systems. J. Theor. Biol. 113: 475–500

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright S. 1923a. Mendelian Analysis of Pure Breeds of Livestock I: The Measurement of Inbreeding and relationship. J. Hered. 14: 339–348, In: Provine (ed.) 1986, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1923b. Mendelain Analysis of Pure Breeds of Livestock II: The Duchess Family of Shorthorns as Bread by Thomas Bates. J. Hered. 14. 405–422. In: Provine (ed.) 1986, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1925. The Shorthorns, J. Hered. 16(6): 205–215. In: Provine (ed.) 1986, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1929. Fisher’s Theory of Dominance. Am. Nat. 63: 274–279. In: Provine (ed.) 1986, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1930. Review of the Genetical Theory of Natural Selection by R.A. Fisher. J. Hered. 21. 349–356. In: Provine (ed.) 1986, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1931. Evolution in Mendelian Populations. Genetics 16: 97–159. In: Provine (ed.) 1986, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1932. The Roles of Inbreeding, Crossbreeding and Selection in Evolution. Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Genetics 1: 356–366. In: Provine (ed.) 1986b, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1934. Physiological and Evolutionary Theories of Dominance. Am. Nat. 68: 25–53. In: Provine (ed.) 1986b, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S. 1978. The Relation of Livestock Breeding to Theories of Evolution, J. Anim. Sci. 46: 1192–1200. In: Provine (ed.) 1986b, Evolution: Selected Papers by Sewall Wright, University of Chicago Press, Chicago

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Sahotra Sarkar, Ron Amundson, Steve Downes, and two anonymous reviewers for their generous feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anya Plutynski.

Appendix

Appendix

Mutation Selection Balance (From Maynard Smith 1989)

Consider a large population of size N, where a is the wildtype allele at frequency q, and A is the mutant allele, at frequency p. So:

Genoätypes

aa

Aa

AA

Fitäness

1

1-hs

1-s

Numäber of zygotes

Nq 2

2Npq

Np 2

There are 2Npq Aa zygotes, of which a proportion hs die, eliminating one A gene. Further, there are Np 2 AA homozygotes, of which s die in each generation, eliminating two A genes with each death. So, the number of A genes lost by selection in each generation will be

$$ 2N_{pqhs} + 2N_{p{\hbox{2}}s} = 2Nps(qh + p) $$

Further, in each new generation, new A genes arise by mutation. Let the mutation rate be u. Thus, since there are 2Nq a genes in each population, there will be 2Nqu new A genes each generation. At equilibrium, (mutation–selection balance), the number of new mutations will equal the number eliminated. Or:

$$ 2N_{qu} = 2N_{ps} (qh + p) $$

Or,

$$ qu = \,{\hbox{ }}ps(qh + p) $$

If A is fully recessive to a, or h = 0, then qu = p 2 s, so, since p approximately = 1

$$ p = \surd (u/s) $$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Plutynski, A. Explaining how and explaining why: developmental and evolutionary explanations of dominance. Biol Philos 23, 363–381 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-006-9047-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-006-9047-5

Keywords

Navigation