Skip to main content
Log in

Are employee stock option exercise decisions better explained through the prospect theory?

  • S.I.: Financial Economics
  • Published:
Annals of Operations Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we introduce a new framework for the analysis of employee stock options exercise decisions. We develop a distorted lattice model where the exercise decision obeys a policy that maximizes the expected value of the exercise outcomes under the Cumulative Prospect Theory. Using a large US dataset of exercise transactions, we show that our framework broadly outperforms the Expected Utility Theory framework in explaining empirical exercise decisions. Interestingly, our empirical estimates of probability weighting are consistent with those from the experimental literature. We argue that this analysis provides a unifying stream for thinking about issues related to the exercise and the valuation of stock options.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The lower boundary at 0.279 is a technical restriction to ensure that \(\partial \psi _a \left( p \right) /\partial p\) is positive over ]0,1[. This constraint ensures that the probability weighting function can not assign negative decision weights consistent with first-order stochastic dominance. For further details see Ingersoll (2008).

  2. An interesting alternative to the CPT probability weighting function is using weighting functions implied by listed options prices. This approach uses non-parametric methods to estimate state price densities from listed options prices. These estimates are then used as building blocks to construct non-parametric estimators of the weighting function without imposing any constraint on the shape of the former. For more details on this approach see Polkovnichenko and Zhao (2013).

  3. See for instance Grasselli and Henderson (2009).

  4. The term “employee” is used to refer to all company insider labour categories, including executives as well as non executive employees.

  5. Depending on the company listing stock exchange, betas were estimated either against the NYSE Composite index or the NASDAQ Composite index.

  6. The optimization problem was solved numerically based on a Monte Carlo approach. This method consists in randomly drawing parameter values within their definition domains. The drawn values are saved if they yield a lower error value than the previous one. This process is retrieved until either the error threshold (i.e. \(10^{-5})\) is hit or the maximum number of trials (i.e. 10,000) is achieved.

  7. Tversky and Kahneman (1992) got 0.65 on average (0.61 for gains and 0.69 for losses). These results are corroborated by Abdellaoui’s (2000) findings (0.60 for gains and 0.70 for losses, hence an average of 0.65) and those in Gonzalez and Wu (1996) (0.71 for gains).

  8. Their model variant ignores, however, the exit amount y.

References

  • Abdellaoui, M. (2000). Parameter-free elicitation of utility and probability weighting functions. Management Science, 46(11), 1497–1512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., & Munier, B. (1998). The risk-structure dependence effect: Experimenting with an eye to decision-aiding. Annals of Operations Research, 80, 237–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arkes, H. R., Hirshleifer, D., Jiang, D., & Lim, S. (2008). Reference point adaptation: Tests in the domain of security trading. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 105(1), 67–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bahaji, H. (2011). Incentives from stock option grants: a behavioural approach. Review of Accounting and Finance, 10(3), 200–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bahaji, H., & Casta, J. F. (2015). Employee stock option-implied risk attitude under rank-dependent expected utility. Economic Modelling, 52, 144–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberis, N. C. (2013). Thirty years of prospect theory in economics: A review and assessment. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 27(1), 173–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bettis, J., Bizjak, J., & Lemmon, M. (2005). Exercise behavior, valuation and the incentive effects of employee stock options. Journal of Financial Economics, 76(2), 445–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, M., Sundaram, R., & Yermack, D. (2000). Altering the terms of executive stock options. Journal of Financial Economics, 57(1), 103–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter, J. (1998). The exercise and valuation of executive stock options. Journal of Financial Economics, 48(2), 127–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Detemple, J., & Sundaresan, S. (1999). Nontraded asset valuation with portfolio constraints: A binomial approach. Review of Economic Studies, 12(4), 835–872.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dittmann, I., Maug, E., & Spalt, O. G. (2010). Sticks or carrots? Optimal CEO compensation when managers are loss averse. Journal of Finance, 65(6), 2015–2050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, R., & Wu, G. (1996). Curvature of the probability weighting function. Management Science, 42(12), 1676–1690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grasselli, M., & Henderson, V. (2009). Risk aversion and block exercise of executive stock options. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 33(1), 109–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, C., Huddart, S., & Lang, M. (1999). Psychological factors and stock option exercise. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(2), 601–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hemmer, T., Matsunaga, S., & Shevlin, T. (1996). The influence of risk diversification on the early exercise of employee stock options by executive officers. Journal of Accounting and Economics, 21(1), 45–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, F., Rajgopal, S., & Shevlin, T. (2010). Do managers value stock options and restricted stock consistent with economic theory? Contemporary Accounting Research, 26(3), 899–932.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huddart, S. (1994). Employee stock options. Journal of Accounting and Economics, 18(2), 207–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huddart, S., & Lang, M. (1996). Employee stock option exercises: An empirical analysis. Journal of Accounting and Economics, 21(1), 5–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • IBBOTSON ASSOCIATES (2006). Stocks, bonds, bills, and inflation. Valuation edition, 2006 Yearbook.

  • Ingersoll, J. (2008). Non-monotonicity of the Tversky-Kahneman probability-weighting function: A Cautionary note. European Financial Management, 14(3), 385–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jennergren, L., & Naslund, B. (1993). A comment on “valuation of executive stock options and the FASB proposal”. The Accounting Review, 68(1), 179–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, E., & Napp, C. (2012). Behavioral biases and the representative agent. Theory and Decision, 73(1), 97–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malmendier, U., & Tate, G. (2005). CEO overconfidence and corporate investment. Journal of Finance, 60(6), 2661–2700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Misra, L., & Shi, Y. (2005). Option exercise by CEOs: Overconfidence VS market timing. Working paper, Texas University.

  • Polkovnichenko, V., & Zhao, F. (2013). Probability weighting functions implied in options prices. Journal of Financial Economics, 107(3), 580–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3(4), 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sautner, Z., & Weber, M. (2005). Stock options and Employee Behavior. Working paper, Mannheim university.

  • Spalt, O. (2013). Probability weighting and employee stock options. Journal of Financial and Quantitative analysis, 48(4), 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spranca, M., Minsk, E., & Baron, J. (1991). Omission and commission in judgment and choice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 27(1), 76–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4), 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hamza Bahaji.

Appendices

Appendix 1

Proof of proposition 1

Let \(B_{i,j} =\left( {{\begin{array}{l} i \\ j \\ \end{array} }} \right) p^{j}\left( {1-p} \right) ^{i-j}\) be the probability of reaching node (ij). The proof can be established by recursion as follows:

For \(i=0\), one can check that \(\overline{{p}}_{0,0} =\psi _a \left( {1-p} \right) =1-p_{0,0} \), which implies \(0<\overline{{p}}_{0,0} <1\), and therefore \(0<p_{0,0} <1\).

For \(i=1\), we have \(\overline{{p}}_{1,0} =\frac{\omega _{2,0} }{\zeta _{1,0} }=\frac{\psi _a \left( {B_{1,0} \left( {1-p} \right) } \right) }{\psi _a \left( {B_{1,0} } \right) }\), then \(0<\overline{{p}}_{1,0} <1\) since \(\psi _a \left( . \right) \) is increasing. We have also \(\overline{{p}}_{1,1} =\frac{\omega _{2,1} -\left( {1-\overline{{p}}_{1,0} } \right) \zeta _{1,0} }{\zeta _{1,1} }=\frac{\psi _a \left( {B_{2,1} +B_{2,0} } \right) -\psi _a \left( {B_{1,0} } \right) }{1-\psi _a \left( {B_{1,0} } \right) }\). Given that \(B_{2,1} +B_{2,0} >B_{1,0} \), we conclude that \(0<\overline{{p}}_{1,1} <1\). Finally, from \(p_{1,1} =\frac{\omega _{2,2} }{\zeta _{1,1} }=\frac{1-\psi _a \left( {B_{2,1} +B_{2,0} } \right) }{1-\psi _a \left( {B_{1,0} } \right) }\), we deduce that \(0<p_{1,1} <1\).

For \(i>1\), assume now that \(0<\overline{{p}}_{k,j} <1\) and \(0<p_{k,j} <1 \forall k\le i,j\le k\), then prove that the inequalities hold for \(k=i+1,\forall j\le i+1\). The inequality holds for \(j=0\) since \(\overline{{p}}_{i+1,0} =\frac{\omega _{i+1,0} }{\zeta _{i,0} }=\frac{\psi _a \left( {B_{i,0} \left( {1-p} \right) } \right) }{\psi _a \left( {B_{i,0} } \right) }\). For \(j>0\), we have:

$$\begin{aligned} \overline{{p}}_{i+1,j}= & {} \frac{\omega _{i+2,j} -\left( {1-\overline{{p}}_{i+1,j-1} } \right) \zeta _{i+1,j-1} }{\zeta _{i+1,j} }=\frac{\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^j {\omega _{i+2,l} } -\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^{j-1} {\omega _{i+1,l} } }{\omega _{i+1,j} }\nonumber \\= & {} \frac{\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^j {B_{i+2,l} } } \right) -\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^{j-1} {B_{i+1,l} } } \right) }{\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^j {B_{i+1,l} } } \right) -\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^{j-1} {B_{i+1,l} } } \right) } \end{aligned}$$
(47)

Given that the binomial distribution increases stochastically as i increases, we have:

\(\sum _{l=0}^{j-1} {B_{i+1,l} } <\sum _{l=0}^j {B_{i+2,l} } <\sum _{l=0}^j {B_{i+1,l} } ,\) which implies that \(0<\overline{{p}}_{i+1,j} <1\) since \(\psi _a \left( . \right) \) is increasing.

In the same way, noting that\(p_{i+1,i+1} =\frac{\omega _{i+2,i+2} }{\zeta _{i+1,i+1} }=\frac{1-\psi _a \left( {\sum _{l=0}^{i+1} {B_{i+2,l} } } \right) }{1-\psi _a \left( {\sum _{l=0}^i {B_{i+1,l} } } \right) }\), we obtain \(0<p_{i+1,i+1} <1\). This completes the proof. \(\square \)

Appendix 2

Proof of proposition 2

Let’s proceed by recursion as previously done:

For \(i=0\), we have \(\overline{{p}}_{0,0} =\psi _a \left( {1-p} \right) =1-p_{0,0} \).

For i=1, one may check that \(\overline{{p}}_{1,1} +p_{1,1} =1\).

For \(i>1\), assume the relationship is verified for i, then prove it for \(i+1\). The transition decision weights at the top node verify:

$$\begin{aligned} 1-\overline{{p}}_{i+1,i+1} =1-\frac{\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^{i+1} {B_{i+2,l} } } \right) -\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^i {B_{i+1,l} } } \right) }{1-\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{l=0}^i {B_{i+1,l} } } \right) }=p_{i+1,i+1} \end{aligned}$$

Proposition 2 states that transition decision weights are unique and may interpret as distorted (i.e. skewed) transition probabilities. There exist at least two different sets of transition decision weights at a given level of the tree leading to the weighted probabilities at the next level (i.e. allow connecting both levels of the tree). The first set is the one retrieved by the algorithm from (5) to (20). The second set is given by a modified version of this algorithm that consists in departing from the top nodes (\(j=i)\) towards the bottom nodes (\(j=0)\), which boils down to taking \(\overline{{p}}_{i,i} =1-p_{i,i} \) instead of (20), and \(\overline{{p}}_{i,0} =\frac{\omega _{i+1,1} -\overline{{p}}_{i,1} \zeta _{i,1} }{\zeta _{i,0} }\) instead of (16). Proposition 2 implies that the two sets are identical. This completes the proof. \(\square \)

Appendix 3

Proof of proposition 3

Consider a given state (ij) where the option is in the money, which means that \(j>\left( {\frac{i}{2}1\hbox {I}_{\left\{ {i\hbox { mod }2=0} \right\} } +\frac{i+1}{2}1\hbox {I}_{\left\{ {i\hbox { mod }2=1} \right\} } } \right) \). In order to show that the probability of exercise increases in the degree of probability weighting (Resp. decreases in a), it suffices to prove that this is true at each node (kl) leading to node (ij) where the option is exercisable, which also boils down to showing that the state subjective value is decreasing in a. Let’s denote the exercise probability at the states (kl) by \(\pi _{k,l} =P\left\{ {Ce_{k,l} <h_{k,l} } \right\} \). Let’s also leave aside the exit state for sake of simplicity (\(p_e =0\)) since it does not affect the sensitivity of \(Ce_{k,l} \)to a. This allows restating the subjective value as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} Ce_{k,l} =v_{\theta _k }^{-1} \left( {p_{k,l} v_{\theta _k } \left( {V_{k+1,l+1}^0 } \right) +\overline{{p}}_{k,l} v_{\theta _k } \left( {V_{k+1,l}^0 } \right) } \right) e^{-r\delta t} \end{aligned}$$

Given that the value function and its reciprocal in (35) are both monotonically increasing, a sufficient condition for \(Ce_{k,l} \) to decrease in a is that \(p_{k,l} \) is a decreasing function of a for \(l>\left( {\frac{k}{2}1\hbox {I}_{\left\{ {k\hbox { mod }2=0} \right\} } +\frac{k+1}{2}1\hbox {I}_{\left\{ {k\hbox { mod }2=1} \right\} } } \right) \). We have from (47):

$$\begin{aligned} p_{k,l} \left( a \right) =\frac{\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{h=0}^l {B_{k,h} } } \right) -\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{h=0}^l {B_{k+1,h} } } \right) }{\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{h=0}^l {B_{k,h} } } \right) -\psi _a \left( {\sum \nolimits _{h=0}^{l-1} {B_{k,h} } } \right) }=\frac{\psi _a \left( {A_{k,l} } \right) -\psi _a \left( {A_{k+1,l} } \right) }{\psi _a \left( {A_{k,l} } \right) -\psi _a \left( {A_{k,l-1} } \right) }, \hbox { with } A_{k,l-1} <A_{k+1,l} <A_{k,l} . \end{aligned}$$

A second order Taylor series expansion of \(\psi _a \left( . \right) \) around \(A_0 \ge 0.5\) gives for some \(a<b<1\):

$$\begin{aligned} p_{k,l} \left( a \right) -p_{k,l} \left( b \right) \approx D_{k,l} \left( {{\psi }'_a \left( {A_0 } \right) {\psi }''_b \left( {A_0 } \right) -{\psi }'_b \left( {A_0 } \right) {\psi }''_a \left( {A_0 } \right) } \right) \end{aligned}$$

where \(D_{k,l} =\frac{\left( {A_{k,l} -A_{k,l-1} } \right) \left( {A_{k,l} -A_{k+1,l} } \right) \left( {A_{k+1,l} -A_{k,l-1} } \right) }{2\left( {\psi _a \left( {A_{k,l} } \right) -\psi _a \left( {A_{k,l-1} } \right) } \right) \left( {\psi _b \left( {A_{k,l} } \right) -\psi _b \left( {A_{k,l-1} } \right) } \right) }\) is a positive constant.

Noting that \({\psi }'_a \left( x \right) /{\psi }''_a \left( x \right) \) is decreasing in \(a,\forall x\ge 0.5\), we have\(p_{k,l} \left( a \right) >p_{k,l} \left( b \right) \), which implies that the upward decision weights increase in the degree of probability weighting at the nodes where the option is exercisable. \(\square \)

Appendix 4

Proof of proposition 4

In the same way, assuming \(p_e =0\), for all loss states (kl) leading to state (ij), where \(x_{k,l} \le 0\) with

\(x_{k,l} =p_{k,l} v_{\theta _k } \left( {V_{k+1,l+1}^0 } \right) +\overline{{p}}_{k,l} v_{\theta _k } \left( {V_{k+1,l}^0 } \right) ,\) the state subjective value writes:

\(Ce_{k,l} =\left( {\theta _k -\left( {-\frac{x_{k,l} }{\lambda }} \right) ^{\frac{1}{\alpha }}} \right) e^{-r\delta t},\) which is decreasing in \(\lambda \).

It follows that the state exercise probabilities \(\pi _{k,l} \) are increasing in \(\lambda \), which implies that the exercise probability at (ij) is also increasing in loss aversion. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bahaji, H. Are employee stock option exercise decisions better explained through the prospect theory?. Ann Oper Res 262, 335–359 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-016-2127-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-016-2127-2

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation