Skip to main content
Log in

The farsighted core in a political game with asymmetric information

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We consider a three-player-political game that modifies a weighted majority game by having farsighted players. We follow Acemoglu et al. (Rev Econ Stud 75:987–1009, 2008) in assuming that the power of each player is exogenously given but allow a winning coalition to choose any wealth distribution, as in Jordan (2006). Under complete information, the farsighted core is enlarged by the heterogeneity of player’s powers. In addition, we introduce asymmetric information about powers among players and define a corresponding concept of the farsighted core under asymmetric information which is a variant of the credible core in Dutta and Vohra (Math Soc Sci 50:148–165, 2005).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Riker (1963) initially applied the cooperative game to international relations and Niou et al. (1989) considered the balance of power in international systems using cooperative games.

  2. Chwe (1994) and Xue (1998) developed other forward-looking solution concepts.

  3. Succeeding studies of Acemoglu et al. (2008) in a political game are provided by Yared (2010), Acemoglu et al. (2012a; b).

  4. Jordan and Obadia (2015) and Rowat and Kerber (2014) also considered a pillage game.

  5. The farsighted core has also been studied in other games (see Jordan 2006, for pillage games and Page and Wooders 2005, for network formation games).

  6. Forges et al. (2002) and Forges and Serrano (2013) have provided an excellent survey.

  7. Jordan (2006) and Jordan and Obadia (2015) defined the power function instead of the characteristic function for the majority game. The power of a coalition depends not only on the size of coalition but also the total wealth of its members of the coalition. Jordan studied the vNM stable set and the farsighted core based on the power function. Jordan (2006) and Jordan and Obadia (2015) assumed the neutrality assumption in considering a domination between the allocations such that the players with same wealth have no relation to the domination and can keep their wealth. However, our model does not satisfy the neutrality assumption. If one player has a deviation, the remaining players together oppose the player.

References

  • Acemoglu D, Egorov G, Sonin K (2008) Coalition formation in non-democracies. Rev Econ Stud 75:987–1009

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Acemoglu D, Egrov G, Sonin K (2012a) Dynamics and stability of constitutions, coalitions, and clubs. Am Econ Rev 102:1446–1476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Acemoglu D, Golosov M, Tsyvinski A, Yared P (2012b) A dynamic theory of resource war. Q J Econ 127:283–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chwe M (1994) Farsighted coalitional stability. J Econ Theory 63:299–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B, Vohra R (2005) Incomplete information, credibility and the core. Math Soc Sci 50:148–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B, Vohra R (2016) Rational expectations and farsighted stability. Theor Econ (forthcoming)

  • Fearon JD (1995) Rationalist explanations for war. Int Organ 49(3):379–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forges F, Minelli E, Vohra R (2002) Incentives and the core of an exchange economy: a survey. J Math Econ 38:1–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forges F, Serrano R (2013) Cooperative games with incomplete information: some open problems. Int Game Theory Rev 15:134009-1–17

  • Harsanyi J (1974) An equilibrium-point interpretation of stable sets and a proposed alternative definition. Manag Sci 20:1472–1495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS (2006) Pillage and property. J Econ Theory 131:26–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS, Obadia D (2015) Stable sets in majority pillage games. Int J Game Theory 44(2):473–486

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee D, Volij O (2002) The core of economies with asymmetric information: an axiomatic approach. J Math Econ 38:43–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgenthau HJ, Thompson K, Clinton D (2005) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 7th edn. Mc-Graw-Hill Education, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Niou EMS, Ordeshook PC, Rose GF (1989) The balance of power: Stability in international systems. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Okada A (2012) Non-cooperative bargaining and the incomplete informational core. J Econ Theory 147:1165–1190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Page FH Jr, Wooders MH (2005) Strategic basins of attraction, the farsighted core, and network formation game. Games Econ Behav 66:462–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piketty T (2014) Capital in the twenty-first century (translated by Goldhammer, A.). Belknap Press: An Imprint of Harvard University Press, Massachusetts

  • Powell R (1999) In the shadow of power. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray D, Vohra R (2014) Coalition formation. In: Young P, Zamir S (eds) Handbook of game theory, vol 4. North-Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray D, Vohra R (2015) The farsighted stable set. Econometrica 83(3):977–1011

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker WH (1963) The theory of political coalitions. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed W (2003) Information, power, and war. Am Polit Sci Rev 97(4):633–641

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowat C, Kerber M (2014) Sufficient conditions for unique stable sets in three agent pillage games. Math Soc Sci 69:69–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Serrano R, Vohra R (2007) Information transmission in coalitional voting games. J Econ Theory 134:117–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1962) Simple games: an outline of the descriptive theory. Behav Sci 7:59–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vohra R (1999) Incomplete information, incentive compatibility and the core. J Econ Theory 86:123–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volij O (2000) Communication, credible improvements and the core of an economy with asymmetric Information. Int J Game Theory 29:63–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann J, Morgenstern O (1944) Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson R (1978) Information, efficiency and the core of an economy. Econometrica 46:807–816

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xue L (1998) Coalitional stability under perfect foresight. Econ Theory 11:603–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yared P (2010) A dynamic theory of war and peace. J Econ Theory 145:1921–1950

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Toshiji Miyakawa.

Additional information

The earlier version of this paper was titled “Political Stability under Asymmetric Information of Powers.” The author wish to thank the Managing Editor, Maggie Penn, the Associate Editor and three anonymous referees for comments that led to substantial improvements in this paper. I especially thank Yu Awaya; this work began from the discussions I had with him when I visited Pennsylvania State University. I am also grateful to Yuji Fujinaka, Amihai Glazer, Koji Kagotani, Tomohiko Kawamori, Nobuhiro Mizuno, and Akira Okada for the useful discussions and helpful comments. I gratefully acknowledge the financial support provided by JSPS KAKENHI (23530232).

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of Proposition 1

  • Consider the game at state (N, (www)).

Let us show that allocations \((x_1, x_2, x_3) = (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0), (\frac{1}{2}, 0, \frac{1}{2}), (0, \frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2})\) are in the farsighted core. These are allocations in which two of the three players obtain \(\frac{1}{2}\). We denote them by \((x_i, x_j, x_k ) = (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0)\). First, consider an objection by coalition \(\{i, j \}\). By (1), we have that

$$\begin{aligned}&y_i ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (w,w,w)) ) = \frac{1}{2}, \\&y_j ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (w,w,w) )) = \frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

Because

$$\begin{aligned}&x_i = \frac{1}{2} = y_i ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (w, w,w) ) ), \\&x_j = \frac{1}{2} = y_j ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (w, w,w)) ), \end{aligned}$$

coalition \(\{ i , j \}\) does not have an objection to \((x_i, x_j, x_k )\). Next, consider an objection by coalition \(\{ i, k \}\). Because

$$\begin{aligned}&y_i ( \{ i, k \} | ( N, (w,w,w)) ) = \frac{1}{2}, \\&y_k ( \{i, k \} | (N, (w,w,w) ) ) = \frac{1}{2}, \end{aligned}$$

player i does not join coalition \(\{i, k \}\) because \(y_i ( \{ i , k \} | ( N , (w,w,w) ) ) = \frac{1}{2} = x_i\), while player k has an incentive to join coalition \(\{ i, k \}\). Therefore, coalition \(\{i, k \}\) cannot form under \((x_i, x_j, x_k)\). Finally, consider an objection by coalition \(\{ j, k \}\). Applying the same argument as in \(\{ i, k \}\), there is no coalition formation at \((x_{i}, x_{j}, x_{k})\). Thus, allocation \((x_i, x_j, x_k ) = (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0)\) is in the farsighted core.

Second, let us show that any allocation except \((x_i, x_j, x_k ) = (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0)\) does not belong to the farsighted core. If \(x= (x_1, x_2, x_3 ) \ne (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0), (\frac{1}{2}, 0, \frac{1}{2}), (0, \frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2})\), then there exists \(\{ i, j \} \subset N \) such that \(x_i < \frac{1}{2} \) and \(x_j < \frac{1}{2}\). Because

$$\begin{aligned}&y_i ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (w,w,w) ) ) = \frac{1}{2}> x_i, \\&y_j ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (w,w,w) ) )= \frac{1}{2} > x_j, \end{aligned}$$

coalition \(\{ i, j \}\) has an farsighted objection to x at (N, (www) ) . This implies that \(x \in X {\setminus } \{ (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0), (\frac{1}{2}, 0, \frac{1}{2}), (0, \frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}) \}\) is not in the farsighted core.

We can apply the same argument to state (N, (sss) ) as state (N, (www) ) because \(y_i ( \{i, j \} | (N , (s, s, s )) ) = y_i ( \{i, j \} | (N, (w, w, w)) )\) and \(y_j ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (s, s, s)) ) = y_j ( \{ i, j \} | (N, (w, w,w )) )\). Therefore, only \((x_i, x_j , x_k) = (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0)\) is in the farsighted core in the political game with complete information at (N, (sss)).

  • Consider the political game at state (N, (ssw) ). Two of the three players, players 1 and 2, are the strong type.

  1. (a)

    Let us show that any allocation \(x=(x_{1},x_{2},x_{3})\) such that \(x_1 + x_2 + x_3 = 1\) and \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}\) is in the farsighted core of a political game with complete information. Since \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}\), \(x_2 + x_3 \le \frac{1}{2}\). Moreover, \( x_2 \le \frac{1}{2}\) and \(x_3 \le \frac{1}{2}\). Because

    $$\begin{aligned} y_1 ( \{1, 2 \} | ( N , (s, s, w) ) ) = \frac{1}{2} \le x_1, \end{aligned}$$

    player 1 never joins coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) which has an objection to x. Therefore, coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) does not form because players 1 and 2 must agree unanimously to form coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\). Next, consider formations of coalition \(\{ 1, 3 \}\) and \(\{ 2, 3 \}\). Because player 3 is the weak type, we have that

    $$\begin{aligned} y_3 ( \{1, 3 \} | ( N, (s, s, w )) ) = y_3 ( \{2, 3 \} | ( N , (s, s, w) ) ) =0 \le x_3. \end{aligned}$$

    Thus, coalitions \(\{ 1, 3 \}\) and \(\{2, 3 \}\) do not have an objection to x. There is no coalition formation at x. This implies that \(x \in X\) such that \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}\) is in the farsighted core.

  2. (b)

    We can prove that an allocation \(x \in X\) satisfying \(x_2 \ge \frac{1}{2}\) is in the farsighted core in a same way because players 1 and 2 are symmetric.

  3. (c)

    Finally, consider the rest of the allocations; that is, \(\hat{X} = X {\setminus } \{ x \in X | (x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}) \text { or } (x_2 \ge \frac{1}{2}) \}\). Let \(\hat{x} = ( \hat{x}_1, \hat{x}_2, \hat{x}_3 ) \in \hat{X}\). These allocations satisfy that \(\hat{x}_1 < \frac{1}{2}\) and \(\hat{x}_2 < \frac{1}{2}\). Because players 1 and 2 are strong, both players obtain the expected payoff of \(\frac{1}{2}\) through forming coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\). Then, we have that

    $$\begin{aligned}&y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | ( N , (s, s, w) ) ) = \frac{1}{2}> \hat{x}_1, \\&y_2 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | ( N, ( s, s, w) ) ) = \frac{1}{2} > \hat{x}_2. \end{aligned}$$

    Thus, coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) has an objection to \(\hat{x}\).

  • Consider the political game at state (N, (wws)). Two players are weak and one player is strong.

  1. (a)

    Let us show that any allocations \(x \in X\) such that \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}\) is in the farsighted core. Because player 3 is strong, the expected payoff for player 1 when coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) forms is

    $$\begin{aligned} y_1 ( \{ 1, 3 \} | ( N, (w, w, s) )) = 0 \le x_1. \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore, player 1 does not join coalition \(\{1, 3 \}\). If coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) forms, the expected payoff for player 1 is

    $$\begin{aligned} y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | ( N, (w, w, s) )) = \frac{1}{2}\le x_1. \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore, player 1 also does not join coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\). Finally, let us check that coalition \(\{ 2, 3 \}\) does not form. Note that \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2} \) implies \(x_2 \le \frac{1}{2}\). If coalition \(\{ 2, 3 \}\) forms, then player 2 obtains

    $$\begin{aligned} y_2 ( \{ 2, 3 \} | ( N, (w, w, s) ) = 0 \le x_2 \end{aligned}$$

    because player 3 is strong. Therefore, player 2 does not join coalition \(\{ 2, 3 \}\). There is no coalition formation at \(x \in X\) such that \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}\). Thus, these allocations are in the farsighted core.

  2. (b)

    Next, consider the set of allocations \(x \in X\) such that \(x_2 \ge \frac{1}{2}\). Because players 1 and 2 are symmetric, we can apply the same argument of (a) to the set of allocations \(x \in X\) such that \(x_2 \ge \frac{1}{2}\). Therefore, these allocations are in the farsighted core.

  3. (c)

    Finally, consider the set of allocations \(x \in X\) such that \(0 \le x_1 < \frac{1}{2}\) and \(0 \le x_2 < \frac{1}{2}\). Because

    $$\begin{aligned}&y_1 ( \{ 1, 3 \} | (N, (w, w, s) ) ) = 0 \le x_1, \\&y_2 ( \{ 2, 3 \} | ( N, (w, w, s) ) ) = 0 \le x_2, \end{aligned}$$

    players 1 and 2 never form a coalition with player 3. However, if players 1 and 2 form coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\), then

    $$\begin{aligned}&y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | (N, (w, w, s) ) )= \frac{1}{2}> x_1, \\&y_2 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | (N, (w, w, s) )) = \frac{1}{2} > x_2. \end{aligned}$$

    Coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) has an objection to x. Thus, these allocations are not in the farsighted core.

1.2 Proof of Proposition 2

(i) Let us show that three allocations \(x = ( \frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0)\), \((\frac{1}{2}, 0, \frac{1}{2})\), and \((0, \frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2})\) are in the farsighted credible core. Here, we will prove it for \((\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0)\). Note that \(x_1 = \frac{1}{2} \in \left[ \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}, 1 - \frac{p}{2} \right) \) and \(x_2 = \frac{1}{2} \in \left[ \frac{1}{2} -\frac{p}{2}, 1 - \frac{p}{2} \right) \). By Lemma 1, information that players i and j are the strong type is transmitted among the members of coalitions if they agree to join it. First, consider an objection by coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\). In this case, both players have commonly known that they are the strong type. The event E for coalition \(\{1, 2 \}\) is given by \(E = E_1 \times E_2 \times \Theta _3 = \{ s \} \times \{ s \} \times \Theta _3\). Let us check that the objection by coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) is self-selective over E. Because \(R_1 (E_1) = \{ w \}\), \(R_2 ( E_2 ) = \{ w \}\) and both player 1 and 2 believe with probability 1 that its partner is strong, the expected payoffs of player 1 and 2 are zero and satisfy

$$\begin{aligned}&Y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | N, w, \{ s\} \times \Theta _3 ) = 0< x_1 = \frac{1}{2}, \\&Y_2 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | N, w, \{ s \} \times \Theta _3 ) = 0 < x_2 = \frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

Thus, the objection is self-selective for coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) over E.

Because \( \theta _1 = s\) and \(E_{-1} = \{(s , s) , (s, w) \}\), the conditional probability of player 1’s belief about \(\theta _{-1}\) is given by \(q ( s, s | s, E_1 ) =p\) and \(q ( s, w | s, E_{-1} ) = 1-p\). Furthermore, taking an account that \( y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | (N, (s, s, s) ) = \frac{1}{2}\) and \(y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | ( N , (s, s, w) ) ) = \frac{1}{2}\), we have that

$$\begin{aligned} Y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | N, s, E_{-1} ) = \frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, player 1 does not join coalition \(\{1, 2 \}\) because \( Y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | N , s, E_{-1} ) = \frac{1}{2} = x_1\). Player 2 also does not join coalition \(\{1, 2 \}\) for the same reason.

Next, consider an objection by coalition \(\{ 1, 3 \}\). Player 3 believes that player 1 is the strong type with probability one. If player 3 is the weak type, he does not join coalition \(\{ 1, 3 \}\). Then, players 1 and 3 have a common belief that player 3 is also the strong type if he joins coalition \(\{ 1, 3 \}\). Under their beliefs, players 1 and 3 expect the payoff of \(\frac{1}{2}\) through an objection by coalition \(\{1, 3 \}\). Thus, \(Y_1 ( \{1, 3 \} | N, s, \Theta _2 \times \{s \} ) = \frac{1}{2}\). Because \(x_1 = \frac{1}{2}\), player 1 would not join the coalition. An objection by coalition \(\{1, 3 \}\) does not occur. We can apply the same argument to coalition \(\{ 2, 3 \}\) as coalition \(\{1, 3 \}\). Because there is no objection, \(( x_1 , x_2, x_3 ) = (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0)\) is in the farsighted credible core.

(ii) We show that any allocation \( x \in X\) except \( \{ (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2}, 0), (\frac{1}{2}, 0, \frac{1}{2}), (0, \frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{2} )\}\) is not in the farsighted credible core. For any x, there are two players i and j such that \(0 \le x_i < \frac{1}{2}\) and \(0 \le x_j < \frac{1}{2}\).

  1. (a)

    If \(0 \le x_i < \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}\) and \(0 \le x_j < \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}\), there is no information transmission among the members of coalition \(\{i, j \}\). Suppose that \(E = \Theta _i \times \Theta _j \times \Theta _k \). Because

    $$\begin{aligned} Y_i ( \{ i , j \} | N, s, E_{-i} )&= 1- \frac{p}{2}> x_i, \\ Y_j ( \{ i, j \} | N, s, E_{-j} )&= 1- \frac{p}{2} > x_j, \end{aligned}$$

    coalition \(\{ i, j \}\) has an objection to x.

  2. (b)

    If \( \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \le x_i < \frac{1}{2}\) and \(\frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \le x_j < \frac{1}{2}\), information that players i and j are the strong type is commonly known by the members of coalition \(\{ i, j \}\). Define \(E = \{ s \} \times \{ s \} \times \Theta _k\). Because \(R_i (E_i) = \{ w \}\), \(R_j ( E_j ) = \{ w \}\), and

    $$\begin{aligned} Y_i ( \{ i , j \} | N, w, E_{-i} )&= 0< x_i, \\ Y_j ( \{ i, j \} | N, w, E_{-j} )&= 0 < x_j, \end{aligned}$$

    an objection to x is self-selective for coalition \(\{ i, j \}\) over E. Moreover, we have that

    $$\begin{aligned} Y_i ( \{ i, j \} | N, s , E_{-i} )&= \frac{1}{2}> x_i, \\ Y_j ( \{ i, j \} | N, s, E_{-j} )&= \frac{1}{2} > x_j. \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore, coalition \(\{ i, j \}\) has a farsighted objection to x over E. Thus, coalition \(\{i, j \}\) has a farsighted credible objection to x.

  3. (c)

    If \( \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \le x_i < \frac{1}{2}\) and \(0 \le x_j < \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}\), information that player i is the strong type is transmitted. Therefore, \(E = E_i \times E_j \times \Theta _k = \{s \} \times \Theta _j \times \Theta _k\). Because

    $$\begin{aligned} Y_i ( \{ i, j \} | N , w, \Theta _j \times \Theta _k )&= \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \le x_i, \end{aligned}$$

    an objection to x is self-selective for coalition \(\{ i, j \}\) over \(E = \{s \} \times \Theta _j \times \Theta _k\). Furthermore, because

    $$\begin{aligned} Y_i ( \{ i, j \} | N , s, \Theta _j \times \Theta _k )&=1 - \frac{p}{2}> x_i, \\ Y_j ( \{ i, j \} | N, s , \{ s \} \times \Theta _k )&= \frac{1}{2} > x_j, \end{aligned}$$

    coalition \(\{ i, j \}\) has a farsighted objection to x over E. Thus, coalition \(\{ i, j \}\) has a farsighted credible objection to x.

1.3 Proof of Proposition 3

(i) We first show that the set of allocations represented by \(F_1\) is in the farsighted credible core. Because \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}\) and \(x_2 \ge \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}\) in \(F_1\), it is commonly known that players 1 and 2 are the strong type if they join a coalition. Therefore, player 3 of the weak type does not join coalitions \(\{1, 3\}\) and \(\{ 2, 3 \}\) because his expected payoff by forming a coalition is zero, which is less than \(x_3\). When coalition \(\{1 , 2 \}\) forms, players 1 and 2 have the expected payoff of \(\frac{1}{2}\) because they believe that their partner is the strong type with probability one. Because player 1 has his wealth of \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}\), he does not agree to form coalition \(\{1, 2 \}\). Therefore, there is no objection to \(x \in F_1\). Thus, \(F_1\) is a part of the farsighted credible core at (N, (ssw)).

Next let us show that any allocation in \(F_2\) is in the farsighted credible core. By Lemma 1, player 3 of the weak type does not join any coalition because he has already obtained \(x_3 \ge \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}\). Only an objection by coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) is possible. However, player 1 does not agree to join the coalition because \(x_1 \ge \frac{1}{2}\). We conclude that any allocation in \(F_2\) is in the farsighted credible core.

Furthermore, we can apply the same argument to allocations in \(F_3\) and \(F_4\) as in \(F_1\) and \(F_2\) if interchanging player 1 for player 2. As a result, \(F_1\), \(F_2\), \(F_3\) and \(F_4\) belong to the farsighted credible core at (N, (ssw) ).

(ii) Next, we prove that

$$\begin{aligned} D_1&= \left\{ x \in X {\big |} ~0 \le x_1< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \text { and } 0 \le x_2< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \right\} , \\ D_2&= \left\{ x \in X {\big |} ~0 \le x_1< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \text { and } 0 \le x_3< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \right\} , \\ D_3&= \left\{ x \in X {\big |} ~0 \le x_2< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \text { and } 0 \le x_3 < \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \right\} \end{aligned}$$

are not in the farsighted credible core.

Consider any allocation x in \(D_1\) and an objection by coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\). By Lemma 1, no information about their types is transmitted between players 1 and 2. Therefore, \(E = \Theta _1 \times \Theta _2 \times \Theta _3\). Because

$$\begin{aligned} Y_1 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | N, s, \Theta _2 \times \Theta _3 )&= p \times \frac{1}{2} + (1-p) \times 1 = 1- \frac{p}{2}> x_1, \\ Y_2 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | N, s, \Theta _1 \times \Theta _3 )&= 1 - \frac{p}{2} > x_2, \end{aligned}$$

coalition \(\{ 1, 2 \}\) can form.

Consider any allocation x in \(D_2\) and an objection by coalition \(\{ 1, 3 \}\). By Lemma 1, no information about their types is transmitted between players 1 and 3. Therefore, \(E = \Theta _1 \times \Theta _2 \times \Theta _3\). Because

$$\begin{aligned} Y_1 ( \{ 1, 3 \} | N, s, \Theta _2 \times \Theta _3 )&= p \times \frac{1}{2} + (1-p) \times 1 = 1- \frac{p}{2}> x_1, \\ Y_3 ( \{ 1, 2 \} | N, w, \Theta _1 \times \Theta _2 )&= p \times 0 + (1- p ) \times \frac{1}{2}= \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} > x_2, \end{aligned}$$

coalition \(\{ 1, 3 \}\) can form.

For any allocation in \(D_3\), applying the same argument as in \(D_2\) by interchanging player 1 to player 2, we can see that coalition \(\{ 2, 3 \}\) forms.

Because any allocation in \(D_1\), \(D_2\) and \(D_3\) has an objection, \(D_1 \cup D_2 \cup D_3\) is not the farsighted credible core.

(iii) Repeating a part of (ii) in the proof of Proposition 2 and considering an objection by coalition \(\{ 1, 2\}\), we can prove that \(\{ x \in X | x_1< \frac{1}{2} \text { and } x_2 < \frac{1}{2} \}\) is not comprised of the farsighted credible core because players 1 and 2 are the strong type.

1.4 Proof of Proposition 4

We can prove that the sets of \(D_1 = \{ x \in X | 0 \le x_1< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \text { and } 0 \le x_2 < \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \}\), \(D_2 = \{ x \in X | 0 \le x_1< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \text { and } 0 \le x_3 < \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \}\) and \(D_3 = \{ x \in X | 0 \le x_2< \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \text { and } 0 \le x_3 < \frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2} \}\) are not in the farsighted credible core by applying the almost same argument as (ii) in the proof of Proposition 3.

For any allocation except \(D_1\), \(D_2\) and \(D_3\), there are at least two players i and j whose wealth allocations \(x_i\) and \(x_j\) are greater than or equal to \(\frac{1}{2} - \frac{p}{2}\). A player of the weak type does not join any coalition if his wealth is greater than or equal to \(\frac{1}{2} -\frac{p}{2}\). Therefore, any coalition cannot form. Thus, these allocations are in the farsighted credible core.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Miyakawa, T. The farsighted core in a political game with asymmetric information. Soc Choice Welf 49, 205–229 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1057-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1057-5

Keywords

Navigation