Skip to main content
Log in

Mathematical Understanding by Thought Experiments

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The goal of this paper is to answer the following question: Does it make sense to speak of thought experiments not only in physics, but also in mathematics, to refer to an authentic type of activity? One may hesitate because mathematics as such is the exercise of reasoning par excellence, an activity where experience does not seem to play an important role. After reviewing some results of the research on thought experiments in the natural sciences, we turn our attention to experiments and thought experiments in mathematics, especially in fundamental mathematics, and investigate what thought experiments can teach us there. If we accept the principle that mathematical practice can sometimes be best described by a pragmatist approach where the concept of experience in mathematics is considered from a new perspective, thought experiments can in some cases be a useful instrument different from both ‘mathematical experiments’ and ‘formal’ proofs: they are mathematical experiments using deviant methods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Nevertheless, according to Imre Lakatos (1976, 11) ‘Thought experiment was the most ancient pattern of mathematical proof.’ Lakatos, as Ernst Mach before him, contrasted informal thought experiments in number theory and geometry—which start from observations – with formal proofs. Here, thought experiments are also linked to informal proofs or to the starting point of mathematics from experience.

  2. With respect to the mode of comprehension, this point was actually already put forth in arguments against the logicisation of mathematical proofs: according to Poincaré, a proof in its logical form is conceptually insufficient for understanding the extensive character of the result with respect to the premises. For experimental mathematicians, ‘formal’ proofs are sometimes incomprehensible due to their excessively abstract character. Poincaré wishes to supplement the standard ‘formalism’ of proof by an architecture (cf. Detlefsen 1992), while the experimental mathematicians would supplement it by a calculation.

  3. According to a tradition spanning from Peirce to the Erlangen School of Lorenzen/Lorenz, the pragmatic approach can be characterised by a set of at least five theses:

    (1) It is a method, not a system.

    (2) Abandoning every absolute empirical criterion or absolute rationale, it takes as its basis observations and statements of common sense.

    (3) It admits a convergence between ontology and the theory of knowledge and considers fruitfulness as an important criterion for the acceptability of propositions.

    (4) It rejects a separation in principle between the context of justification and the context of invention as well as between the context of justification and the context of understanding.

    (5) It admits a correlation between knowledge and value.

    By forming this picture, my aim is neither to articulate a particular historical position held by various thinkers, nor do I intend to present the features shared by such positions.

  4. The function sin(x) and the infinite product have exactly the same roots and have the same value at x = 0 and so “Euler asserts that they describe the same function. Euler is correct that they describe the same function, but these reasons are insufficient to guarantee it. For example, the function \(e^{X} \frac{{sinx}}{x}\) also has the same roots and the same value at x = 0, but is a different function.” (Sandifer 2003, 1).

References:

  • Ayoub R (1974) Euler and the Zeta Function. Am Math Mon 81:1067–1086

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borwein J and Bailey D (2004) Mathematics by Experiment: plausible reasoning in the 21st Century, Natick MA: AK Peters

  • Brown JR (1986) Thought experiments since the scientific revolution. Int Stud Philos Sci 1:1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2008) Thought experiment in the natural sciences. An operational and reflective-transcendental conception, Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann

  • Buzzoni M (2011) Kant und das Gedankenexperiment. Über eine kantische Theorie der Gedankenexperimente in den Naturwissenschaften und in der Philosophie. Deut Z Philos 59:93–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2021) Mathematical vs empirical thought experiments. In: Calosi C, Graziani P, Pietrini D and Tarozzi G (eds), Experience, abstraction, and the scientific of the World. Festschrift for Vincenzo Fano on his 60th Birthday, Franco Angeli Editore, Milan, pp 215–228

  • Detlefsen M (1992) Poincaré against the Logicicians. Synthese 90:349–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel P (2011) Philosophical thought experiments: In or out of the armchair? In: Ierodiakonou K and Roux S (eds), Thought experiments in methodological and historical contexts, Leiden–Boston, pp 145–163

  • Goffi, J-Y and Roux S (2018) A dialectical account of thought experiments. In Brown JR, Fehige Y and Stuart M (eds.). A Routledge companion to thought experiment, London–Boston: Routledge, pp 439–453

  • Gonseth F (1945–55) La géométrie et le problème de l'espace, vols. I–VI, Neuchâtel: Griffon

  • Goodman N (1969) Languages of Art. An approach to a theory of symbols. Oxford University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinzmann G (ed) (1986), Poincaré, Russell, Zermelo et Peano. Textes de la discussion (1906–1912) sur les fondements des mathématiques: des antinomies à la prédicativité, Paris: Blanchard

  • Heinzmann G (2013) L’intuition épistémique. Une approche pragmatique du contexte de justification en mathématiques et en philosophie, Paris: Vrin, collection Mathesis

  • Kuhn TS (1977) The essential tension. Selected Studies in scientific tradition and change, Chicago–London: University of Chicago Press

  • Lakatos I (1976) Proofs and refutation – the logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge University Press, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard J (2018) Thought experiments and simulation experiments. Exploring hypothetical worlds. In: Brown JR, Fehige Y, and Stuart M (eds). A Routledge companion to thought experiment, London–Boston: Routledge, pp 484–497

  • Lorenz K (2010) Logic, language and method. On polarities in human experience, Berlin: De Gruyter

  • Marconi D (2017) Philosophical thought experiments: the case for Engel. Philos Sci 21(3):111–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton JD (1996) Are thought experiments just what you thought? Can J Philos 26:333–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton JD (2004) Why thought experiments do not transcend empiricism. In: Hitchcock C (ed) Contemporary debates in the philosophy of science. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 44–66

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1933–1958) Collected papers (edited by Hartshorne Ch and Weiss P), Volume I–VI, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press

  • Poincaré H (1898) On the foundations of geometry. The Monist IX: 1–43

  • Poincaré H (1902) La Science et l’hypothèse, Paris: Flammarion. English translation Science and Hypothesis: the complete text, New York–London: Bloomsbury, 2017

  • Reiss J (2016) Thought experiments in economics and the role of coherent explanations. Stud Metodol 36:113–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars W (1956) Empiricism and the philosophy of mind, Cambridge, MA–London: Harvard University Press (1997)

  • Sandifer Ed (2003) How Euler did it,http://eulerarchive.maa.org/hedi/HEDI-2004-03.pdf

  • Sundholm G (2008) Proofs as acts and proofs as objects: some questions for dag Prawitz. Theoria 64(2–3):187–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundholm G (2012) ‘Inference versus consequence’ revisited: inference, consequence, conditional, implication. Synthese 187:943–956

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank my Nancy colleagues Jean-Pierre Ferrier, Philippe Lombard, and Andrew Arana for their advice and numerous discussions of this article first presented in the FFIUM seminar (French–German ANR/DFG project), where the mathematical example of the Basel problem was presented by Phillipe Lombard, and my proposal in general analysed by Jean-Pierre Ferrier, to whom I am indebted for several other analyses. I am especially grateful to Marco Buzzoni (Macerata), who sparked my interest in this topic, directed me to relevant literature, and shared with me many ideas during our discussions in Macerata, in Nancy and during our distance discussion at the FFIUM seminar. I am grateful to Marco Panza (Chapman (Orange)/Paris-Sorbonne) for his reformulation of the hierarchy in chapter 2.2 and I finally thank Anna Pilatova for her linguistic corrections of an earlier version of this paper, that will be published in the proceedings of the XVIth CDLMPST, hold in Prague. The present version contains substantial improvements to the older Prague paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerhard Heinzmann.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heinzmann, G. Mathematical Understanding by Thought Experiments. Axiomathes 32 (Suppl 3), 871–886 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-022-09640-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-022-09640-4

Keywords

Navigation