Skip to main content
Log in

The Structure of Arguments by Analogy in Law

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Successful accounts of analogy in law have two burdens to discharge. First, they must reflect the fact that the conclusion of an argument by analogy is a normative claim about how to decide a certain case (the target case). Second, they must not fail to accord relevance to the fact that the source case was authoritatively decided in a certain way. We argue in the first half of this paper (Sections 2, 3, 4) that the common view of the structure of analogical arguments in law cannot overcome these hurdles. In the second half (Sections 5, 6, 7) we develop an original account that aims to succeed where others failed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Brewer (1996: 955, 967), with references to other authors who subscribe to this “widely endorsed form” (“analogical argument works this way: on the basis of one or more shared characteristics in a target and a source, a reasoner infers that the target possesses an inferred characteristic that the source is known to possess”). For more examples, see Landau (1981: 77-80), or White (2010: 572).

  2. See also Golding (1988). Our way of graphically representing the argument differs slightly from Golding’s, but the contents are quoted verbatim.

  3. Adams v. New Jersey Steamboat Company 151 NY 163 (1896). Golding is sometimes credited with having “unearthed” this case, but he didn’t: see Hall (1938: 577–578). Authors who discuss Adams include Brewer (1996), Rotolo (2001), Weinreb (2005), Posner (2006), Finnis (2011), and Schauer (2013).

  4. The court also discussed whether a previous case—Carpenter v. New York etc. R.R. Co, 124 N.Y. 53—in which it had been held that “a railroad running sleeping coaches on its road was not liable for the loss of money taken from a passenger while in his berth, during the night, without some proof of negligence on its part”, could be taken to apply—also on the grounds of an analogy—to the case at hand (which of course would have led to the opposite conclusion that the steamboat company ought not to be held liable for the stolen money). The Adams court argued, however, that Carpenter “does not… control the case under consideration… [I]t is quite obvious that the [train] passenger has no right to expect, and in fact does not expect, the same degree of security from thieves while in an open berth in a car on a railroad as in a stateroom of a steamboat, securely locked and otherwise guarded from intrusion”.

  5. As Atienza (1986: 116–120) remarks, this issue had also been raised by several other theorists of analogy; see also Bobbio (1938: 100–101), Kalinowski (1965: 166), and Wellman (1985: 85).

  6. This claim is perhaps too broad—Golding does not specify what he takes “good reason” to mean—but there is no need to dwell on the issue.

  7. The truth of a premise like (6) will depend on several factors, including the absence of stronger competing analogies: see Golding (2001: 110).

  8. When “y” is taken to refer to a general case, a further argument would then be subjoined classifying any particular case at hand as an instance of y, in order to justify the particular normative outcome in that particular case: see Bańkowski (1991: 204–205).

  9. It might be objected that we can only make this point because we have already smuggled the adverb “probably” into our formulation of premise (4), and that that is something that Golding’s scheme does not contemplate. But this objection would be misguided. If we phrase premise (4) without the adverb, then what now follows—again deductively—is that Brown will be a successful salesman.

  10. We have retained here the original numbering of premises and conclusions; and to avoid confusion we used “a” and “b”—rather than “x” and “y”—to stand for the source and the target cases.

  11. See also Bobbio (1938: 87–95), Sunstein (1996: 65–66), Reidhav (2007: 35–36, 72–84), Shecaira (2013: 409, 428–30), and Spielthenner (2014: 867).

  12. Golding himself, however, would not welcome this revision: see note 15 below.

  13. See the text accompanying note 10 above.

  14. See e.g. Patterson (1942: 903–4), Halper (1968: 42), Murray (1982: 847–8), Klug (1982: 115–6), Hunter (2001: 1208, 1252), and Schauer (2009: 98–100); and also Quine and Ullian (1978: 90–95) and Govier (1989: 147–8). The doctrine of binding precedent is sometimes also said to involve reasoning “from case to case”; but here there is normally no implication—on the contrary—that the decision in the second case can dispense with the invocation of a rule. Edward Levi’s well-known description makes this quite clear: “The basic pattern of legal reasoning is reasoning by example. It is reasoning from case to case. It is a three-step process described by the doctrine of precedent in which a proposition descriptive of the first case is made into a rule of law and then applied to a next similar situation”: Levi (1949: 1–2, footnote omitted, emphasis added).

  15. That is why Golding, who himself briefly considers the possibility of interpreting arguments by analogy as “involving two steps”, the first step consisting in “generalizing a broad rule from the prior case(s)”, and the second “in the deduction of the decision” for the instant case from that generalised rule, goes on to say (2001: 103) that “under this interpretation there is, strictly speaking, no argument by analogy at all”.

  16. See e.g. Westen (1982: 1162–3), Eisenberg (1988: 83–96), and Alexander and Sherwin (2008: 66–88); but see, for discussion, Postema (2007: 108–116).

  17. See note 4 above.

  18. As Reidhav (2007: 102–105) points out, the risk of over-inclusiveness is a cost of generalisation.

  19. For some useful surveys of debate, see Cross and Harris (1991: 39–75), Collier (1988), Duxbury (2008: 58–92).

  20. Lawyers sometimes also use the term “distinguishing” in a different sense: they use it to refer to what a court does when, faced with a candidate (and prima facie plausible) formulation of the ratio of a previous decision—a formulation under which the instant case would count as being the “same” as the previous one—it offers and defends an alternative interpretation (or reinterpretation) of that ratio such that it no longer covers the instant case. Note, by contrast, that the sense of “distinguishing” we are concerned with in the text, which the sense in which courts are said to be duty-bound to either “follow” or “distinguish” precedent, actually presupposes that the instant case—the case to be distinguished—is and remains covered by the ratio of the precedent decision: on this point see Raz (2009: 185) and Lamond (2016, Sect. 2.2).

  21. There may be further conditions constraining the scope of permissible distinguishing. For example, there seems to be no room for a court to argue that the ratio of a previous decision was over-inclusive, on the basis that that ratio fails to take into account certain features of the previous case, if the previous court did explicitly take those features into account—if it did assess and discuss their relevance—and declared them to be irrelevant. The scope of permissible distinguishing seems to be restricted to features of the previous case whose relevance the previous court overlooked or failed to consider.

  22. On the qualification of over-inclusive rationes decidendi, see also Hodgson (1967: 122–123, 130–132).

References

  • Alexander, L., and E. Sherwin. 2008. Demystifying legal reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, M. 1986. Sobre la analogía en el Derecho: Ensayo de análisis de un razonamiento jurídico. Madrid: Civitas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. 1911. Lectures on jurisprudence, volume 2, 5th edition, ed. R. Campbell. London: John Murray.

  • Bańkowski, Z. 1991. Analogical reasoning and legal institutions. In Legal knowledge and analogy, ed. P. Nerhot, 198–216. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio, N. 1938. L’Analogia nella logica del diritto. Torino: Istituto Giuridico della R. Università.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boonin, L.G. 1965. The logic of legal decisions. Ethics 75(3): 179–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, S. 1996. Exemplary reasoning: Semantics, pragmatics, and the rational force of legal argument by analogy. Harvard Law Review 109(5): 923–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collier, C.W. 1988. Precedent and legal authority: A critical history. Wisconsin Law Review 1988(5): 771–825.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, R., and J.W. Harris. 1991. Precedent in English law, 4th ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duxbury, N. 2008. The nature and authority of precedent. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, M.A. 1988. The nature of the common law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. 2011. Analogical reasoning in law. In Philosophy of law: Collected essays, vol. IV, ed. J. Finnis, 299–396. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gianformaggio, L. 2008. L’analogia giuridica. In L. Gianformaggio, Filosofia del diritto e ragionamento giuridico, ed. E. Diciotti and V. Veluzzi, 131–147. Torino: Giapichelli.

  • Golding, M.P. 2001. Legal reasoning. Peterborough, ON: Broadview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golding, M.P. 1988. The logical force of arguments by analogy in common law reasoning. In Reason in law: Proceedings of the conference held in Bologna, 12–15 December 1984, vol. 3, ed. C. Faralli, and E. Pattaro, 273–279. Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodhart, A.L. 1930. Determining the ratio decidendi of a case. The Yale Law Journal 40(2): 161–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. 1987. Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. 1989. Analogies and missing premises. Informal Logic 11(3): 141–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, J. (ed.). 1938. Readings in jurisprudence. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halper, T. 1968. Logic in judicial reasoning. Indiana Law Journal 44(1): 33–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, D.H. 1967. The consequences of utilitarianism: A study in normative ethics and legal theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, D. 2001. Reason is too large: Analogy and precedent in law. Emory Law Journal 50(4): 1197–1264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Juthe, A. 2005. Argument by analogy. Argumentation 19(1): 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalinowski, G. 1965. Introduction a la logique juridique: Éléments de sémiotique juridique, logique des normes et logique juridique. Paris: R. Pichon & R. Durand-Auzias.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klug, U. 1982. Juristische Logik, 4th ed. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. 2005. Do precedents create rules? Legal Theory 11(1): 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. 2014. Analogical reasoning in the common law. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 34(3): 567–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. 2016. Precedent and analogy. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/legal-reas-prec/.

  • Landau, J.L. 1981. Logic for lawyers. Pacific Law Journal 13(1): 59–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, E.H. 1949. An introduction to legal reasoning. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, T. 1997. Analogy and argument. Teaching Philosophy 20(1): 49–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, J.R. 1982. The role of analogy in legal reasoning. UCLA Law Review 29(4): 833–871.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, E.W. 1942. Logic in the law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 90(8): 875–909.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R.A. 2006. Reasoning by analogy. Cornell Law Review 91(3): 761–774.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postema, G.J. 2007. A similibus ad similia: Analogical thinking in law. In Common law theory, ed. D.E. Edlin, 102–133. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V., and J.S. Ullian. 1978. The web of belief, 2nd ed. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 2009. Law and value in adjudication. In The authority of law: Essays on law and morality, 2nd ed, ed. J. Raz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reidhav, D. 2007. Reasoning by analogy: A study on analogy-based arguments in law. Lund: Lund University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rinaldi, F. 1971. Is analogy a decision process in English law? Logique et Analyse 14(53–4): 363–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotolo, A. 2001. Identità e somiglianza: Saggio sul pensiero analogico nel diritto. Bologna: Clueb.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. 2008. Why precedent in law (and elsewhere) is not totally (or even substantially) about analogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science 3(6): 454–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. 2009. Thinking like a lawyer: A new introduction to legal reasoning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. 2013. Analogy in the Supreme Court: Lozman v City of Riviera Beach. The Supreme Court Review 2013: 405–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shecaira, F.P. 2013. Analogical arguments in ethics and law: A defence of a deductivist analysis. Informal Logic 33(3): 406–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, A.W.B. 1961. The ratio decidendi of a case and the doctrine of binding precedent. In Oxford essays in jurisprudence, ed. A.G. Guest, 148–175. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spielthenner, G. 2014. Analogical reasoning in ethics. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17(5): 861–874.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C.R. 1993. On analogical reasoning. Harvard Law Review 106(3): 741–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C.R. 1996. Legal reasoning and political conflict. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinreb, L.L. 2005. Legal reason: The use of analogy in legal argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, V.A. 1985. Practical reasoning and judicial justification: Toward an adequate theory. University of Colorado Law Review 57(1): 45–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westen, P. 1982. On ‘confusing ideas’: Reply. The Yale Law Journal 91(6): 1153–1165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, J. 2010. Analogical reasoning. In A companion to philosophy of law and legal theory, 2nd ed, ed. Dennis Patterson, 571–577. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments and discussion, we are grateful to Matthew H. Kramer, Euan MacDonald, Pedro Múrias, Fábio Perin Shecaira, and Katharina Stevens; to the Edinburgh Legal Theory Research Group; to audiences in Edinburgh, Oxford, Heidelberg, Lisbon, San Francisco, Washington (DC), London, Freiburg, Lund, and Kingston (Ontario); and to the anonymous reviewers for Argumentation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luís Duarte d’Almeida.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Duarte d’Almeida, L., Michelon, C. The Structure of Arguments by Analogy in Law. Argumentation 31, 359–393 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-016-9409-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-016-9409-3

Keywords

Navigation